Impiety Avenged: Rewriting Athenian History 125

Total Page:16

File Type:pdf, Size:1020Kb

Impiety Avenged: Rewriting Athenian History 125 Splendide Mendax Rethinking Fakes and Forgeries in Classical, Late Antique, and Early Christian Literature edited by Edmund P. Cueva and Javier Martínez BARKHUIS GRONINGEN 2016 Book design: Barkhuis Cover Design: Nynke Tiekstra, Noordwolde Image on cover: Unknown, Statuette of a Sleeping Cupid, 50 - 100, Marble 13.5 × 41.9 × 26 cm (5 5/16 × 16 1/2 × 10 1/4 in.), The J. Paul Getty Museum, Los Angeles, Digital image courtesy of the Getty's Open Content Program. ISBN 9789491431982 Copyright © 2016 the authors and editors All rights reserved. No part of this publication or the information contained herein may be reproduced, stored in a retrieval system, or transmitted in any form or by any means, elec- tronical, mechanical, by photocopying, recording or otherwise, without prior written per- mission from the authors. Although all care is taken to ensure the integrity and quality of this publication and the information herein, no responsibility is assumed by the publishers nor the authors for any damage to property or persons as a result of operation or use of this publication and/or the information contained herein. Contents Acknowledgments IX I. Introduction 1 JAVIER MARTÍNEZ Cheap Fictions and Gospel Truths 3 II. Classical Works 21 BRIAN R. DOAK Remembering the Future, Predicting the Past: Vaticinia ex eventu in the Historiographic Traditions of the Hebrew Bible and the Ancient Near East 23 GAIUS C. STERN Imposters in Ancient Persia, Greece, and Rome 55 III. Greek Literature 73 REYES BERTOLÍN The Search for Truth in Odyssey 3 and 4 75 VALENTINA PROSPERI The Trojan War: Between History and Myth 93 EMILIA RUIZ YAMUZA Protagoras’s Myth: Between Pastiche and Falsification 113 JAKUB FILONIK Impiety Avenged: Rewriting Athenian History 125 VI CONTENTS MIKEL LABIANO Dramas or Niobus: Aristophanic Comedy or Spurious Play? 141 EDMUND P. CUEVA ὃ γὰρ βούλεται τοῦθ̓ ἕκαστος καὶ οἴεται: Dissembling in the Ancient Greek Novel 157 IV. Latin Literature 175 ANDREW SILLETT Quintus Cicero's Commentariolum: A Philosophical Approach to Roman Elections 177 KLAUS LENNARTZ Not Without My Mother: The Obligate Rhetoric of Daphne’s Transformation 193 MICHAEL MECKLER Comparative Approaches to the Historia Augusta 205 V. Late Antique Works 217 ANNE-CATHERINE BAUDOIN Truth in the Details: The Report of Pilate to Tiberius as an Authentic Forgery 219 KRISTI EASTIN Virgilius Accuratissimus: The “Authentic” Illustrations of William Sandby’s 1750 Virgil 239 LUIGI PEDRONI The Salii at the Nonae of October: Reading Lyd. Mens. 4.138 W 273 CRISTIAN TOLSA Evidence and Speculation about Ptolemy’s Career in Olympiodorus 287 CONTENTS VII VI. Early Christian Works 301 SCOTT BROWN Mar Saba 65: Twelve Enduring Misconceptions 303 ARGYRI KARANASIOU A Euripidised Clement of Alexandria or a Christianised Euripides? The Interplay of Authority between Quoting Author and Cited Author 331 MARKUS MÜLKE Heretic Falsification in Cyprian’s Epistulae? 347 Contributors 355 Indices 361 Index locorum 361 General Index 363 Impiety Avenged: Rewriting Athenian History JAKUB FILONIK University of Warsaw In sources from various periods of antiquity we can find numerous remarks concerning the trials for ἀσέβεια (“impiety”) that reportedly took place in fifth- and fourth-century Athens. Despite several notorious trials well attested in the contemporary sources, these remarks can often be dated many centuries later than the actual events that they describe, sometimes even as late as the biograph- ical writings of Diogenes Laertius (ca. 3rd century CE) or Plutarch (1st/2nd century CE), neither of whom was particularly careful in his approach to the sources. This essay argues that some of these cases follow a pattern of construct- ing ancient fake testimonies of the past and, as such, they display numerous shared features relating to their fictive nature. The first to raise serious doubts about the value of these testimonies in ex- tenso was Dover (1976) in his paper on the freedom of intellectuals in ancient Greece, followed by important general remarks on Hellenistic biography by Lefkowitz (1981, 110–111 et al. and 1987) and Stone (1988), and a more de- tailed study of selected fifth-century cases by Wallace (1994). Here, I would like to go one step further in calling the surviving testimonies into question. In order to give a more detailed picture of the methods of ancient biographers and schol- ars, I will focus in this essay on four cases of the use of fake source material in the descriptions of the trials allegedly held in classical Athens. First, I argue that some of these trials almost certainly did not take place, while traditions that refer to those possibly authentic most likely included numerous fictitious additions. Second, I intend to highlight the shared features of the cases described below. Third, I discuss possible reasons for the emergence and re-use of those inauthen- tic testimonies. Finally, I tentatively suggest some new arguments concerning 126 JAKUB FILONIK legal issues connected with the early impiety trials.1 The four cases in question are those of Aspasia, Protagoras, Euripides, and Phryne. First, let us have a look at a particularly revealing passage from Diogenes Laertius, which proves to be very informative on the methods of ancient biog- raphers describing events dating back to the classical period: Of the trial of Anaxagoras different accounts are given. Sotion in his Suc- cession of the Philosophers says that he was indicted by Cleon on a charge of impiety, because he declared the sun to be a mass of red-hot metal; that his pupil Pericles defended him, and he was fined five talents and banished. Satyrus in his Lives says that the prosecutor was Thucydides,2 the opponent of Pericles, and the charge one of treasonable correspondence with Persia as well as of impiety; and that sentence of death was passed on Anaxagoras by default. When news was brought him that he was condemned and his sons were dead, his comment on the sentence was, “Long ago nature condemned both my judges and myself to death”; and on his sons, “I knew that my chil- dren were born to die.” Some, however, tell this story of Solon, and others of Xenophon. That he buried his sons with his own hands is asserted by Demetrius of Phalerum in his work On Old Age. Hermippus3 in his Lives says that he was confined in the prison pending his execution; that Pericles came forward and asked the people whether they had any fault to find with him in his own public career; to which they replied that they had not. “Well,” he continued, “I am a pupil of Anaxagoras; do not then be carried away by slanders and put him to death. Let me prevail upon you to release him.” So he was released; but he could not brook the indignity he had suf- fered and committed suicide. Hieronymus in the second book of his Scat- tered Notes states that Pericles brought him into court so weak and wasted from illness that he owed his acquittal not so much to the merits of his case as to the sympathy of the judges. So much then on the subject of his trial. ————— 1 The content of this essay has been supplemented by Filonik (2013) which focuses on legal and socio-political aspects of the impiety accusations in classical Athens, and in- cludes a detailed discussion of the less clear-cut cases, such as those of Anaxagoras, Di- agoras, and some fourth-century trials. The project from which the present paper emerges has been funded by the National Science Centre, Poland based on the decision number DEC2012/07/N/HS2/00967. The research has been also supported by the Foundation for Polish Science (FNP). 2 For controversies on Thucydides, son of Melesias, anti-Periclean opposition in Athens, and Plutarch’s account of these “events,” see Andrewes 1978; Raaflaub 2000, 98–100. 3 FGrHist IV A 3, 1026 T 6 b = F 65. For Hermippus’ of Smyrna methods in his biograph- ical writing, see e.g. Bollansée 1999a: 118ff., 182–84. IMPIETY AVENGED 127 […] At length he retired to Lampsacus and there died. (D. L. 2.12–14; trans. R. D. Hicks). Here, we are given several variants of—apparently—the same events, which demonstrate the author’s complete lack of ability to assess the sources available to him. As if presenting these four variants as equally plausible were not confus- ing enough, the biographer simply adds that Anaxagoras died at Lampsacus. To support this statement, Diogenes Laertius (2.15) further “quotes” the inscription from the philosopher’s grave, followed by a more elaborate epigram written by our biographer, which, again, focuses on the trial resulting in the philosopher’s death(!) For the story to be rendered more appealing, he includes (1) gnomic quotations—ascribed to various authors—which offer a brilliant summary of the famous person’s death, (2) witty dialogues with renowned figures (in this in- stance, Pericles) who are introduced only to offer aid to the central character, and (3) the authority of earlier authors merged into one ostensibly coherent nar- rative. In his Life of Pericles (32), Plutarch mentions the charge of ἀσέβεια against Aspasia, the concubine of Pericles. According to the biographer, the case was brought by Hermippus the comic writer (not his Hellenistic namesake just men- tioned), who claimed that Aspasia was helping free women to rendezvous with Pericles. The latter was also said to have helped in her acquittal by shedding a flood of tears over her fate before the dicasts (a story Plutarch attributes to Aes- chines of Sphettus). The biographer most likely transferred the stage humor of the comic writer Hermippus to an imaginary lawsuit.4 It would otherwise be an isolated example from classical Athens of a comic poet repeating his insults from the stage in court.
Recommended publications
  • Aristotle's Contribution to Scholarly Communication
    University of Tennessee, Knoxville TRACE: Tennessee Research and Creative Exchange Doctoral Dissertations Graduate School 12-2008 Aristotle’s Contribution to Scholarly Communication Stephen Edward Bales University of Tennessee - Knoxville Follow this and additional works at: https://trace.tennessee.edu/utk_graddiss Part of the Communication Commons Recommended Citation Bales, Stephen Edward, "Aristotle’s Contribution to Scholarly Communication. " PhD diss., University of Tennessee, 2008. https://trace.tennessee.edu/utk_graddiss/475 This Dissertation is brought to you for free and open access by the Graduate School at TRACE: Tennessee Research and Creative Exchange. It has been accepted for inclusion in Doctoral Dissertations by an authorized administrator of TRACE: Tennessee Research and Creative Exchange. For more information, please contact [email protected]. To the Graduate Council: I am submitting herewith a dissertation written by Stephen Edward Bales entitled "Aristotle’s Contribution to Scholarly Communication." I have examined the final electronic copy of this dissertation for form and content and recommend that it be accepted in partial fulfillment of the requirements for the degree of Doctor of Philosophy, with a major in Communication and Information. J. Michael Pemberton, Major Professor We have read this dissertation and recommend its acceptance: Suzie Allard, Barbara J. Thayer-Bacon, Dwight Teeter Accepted for the Council: Carolyn R. Hodges Vice Provost and Dean of the Graduate School (Original signatures are on file with official studentecor r ds.) To the Graduate Council: I am submitting herewith a dissertation written by Stephen Edward Bales entitled “Aristotle’s Contribution to Scholarly Communication.” I have examined the final electronic copy of this dissertation for form and content and recommend that it be accepted in partial fulfillment of the requirements for the degree of Doctor of Philosophy, with a major in Communication & Information.
    [Show full text]
  • A Reading of Porphyry's on Abstinence From
    UNIVERSITY OF CALIFORNIA Los Angeles Justice Purity Piety: A Reading of Porphyry’s On Abstinence from Ensouled Beings A dissertation submitted in partial satisfaction of the requirements for the degree Doctor of Philosophy in Classics by Alexander Press 2020 © Copyright by Alexander Press 2020 ABSTRACT OF THE DISSERTATION Justice Purity Piety: A Reading of Porphyry’s On Abstinence from Ensouled Beings by Alexander Press Doctor of Philosophy in Classics University of California, Los Angeles, 2020 Professor David Blank, Chair Abstract: Presenting a range of arguments against meat-eating, many strikingly familiar, Porphyry’s On Abstinence from Ensouled Beings (Greek Περὶ ἀποχῆς ἐµψύχων, Latin De abstinentia ab esu animalium) offers a sweeping view of the ancient debate concerning animals and their treatment. At the same time, because of its advocacy of an asceticism informed by its author’s Neoplatonism, Abstinence is often taken to be concerned primarily with the health of the human soul. By approaching Abstinence as a work of moral suasion and a work of literature, whose intra- and intertextual resonances yield something more than a collection of propositions or an invitation to Quellenforschung, I aim to push beyond interpretations that bracket the arguments regarding animals as merely dialectical; cast the text’s other-directed principle of justice as wholly ii subordinated to a self-directed principle of purity; or accept as decisive Porphyry’s exclusion of craftsmen, athletes, soldiers, sailors, and orators from his call to vegetarianism.
    [Show full text]
  • Chapter Five
    chapter five SUMMARY Theophrastus, Aristotle’s pupil and second head of the Peripatetic School, wasapopularteacher.Heissaidtohavehadroughly,students (.). He was also a prolific writer. The catalogue of Theophrastus’ writ- ings preserved by Diogenes Laertius in his Life of Theophrastus lists c. titles (.–). His surviving works include two multi-book treatises on botany, eight scientific opuscula, a short work on first principles (the so-called Metaphysics), a doxographical work on sense-perception and the Characters. Aside from the last, none of Theophrastus’ writings on ethical topics has survived intact, so that we must turn to secondary sources in order to gain knowledge of Theophrastus’ teachings on ethics. These sources (those that are printed in the text-translation volumes as against those that are listed in the apparatus of parallel texts) number . Some belong to the Roman Republic, while others belong to the Empire and the Middle Ages. Some source authors wrote in Greek, but there are also Latin and Arabic sources; even one in Italian. Moreover and most important, the sources vary greatly in their reliability. Late collections of excerpts and sayings must always be approached with caution, but even earlier, respected authors like Cicero and Plutarch may write in ways that are misleading. Each source author needs to be evaluated not only in regard to general reliability but also in regard to particular assertions in particular contexts. Most likely Diogenes’ catalogue of Theophrastean writings derives from the work On Theophrastus byHermippusofSmyrna(ndhalfofthe rd cent. bc). The catalogue divides into five lists plus two addenda. The lists probably represent different purchases by the library in Alexandria.
    [Show full text]
  • Studies on the Ancient Catalogues of Aristotle's Works
    Studies on the Ancient Catalogues of Aristotle's Works https://www.ontology.co/biblio/corpus-aristotelicum-biblio-two.htm Theory and History of Ontology by Raul Corazzon | e-mail: [email protected] Bibliography on the Ancient Catalogues of Aristotle's Writings and the Rediscovery of the Corpus Aristotelicum ANNOTATED BIBLIOGRAPHY OF THE STUDIES IN ENGLISH 1 di 22 28/03/2017 11:57 Studies on the Ancient Catalogues of Aristotle's Works https://www.ontology.co/biblio/corpus-aristotelicum-biblio-two.htm ENGLISH See also: The Lives and Opinions of Eminent Philosophers by Diogenes Laërtius. A Bibliography 1. Barnes, Jonathan. 1997. "Roman Aristotle." In Philosophia Togata Ii. Plato and Aristotle at Rome, edited by Barnes, Jonathan and Griffin, Miriam, 1-69. Oxford: Clarendon Press. Reprinted in: Gregory Nagy (ed.), Greek Literature in the Roman Period and in Late Antiquity, New York, Routledge, 2001 pp. 119-187; revised edition in J. Barnes, Mantissa: Essays in Ancient Philosophy IV, Oxford: Clarendon Press, 2015, pp. 407-478. "When Theophrastus died, his library, which included the library of Aristotle, was carried off to the Troad. His successors found nothing much to read; the Lyceum sank into a decline; and Peripatetic ideas had little influence on the course of Hellenistic philosophy. It was only with the rediscovery of the library that Aristotelianism revived — and it revived in Italy. For the library went from the Troad to Athens — and thence, as part of Sulla’s war-booty, to Rome. There Andronicus of Rhodes produced the ‘Roman edition’ of the corpus Aristotelicum. It was the first complete and systematic version of Aristotle’s works, the first publication in their full form of the technical treatises, the first genuinely critical edition of the text.
    [Show full text]
  • Aristotle & the Corpus Aristotelicum
    Aristotle & The corpus aristotelicum Socrates 469-399 B.C.; Plato 427-347 Aristotle: 384-322 B.C. Earliest known biography of Aristotle was written by Hermippus of Smyrna, an Alexandrian grammarian and librarian, in the early 200’s B.C., i.e., the end of the 3rd century B.C. This biography is not extant, but was partially preserved in the biography by Diogenes Laertius, writing in the 2nd century A.D. 384 Born in Stagira, Chalcidice; his father, Nicomachus, was a physician at the Macedonian royal household. 367 At the age of 17, he arrives in Athens to study at Plato’s Academy, Plato then being 60 years old. 347 Plato’s death; Aristotle leaves Athens. 343 Invited to the court of King Philip of Macedon to tutor his son, Alexander the Great. 340 Alexander becomes regent to his father, who was engaged in military operations in Byzantium; end of Aristotle’s tutorship. Alexander is thought later to have helped Aristotle’s researches in natural history by sending him specimens from the different parts of his empire. 335 Returns to Athens; establishes the Lyceum. 323 Death of Alexander; anti-Macedonian feelings in Athens cause him to return to Chalcis. Leadership of the Lyceum was taken over by his student Theophrastus. 322 Dies in Chalcis. 225 End of Lyceum (by contrast, Plato’s Academy lasted, with some interruptions, until 529 A.D., when it was closed by the Emperor Justinian.) Corpus aristotelicum It contains heterogeneous material, such as a lexicon, discussion notes and lecture notes, both polished and unpolished. Still, there is a systematic coherence and uniform style to them.
    [Show full text]
  • S.Y. Luria Democritus Texts Translation Investigations
    S.Y. LURIA DEMOCRITUS TEXTS TRANSLATION INVESTIGATIONS English translation by C.C.W. TAYLOR NAUKA PUBLISHERS Leningrad 1970 Copyright Note I have tried unsuccessfully to identify the present holder or holders of the copyright in Luria’s book, in order to seek permission for the publication of this translation. Enquiries made of the publisher in Moscow and St Petersburg and of the Society of Russian Authors in St Petersburg have failed to elicit the information sought. CCWT CONTENTS Translator’s preface Editors’ preface Abbreviations Texts Variant readings Concordance Luria – DK Index locorum Translation of texts Commentary Works of S.Y Luria relating to Democritus TRANSLATOR’S PREFACE In this volume I present a translation into English of S.Y. Luria’s edition of the fragments of Democritus and of the testimonia relating to him. The work has the sole aim of making Luria’s work available to students in the English-speaking world and in other countries worldwide who are familiar with English but not with Russian. A valuable Italian translation of Luria’s work (Democrito, Raccolta dei frammenti, interpretazione e commentario di Salomon Luria, ed. G. Girgenti et al., Edizione Bompioni, Milan) appeared in 2007, but my impression of the current level of comprehension of Italian, even among students of ancient philosophy, convinces me that, regrettably, only an English translation can expect to reach a truly worldwide audience. Our author’s full name, spelled in the Cyrillic alphabet, is Соломон Яковлевич Лурье, to which the closest approximation in the Roman alphabet is ‘Solomon Yakovlevich Lurye’. However, in publications in languages using the Roman alphabet.
    [Show full text]
  • Brill's Companion to the Reception Of
    ANDREA FALCON (ED.), BRILL’S COMPANION TO THE RECEPTION OF ARISTOTLE IN ANTIQUITY, BRILL: LEIDEN – BOSTON 2016. XV + 512 PP. ISBN 9789004266476 (HBK) ISBN 9789004315402 (E-BOOK) LUCAS ORO HERSHTEIN UNIVERSITY OF BUENOS AIRES – CONICET In what I have always considered one of the most beautiful descriptions of the philosophical path, a renowned medieval thinker once said, through the words of a teacher talking to his pupil: ‘stude ergo in hoc et ama, quia haec est intentio propter quam est humana anima, et ibi est delectatio magna et felicitas maxima’.1 If ancient philosophy is –as it was said by Pierre Hadot– ‘an invitation to each human being to transform himself’, an honest intellectual approach should reflect this intimate, inner dimension of it. A book on ancient philosophy needs to be, therefore, a ‘spiritual exercise’.2 This can be done in many ways and here, is done by finding a way to write a ‘story’ –or many of them– about the ‘history’ that is going to be told. Ancient philosophy was not only about ‘studying’ but also about ‘loving’, and since knowledge was understood not just as an intellectual matter but also as an existential one, a comprehensive reading of it needs to unveil, as much as possible, all the non-discursive meanings that surrounded that world. This is precisely what the reader feels when going through this book: moving from one page to another, as if they were the successive doors of a palace, it is possible to ‘see’ the philosophers gathering together arguing on the most important issues, to ‘listen’ to them whispering the secrets of life and death.
    [Show full text]
  • Matthew W. Dickie, Magic and Magicians in the Greco-Roman World
    MAGIC AND MAGICIANS IN THE GRECO- ROMAN WORLD This absorbing work assembles an extraordinary range of evidence for the existence of sorcerers and sorceresses in the ancient world, and addresses the question of their identities and social origins. From Greece in the fifth century BC, through Rome and Italy, to the Christian Roman Empire as far as the late seventh century AD, Professor Dickie shows the development of the concept of magic and the social and legal constraints placed on those seen as magicians. The book provides a fascinating insight into the inaccessible margins of Greco- Roman life, exploring a world of wandering holy men and women, conjurors and wonder-workers, prostitutes, procuresses, charioteers and theatrical performers. Compelling for its clarity and detail, this study is an indispensable resource for the study of ancient magic and society. Matthew W.Dickie teaches at the University of Illinois at Chicago. He has written on envy and the Evil Eye, on the learned magician, on ancient erotic magic, and on the interpretation of ancient magical texts. MAGIC AND MAGICIANS IN THE GRECO-ROMAN WORLD Matthew W.Dickie LONDON AND NEW YORK First published in hardback 2001 by Routledge First published in paperback 2003 by Routledge 11 New Fetter Lane, London EC4P 4EE Simultaneously published in the USA and canada by Routledge 29 West 35th Street, New York, NY 10001 Routledge is an imprint of the Taylor & Francis Group This edition published in the Taylor & Francis e-Library, 2005. “To purchase your own copy of this or any of Taylor & Francis or Routledge’s collection of thousands of eBooks please go to www.eBookstore.tandf.co.uk.” © 2001, 2003 Matthew W.Dickie All rights reserved.
    [Show full text]
  • Philology. Linguistics P
    P PHILOLOGY. LINGUISTICS P Philology. Linguistics Periodicals. Serials Cf. P215+ Phonology and phonetics Cf. P501+ Indo-European philology 1.A1 International or polyglot 1.A3-Z American and English 2 French 3 German 7 Scandinavian 9 Other (10) Yearbooks see P1+ Societies Cf. P215+ Phonology and phonetics Cf. P503 Indo-European philology 11 American and English 12 French 13 German 15 Italian 17 Scandinavian 18 Spanish and Portuguese 19 Other Congresses Cf. P505 Indo-European philology 21 Permanent. By name 23 Other Museums. Exhibitions 24 General works 24.2.A-Z Individual. By place, A-Z Collected works (nonserial) Cf. P511+ Indo-European philology 25 Monographic series. Sets of monographic works 26.A-Z Studies in honor of a particular person or institution. Festschriften. By honoree, A-Z 27 Collected works, papers, etc., of individual authors 29 Encyclopedias. Dictionaries 29.5 Terminology. Notation Cf. P152 Grammatical nomenclature Theory. Method General works see P121+ 33 General special Relation to anthropology, ethnology and culture Including Sapir-Whorf hypothesis Cf. GN1+ Anthropology 35 General works 35.5.A-Z By region or country, A-Z Relation to psychology. Psycholinguistics Cf. BF455+ Psycholinguistics (Psychology) 37 General works Study and teaching. Research 37.3 General works 37.4.A-Z By region or country, A-Z 37.45.A-Z By region or country, A-Z 37.5.A-Z Special aspects, A-Z 37.5.C37 Cartesian linguistics 37.5.C39 Categorization Cf. P128.C37 Categorization (Linguistic analysis) 1 P PHILOLOGY. LINGUISTICS P Theory. Method Relation to psychology. Psycholinguistics Special aspects, A-Z -- Continued 37.5.C64 Communicative competence Cf.
    [Show full text]
  • Empedocles Democraticus: Hellenistic Biography at the Intersection of Philosophy and Politics*
    phillip sidney horky durham university EMPEDOCLES DEMOCRATICUS: HELLENISTIC BIOGRAPHY AT THE INTERSECTION OF PHILOSOPHY AND POLITICS* Introduction A tantalizing fragment of Aristotle, probably from his lost On Poets,1 appears at first glance to characterize Empedocles of Agrigentum as an advocate for democracy: Aristotle too says that he [sc. Empedocles] was a free man, and estranged from every sort of rule, if indeed it is true that he declined the kingship when it was offered to him, as Xanthus claims in his account of him [sc. Empedocles] – obviously because he was more content with a life of simplicity. Timaeus also said these things, at the same time adding the reason for his [sc. Empedocles’] being a man of the people.2 * This paper has benefited tremendously from suggestions and criticisms by -Lu cas Herchenroeder, Chris Pelling, and Stefan Schorn. I thank them kindly for their thoughts, while noting that I probably have not dispelled all of their hesitations. All arguments expressed here, then, remain my own. 1 So Janko 2010, who notes that it is ‘hard to be sure’ whether the fragment comes from the lost On Poets or Sophist. Rose, followed by Gigon (F 865), speculated that it came from Aristotle’s lost Sophist, probably because Diogenes knows the Sophist to be the text of Aristotle that speaks about Empedocles (F 65 Rose = Diog. Laert. 8.57 and 9.25). For reasons that will become clear, i.e. that I believe that Aristotle was evaluating Empedocles’ character by way of exegesis of his poems, I opt for On Poets.
    [Show full text]
  • Ancient Catalogues of Aristotle's Works: Diogenes Laã
    Ancient Catalogues of Aristotle's Works: Diogenes Laërtius https://www.ontology.co/aristotle-catalogues.htm Theory and History of Ontology by Raul Corazzon | e-mail: [email protected] Ancient Catalogues of Aristotle's Works: First Part Diogenes Laërtius Lives V, 22-27 Second Part: Hesychius and Ptolemy al-Garib THE VITAE ARISTOTELIS AND THE ANCIENT CATALOGUES OF ARISTOTLE'S WRITINGS "The following pages are an attempt to give a brief account or compressed overview of what may be called the 'traditional' Vitae Aristotelis, namely, the lost Vita authored by the Peripatetic Hermippus of Smyrna, and the lost Vita composed by the Neo-Platonist Ptolemy, whom the Arabic biographers call Ptolemy-el-Garib. These two Vitae, which have been compiled in antiquity, survive in one form or another only through their respective 'derivatives' or epitomes of which we still possess a fair number. The more important biographies of Aristotle, (6) which have been handed down to us from antiquity, are: Diogenes Laërtius, The Lives And Opinions of Eminent Philosophers V. 1-35; (7) the Vita Aristotelis Hesychii; (8) the Pseudo-Hesychius; (9) the Vita Aristotelis Marciana; (10) the Vita Aristotelis Vulgata; (11) the Vita Lascaris; (12) the Vita Aristotelis Latina; (13) the Vita Aristotelis Syriaca I (anonymous); (14) the Vita Aristotelis Syriaca II (anonymous); (15) the Vita Aristotelis Arabica I (by An-Nadim); (16) the Vita Aristotelis Arabica II (by Al-Mubashir or Mubassir); (17) the Vita Aristotelis Arabica III (by Al-Qifti); (18) and the Vita Aristotelis Arabica IV (by Usaibi'a). (19) All these Vitae in some ways are related to, or are more or less accurate abridgments of, either the Vita Aristotelis of Hermippus or the Vita Aristotelis of Ptolemy-el-Garib.
    [Show full text]
  • Zalmoxis, Abaris, Aristeas
    The Classical Quarterly 1–17 © The Classical Association (2016) 1 doi:10.1017/S0009838816000641 PYTHAGORAS’ NORTHERN CONNECTIONS: ZALMOXIS, ABARIS, ARISTEAS Apart from his teachings, wonders and scientific discoveries, Pythagoras was also known for his wide-ranging journeys. Ancient authors alleged that he visited many countries and nations from Egypt to India, stayed with the Phoenicians and the Ethiopians and talked to the Persian Magi and Gallic Druids. However, he never went to the North. If, nevertheless, he was eventually associated with the northern inhabitants, it is only because they themselves came into close contact with him. The first of them was Zalmoxis, a deity of a Thracian tribe, the Getae, who guaranteed them immortality after death (Hdt. 4.94).1 Having described a blood ritual that the Getae practised to become immortal, Herodotus relates a story he heard from the Hellespontine and Pontic Greeks. It goes that Zalmoxis was not a daimōn but a former slave of Pythagoras on Samos and, having adopted the doctrine of immortality from him, he returned to Thrace and converted his tribesmen to it with a cunning trick. He invited the most prominent of them to a men’s hall (ἀνδρείων) for entertainment and told them that neither he nor they or their descendants would die, but would live eternally. Then, having constructed a secret underground chamber, he suddenly disappeared from the eyes of the Getae and hid in his shelter for three full years, being lamented as dead. Then he showed himself again to the Getae, thus persuading them of the truth of his promises (4.95).
    [Show full text]