Toward a Monistic Theory of Science the “Strong Programme” Reconsidered

Total Page:16

File Type:pdf, Size:1020Kb

Toward a Monistic Theory of Science the “Strong Programme” Reconsidered 10.1177/0048393103252780PHILOSOPHYKempARTICLE / STRONG OF PROGRAMMETHE SOCIAL SCIENCES RECONSIDERED / September 2003 Toward a Monistic Theory of Science The “Strong Programme” Reconsidered STEPHEN KEMP University of Sussex This article considers the “Strong Programme” account of scientific knowledge from a fresh perspective. It argues that insufficient attention has been paid to the Strong Programme’s monistic intent, that is, its aim to unify considerations of instrumental adequacy and social interests in explanations of the development of scientific knowledge. Although sharing the judgment of many critics that the Strong Programme approach is flawed, the article diverges from standard criti- cisms by suggesting that the best alternative is not a dualistic framework but a more adequate monistic approach. Keywords: Strong Programme; interests; monism; finitism; classification 1. INTRODUCTION The Strong Programme (SP) analysis of scientific knowledge is generally acknowledged to have been a crucial inspiration for devel- opments in the sociological study of science over the past 25 years. David Bloor and Barry Barnes, sometimes in collaboration with Don- ald MacKenzie and Steven Shapin, rigorously argued that social fac- tors must be incorporated into any account of the dynamics of scien- tific knowledge. Crucially, they claimed that the commitments of scientists to specific beliefs cannot be explained without reference to social interests, even if those beliefs are judged to be rational or ade- quate. These arguments stimulated many responses, including sple- netic attacks (e.g., Slezak 1994), careful critical appraisals (e.g., Keat Received 1 November 2001 My thanks go to the British Academy for supporting me during the completion of this article through their Postdoctoral Fellowship scheme. Thanks also to Gillian Haddow, Gregor McLennan, Maureen O’Malley, Sharani Osborn, Irene Rafanell, and especially John Holmwood for their comments on this piece. Philosophy of the Social Sciences, Vol. 33 No. 3, September 2003 311-338 DOI: 10.1177/0048393103252780 © 2003 Sage Publications 311 312 PHILOSOPHY OF THE SOCIAL SCIENCES / September 2003 1989; Turner 1981), and sympathetic defences (e.g., Manicas and Rosenberg 1985, 1988). Even though the basic tenets of the SP approach have remained the same since the 1970s, having been sub- ject to careful elaboration rather than serious revision, new and inter- esting critical appraisals continued to appear throughout the 1990s (e.g., Roth 1994; Mermin 1998; Pels 1996). Despite the large amount of critical scrutiny given to the SP, I would argue that a fundamental aspect of this approach has not been given the attention that it deserves. Specifically,serious consideration has not been afforded to the SP thesis that the pursuit of social inter- ests and the pursuit of instrumentally adequate knowledge are not antithetical to one another (Barnes 1982; Bloor 1976). To put this thesis another way, the SPers claim that the logics of interest and of instru- mental adequacy are not separate and potentially conflicting but are one and the same. It is important to analyze this argument for two rea- sons. First, if we are to properly assess the merits of the theoretical apparatus produced by the SPers, we must adequately comprehend the intent of the theory. Otherwise, critical remarks may be misdi- rected and the true benefits and problems of the approach obscured.1 Second, there are wider issues at stake in a reassessment of the SP approach. The SP argument for the consonance of social interests and instrumental adequacy is of particular interest because it goes against dominant tendencies within philosophy and sociological theory. In recent times, many approaches have either implicitly or explicitly offered a dualistic analysis of science that separates issues of interest from those of adequacy, suggesting that commitments to belief based on social interests may diverge from commitments based on the ratio- nality or adequacy of belief. Such a position is found in those philo- sophical responses to the SP that argue that a plausible explanation for scientists’ commitments to irrational beliefs is that they are pursu- ing social interests that conflict with rational appraisals of the ade- quacy of knowledge (see, e.g., Hollis 1982; Newton-Smith 1981). Dualist theories are also popular within British social science. Realists such as Margaret Archer and Roy Bhaskar argue that the pursuit of social interests may lead actors to commit to beliefs other than those that are the most demonstrably adequate at the time (Archer 1988, 1995; Bhaskar 1986). Against this tendency, the SPers offer a monistic approach, in which no distinction can be made between the pursuit of social interest and the pursuit of adequate belief. Rather, commit- ments based on social interests and commitments based on the instru- mental adequacy of belief are said to be the same. Kemp / STRONG PROGRAMME RECONSIDERED 313 An assessment of the SP framework is thus relevant to the debate between monistic and dualistic approaches. Within the course of this article, I shall be arguing that there are serious difficulties within the SP approach. However, unlike many critics, I shall suggest that we should look to resolve these problems by adopting a more consistent monism rather than shifting to a dualist perspective. To offer a coher- ent analysis of scientific knowledge, it is necessary to successfully unite the analysis of social interests and the adequacy of knowledge. To draw out the monistic intent of SP theorizing, I shall focus on their theory of classification, which is based on the philosophical doc- trine of meaning finitism. This is outlined in some detail in Section 2. Section 3 then critically assesses this theory, lauding its attempt to unify analysis of interests and adequacy but suggesting that this ulti- mately fails due to untenable accounts of both factors. Section 4 offers some concluding remarks. 2. SCIENTIFIC CLASSIFICATION: A SOCIOLOGICAL APPROACH This section introduces the SP theory of categorization. Processes of categorization are fundamental to the development of knowledge in two respects. Firstly, it is through categorization that actors pro- duce a differentiated understanding of the world and identify the characteristics of the entities that they encounter. Second, such cate- gorizations are called upon in other forms of knowledge, including generalizations, laws, and predictions. As a result, our understanding of processes of categorization has ramifications for these other forms of knowledge. The theory of classification2 offered by the SPers is intended to demonstrate the importance of social and instrumental influences in the development of classifications. To show this, they build upon a theory of the meaning and content of categorizations called meaning finitism, developed from the work of Mary Hesse (1974) and Ludwig Wittgenstein (1968), among others.3 Although the essentials of the SP approach to classification were developed in the early 1980s (e.g., Barnes 1982), interest in this approach has been renewed by the release of a textbook expounding the SP approach titled Scientific Knowledge: A Sociological Analysis (Barnes, Bloor, and Henry 1996) (for recent discussions, see Mermin 1998; Forge 1996; Miller 1996). 314 PHILOSOPHY OF THE SOCIAL SCIENCES / September 2003 Meaning finitism is an account of categorization processes that is intended to apply to all categorizations, whether these are part of our wider culture or lodged in specialized bodies of knowledge. Put sim- ply, meaning finitism argues that the meaning or content of any term is given by the finite set of particulars that the term designates (Bloor 1996). To grasp the meaning of any term is to learn the set of particular entities that are classified under it and that are thus instances of it. For example, to learn the meaning of the term dog is to learn which partic- ular creatures fall under that categorization. It is the set of instances that conveys the sense in which all members of the category are simi- lar to each other, that is, resemble each other, and are thus appropri- ately classified together (Barnes, Bloor, and Henry 1996, 50). So the sense in which dogs are similar is conveyed by an examination of the instances of the term dog. This understanding of the similarity of one set of entities may also provide a sense of their difference from other sets of entities. By identifying a group of particulars as dogs, we dif- ferentiate them from another group of particulars classified as cats. Having made these basic points, the SPers then make a radical move. They argue that, formally speaking, existing categorizations of similarity do not provide any guidance whatsoever for continuing acts of classification, that is, attempts to decide if a new case should be treated as an instance of an existing category. As they put it, Any classification of the next case can be reconciled with what has already been learned...however other things have been classified so far, the next thing can be classified in any way without any formal inconsistency with earlier practice. (Barnes, Bloor, and Henry 1996, 51) The reasoning behind this move is fairly simple. The SPers argue that a comparison of any and every pair of entities will find them to be both similar to each other in some respects, and different in other respects (Barnes 1982, 28). As such, if we compare a new particular to members of some existing category, we will always find that it has both similarities and differences to members of that category (Barnes, Bloor, and Henry 1996, 50). This gives us no general grounds for deciding whether it should enter that category. It could be objected that particulars can still be classified by their greater or lesser degrees of resemblance. However, Barnes, Bloor, and Henry (1996) argue that there is no possible “metric for resemblance,” and this being the case, there is no objective basis for claiming that “sameness here outweighs difference there” (Barnes, Bloor, and Kemp / STRONG PROGRAMME RECONSIDERED 315 Henry 1996, 51).
Recommended publications
  • Philosophy in Review/Comptes Rendus Philosophiques Volume XXII, No
    Philosophy in Review/Comptes rendus philosophiques Volume XXII, No. 1 Alexander Bird Thomas Kuhn. Princeton, NJ: Princeton University Press 2000. Pp. xii + 308. US$39.50 (cloth: TSBN 0-691-05709-5); US$16.95 (paper: TSBN 0-691-05709-9). After Thomas Kuhn's death in 1996, there has been increasing interest in his work, so much so that in the year 2000 there was a book of Kuhn's previously published essays, The Road Since Structure: Philosophical Es- says, 1970-1993, with an Autohiographical Interview (RSS), and there were four books published on Kuhn: Alexander Bird's book, Steve Fuller's Thomas Kuhn: A Philosophical History for Our Times, Hanne Anderson's On Kuhn, and Ziauddin Sardar's Thomas Kuhn and the Science Wars. Bird's book, which is the first book on Kuhn from the perspective of naturalistic episte- mology, puts Kuhn's ideas into their historical context, and expounds on what Kuhn thinks on topics such as normal and revolutionary science. Bird argues that Kuhn's theory is imbued with commitments to empiricist and Cartesian 9 traditions, which Kuhn has already rejected. Hence, Kuhn's theory is not a thorough naturalistic epistemology, which then leads to scepticism and relativism. Of interest to the generalist are the first three chapters, which are on Kuhn's historical context, normal and revolutionary science, and paradigms. Of interest to the specialist are the last three chapters that are on the topics of perception and world change, incommensurability and meaning, and progress, truth, knowledge and relativism. In these latter chapters Bird argues that if Kuhn had become a naturalistic epistemologist, he would have avoided scepticism.
    [Show full text]
  • Naturalized Epistemology, Or What the Strong Programme Can't Explain
    Studies in History and Philosophy of Science Stud. Hist. Phil. Sci. 36 (2005) 135–148 www.elsevier.com/locate/shpsa Naturalized epistemology, or what the Strong Programme canÕt explain Karyn L. Freedman University of Guelph, Guelph, Ont., Canada, N1G 2W1 Received 26 September 2003; received in revised form 5 April 2004 Abstract In this paper I argue that the Strong ProgrammeÕs aim to provide robust explanations of belief acquisition is limited by its commitment to the symmetry principle. For Bloor and Barnes, the symmetry principle is intended to drive home the fact that epistemic norms are socially constituted. My argument here is that even if our epistemic standards are fully natu- ralized—even relativized—they nevertheless can play a pivotal role in why individuals adopt the beliefs that they do. Indeed, sometimes the fact that a belief is locally endorsed as rational is the only reason why an individual holds it. In this way, norms of rationality have a powerful and unique role in belief formation. But if this is true then the symmetry principleÕs emphasis on Ôsameness of typeÕ is misguided. It has the undesirable effect of not just naturalizing our cognitive commitments, but trivializing them. Indeed, if the notion of ÔsimilarityÕ is to have any content, then we are not going to classify as Ôthe sameÕ beliefs that are formed in accor- dance with deeply entrenched epistemic norms as ones formed without reflection on these norms, or ones formed in spite of these norms. My suggestion here is that we give up the sym- metry principle in favor of a more sophisticated principle, one that allows for a taxonomy of causes rich enough to allow us to delineate the unique impact epistemic norms have on those individuals who subscribe to them.
    [Show full text]
  • HPSC0105 Sociology of Science & Technology Course Syllabus
    HPSC0105 Sociology of Science & Technology Course Syllabus 2019-20 session | Edward Thomas Bankes | [email protected] Course Information This course examines the complex relationship between science and society. It also takes a sociological look at the process by which knowledge is constructed, using both historical and contemporary studies. The module also introduces students to the main currents of thought which have been influential in sociology of science. Basic course information Course See Moodle website: Moodle Web See Moodle, search HPSC0105 site: Assessment: 3-hour exam - 50% and essay (2500 words) - 50% Timetable: See UCL online timetable Prerequisites: None. Course aimed at 2nd and 3rd years Required texts: See below Course tutor(s): Mr Edward Thomas Bankes Contact: [email protected] Web: - Office location: 22 Gordon Square, Room B14 1 Schedule The course is split between nine topics in the sociology of science and sociology. The first four topics explore the history of the field, looking to the key moments in the maturation of the sociology of science as an academic discipline in its own right and as a way of understanding science in the world. The subsequent topics are more thematic, looking at issues that have been (and continue to be) of interest to scholars in the field. Following an introductory seminar in the first session, the lecture for each topic will take place in the second half of the session. The seminar will take place the following week in the first half of the next session. UCL Topic Activity Week 6 Introductory Seminar Core What does it mean to study science sociologically? readings can 1: Starting points: From Functionalist Sociology of be found in this syllabus.
    [Show full text]
  • Constructivist Sociology of Scientific Knowledge. in P. Galison and D
    Science Made Up: Constructivist Sociology of Scientific Knowledge. In P. Galison and D. Stump (eds.) The Disunity of Science: Boundaries, Contexts, and Power. Stanford: Stanford University Press, 1996, pp. 231-54. END NOTES 1 Part of the work for this paper was done during the tenure of a fellowship at the Center for Advanced Study in the Behavioral Sciences. I am grateful for financial support provided by the National Science Foundation, Grant #BNS-8011494, and for the assistance of the staff of the Center. I also want to thank David Bloor, Stephen Downes, David Hull and Andy Pickering for offering good advice and criticism, some of which I have heeded. 2 Later developments in this line include ethnomethodology. See Garfinkel (1967) and Sharrock and Anderson (1986). 3 For a sample of some especially sympathetic admirers see the articles in Lawson and Appignanesi (1988). 4 Of course it is not only analytic philosophers who take a combative stance towards constructivism. Some Critical Theorists do too. See, for example, McCarthy (1988). 5 The platform below is an amalgam that constitutes an "ideal type" description of constructivism. I believe it captures important features of the school (at least in many of its stages). Nevertheless I have no doubt that each member of the school will find some things in my mix with which to quarrel. In any case, I have drawn the amalgam from the social interest Edinburgh school; especially Barnes (1977), Bloor (1976), Knorr-Cetina (1981) and Pickering (1984); the historical sociology of knowledge promoted by Shapin (1982) and the actor-network analysis of texts and transcription devices pioneered by Latour and Woolgar (1979) and developed further in Latour (1987).
    [Show full text]
  • WHO HAS WON the SCIENCE WARS? Darko POLŠEK Faculty of Humanities and Social Sciences, Zagreb UDK: 001.9 Izvorni Znanstveni Rad Primljeno: 29
    WHO HAS WON THE SCIENCE WARS? Darko POLŠEK Faculty of Humanities and Social Sciences, Zagreb UDK: 001.9 Izvorni znanstveni rad Primljeno: 29. 5. 2008. Bogdanov affair in astrophysics is strikingly similar to Sokal’s in "cultural studies". This paper discusses similarities between Sokal and Bogdanov affairs, especially the outrageous methods and behaviour of brothers Bogdanov, and concludes that the latter affair has shown that natural sciences and natural scientists are not beyond reproach, beyond criteria of cogency, validity and criticism, as was once suggested by Sokal’s affair. This has a broader morale: Since "high science" is understood by fewer scholars, such science is sometimes more prone to outrageous hypothesis which would not be tolerated in the more common ones. Therefore, there has to be at least a symmetry in critical approach to scientific claims: neither the type of science, nor the fame of scientists should provide a guarantee of proper conduct and scientific methodology. The paper discusses various meanings of symmetry in scientific approach to science, and discussing "trust" and "distrust" in science suggests a description of the s.c. "circle of credibility". Keywords: Bogdanov affair, Sokal affair, symmetry of criticism, circle of credibility Darko Polšek, Faculty of Humanities and Social Sciences, University of Zagreb, Department of Anthropology, I. Lučića 3, 10 000 Zagreb, Croatia. E-mail: dpolsek @ffzg.hr The goal of the paper 1 is to describe the state of the art in the social studies of science. By enlisting problems with scientific fraud of various kinds, it tries to answer the question about the importance of relativism as a standard commitment in the social studies of science (SSS), to assess the weight and long term consequences of the previous affairs in SSS, most noto - 1023 riously the Sokal's affair, and it tries to answer the question: DRU[.
    [Show full text]
  • Logical Empiricism
    Logical Empiricism HISTORICAL CONTEMPORARY PERSPECTIVES Edited by Paolo Parrini, University ofFlorence Wesley C. Salmon, University ofPittsburgh Merrilee H. Salmon, University of Pittsburgh UNIVERSITY OF PITTSBURGH PRESS This book is dedicated to the memory of Wesley C . Salmon 1925-2001 Published by the University of Pittsburgh Press, Pittsburgh, P&, 15260 Copyright ® 2003, University of Pittsburgh Press All rights reserved Manufactured in the United States of America Printed on add-free paper 10987654321 ISBN 0 - 8n9- 4194-5 Contents Preface Introduction r Paolo Parrini and Wesley Salmon I. Turning Points and Fundamental Controversies rt A Turning Point in Philosophy : Carnap-Cassirer-Heidegger 13 Michael Friedman Carnap's "Elimination of Metaphysics through Logical Analysis of Language" : A Retrospective Consideration of the Relationship between Continental and Analytic Philosophy 30 Gottfried Gabriel Schlick and Husserl on the Essence of Knowledge 43 Roberta Lanfredini Carnap versus Gbdel on Syntax and Tolerance 57 S. Awodey and A. W Carus II. On the Origins and Development of the Vienna Circle 65 On the Austrian Roots of Logical Empiricism: The Case of the First Vienna Circle 67 Thomas Uebel On the International Encyclopedia, the Neurath-Carnap Disputes, and the Second World War 94 George Reisch Carl Gustav Hempel : Pragmatic Empiricist log Gereon Wolters III. The Riddle of Wittgenstein 123 The Methods of the Tractatus: Beyond Positivism and Metaphysics? 125 David G. Stern IV Philosophy of Physics 157 Two Roads from Kant : Cassirer, Reichenbach, and General Relativity ' 159 T A. Ryckman Vienna Indeterminism II : From Exner to Frank and von Mises 194 'Michael Stoltzner V. The Mind-Body Problem 231 The Mind-Body Problem in the Origin of Logical Empiricism : Herbert Feigl and Psychophysical Parallelism 233 Michael Heidelberger Logical Positivism and the Mind-Body Problem 263 Jaegwon Kim VI.
    [Show full text]
  • Truth After Post-Truth: for a Strong Programme in Discourse Studies
    Original citation: Angermüller, Johannes (2018) Truth after post-truth : for a strong programme in discourse studies. Palgrave Communications, 4 (1). 30. doi:10.1057/s41599-018-0080-1 Permanent WRAP URL: http://wrap.warwick.ac.uk/101933 Copyright and reuse: The Warwick Research Archive Portal (WRAP) makes this work of researchers of the University of Warwick available open access under the following conditions. This article is made available under the Creative Commons Attribution 4.0 International license (CC BY 4.0) and may be reused according to the conditions of the license. For more details see: http://creativecommons.org/licenses/by/4.0/ A note on versions: The version presented in WRAP is the published version, or, version of record, and may be cited as it appears here. For more information, please contact the WRAP Team at: [email protected] warwick.ac.uk/lib-publications ARTICLE DOI: 10.1057/s41599-018-0080-1 OPEN Truth after post-truth: for a Strong Programme in Discourse Studies Johannes Angermuller1 ABSTRACT Contemporary post-truth discourses put the constructivist foundations of Discourse Studies to a test. According to critical observers, discourse analysts have been playing into the hands of Trump, Brexit and right-wing populists by politicising scientific fi 1234567890():,; knowledge and undermining the idea of scienti c truth. In order to respond to these concerns, this article outlines a Strong Programme in Discourse Studies. While the Strong Programme insists on truths as discursive constructions, in no way does it claim that all ideas have the same truth value or that an idea can become true because somebody wants it to be true.
    [Show full text]
  • We Have Never Been Anti-Science: Reflections on Science Wars and Post-Truth
    Engaging Science, Technology, and Society 6 (2020), 49-57 DOI:10.17351/ests2020.309 We Have Never Been Anti-Science: Reflections on Science Wars and Post-Truth MICHAEL LYNCH1 CORNELL UNIVERSITY Abstract This essay addresses the so-called "post-truth" era in which scientific evidence of, for example, climate change, is given little weight compared to more immediate appeals to emotion and belief, and examines the relationship of alleged anti-science and populist irrationality to left- and right- wing political alignments. It also addresses charges of anti-science that were once leveled at Science and Technology Studies (STS) itself, and particularly in relation to the “symmetrical” posture taken toward scientific controversies. Recently, "symmetry" in STS has been linked to the media conventions and argumentative strategies that have sustained controversies over climate change and other health and safety concerns. This essay argues that "symmetry" was originally set up in a circumscribed way to encourage research on controversies, but that it does not amount to a general conclusion to the effect that science is no different from any other system of belief. Instead, an effort to pursue "symmetrical" research on scientific controversies can document how, far from being displaced from all relevance, scientific authority and its institutional supports are being duplicated along parallel tracks which sustain disputes and delay concerted action. Keywords anti-science; Trump Administration; symmetry; climate change Putting Post-truth and Anti-science in Perspective The treatment of science policy by the Trump administration (especially those aspects of it focused around climate change and other areas of environmental and safety policy) is part of a larger and longer-term picture that dates back at least to 1980, when Ronald Reagan was elected as President of the USA.
    [Show full text]
  • Chapter 18 Albert Borgmann and a Philosophy of Technology? I Begin
    Technè 10:2 Winter 2006 Special Issue: Durbin, In Search of Discourse Synthesis/168 Chapter 18 Albert Borgmann and a Philosophy of Technology? I begin this chapter with Higgs, Light, and Strong and their argument in Technology and the Good Life? (2000) in favor of the need for a new discipline: Broadening the scope of Philosophy of Technology “The set of questions a philosophy of technology should address in order to fulfill its promise are often at the intersection of it and other fields. In our opinion, philosophy of technology at its best should appeal to a very wide audience partly because it illuminates our shared, ordinary everyday life, such as with things and devices, and partly because the issues it probes cut across the full range of disciplines. Many of these issues are already vital matters of concern for these disciplines, such as ethics, social and political philosophy, aesthetics, art history, architecture, music, anthropology, religion, history, history of science and technology, cultural studies, sociology, political science, economics, linguistics, literary criticism, visual culture, and the hard sciences. For example, one of the interdisciplinary successes that philosophy of technology has had is with environmental ethics. Issues that join both fields are addressed in journals regularly, and numerous books have appeared. However, this kind of success should be occurring with other fields as well. What does philosophy of technology have to offer other disciplines? In the view of some of our contributors, traditional philosophical approaches may not be capable of questioning and challenging technology in a sufficiently radical manner. Nevertheless, we can show the kinds of questions a robust philosophy of technology can raise and address.
    [Show full text]
  • An Introduction to Science and Technology Studies
    9781405187657_4_005.qxd 15/7/09 10:30 AM Page 47 5 The Strong Programme and the Sociology of Knowledge The Strong Programme In the 1970s a group of philosophers, sociologists, and historians based in Edinburgh set out to understand not just the organization but the content of scientific knowledge in sociological terms, developing the “strong pro- gramme in the sociology of knowledge” (Bloor 1991 [1976]; Barnes and Bloor 1982; MacKenzie 1981; Shapin 1975). The most concise and best- known statement of the programme is David Bloor’s “four tenets” for the sociology of scientific knowledge: 1. It would be causal, that is, concerned with the conditions which bring about belief or states of knowledge. 2. It would be impartial with respect to truth and falsity, rationality or irrationality, success or failure. Both sides of these dichotomies will require explanation. 3. It would be symmetrical in its style of explanation. The same types of cause would explain, say, true and false beliefs. 4. It would be reflexive. In principle its patterns of explanation would have to be applicable to sociology itself. (Bloor 1991 [1976], 5) These represent a bold but carefully crafted statement of a naturalistic, perhaps scientific, attitude toward science and scientific knowledge, which can be extended to technological knowledge as well. Beliefs are treated as objects, and come about for reasons or causes. It is the job of the sociologist of knowledge to understand these reasons or causes. Seen as objects, there is no a priori distinction between beliefs that we judge true and those false, or those rational and irrational; in fact, rationality and irrationality are themselves objects of study.
    [Show full text]
  • STS C200, Week 5: the Sociology of Scientific Knowledge
    STS C200, Week 5: The Sociology of Scientific Knowledge Orr Paradise September 27th, 2020 1 Bloor [3, 2], Barnes and Bloor [1] on the Strong Programme The strong programme of the sociology of knowledge clarifies some questions that arose in our discussion of last week’s readings. Let us recall these questions. Following Kuhn [7], we wondered what exactly is relativism (that he worked so hard to avoid), and what would sociology of knowledge look like had it embraced relativism with open arms? Following Lakatos [8], the boundaries of sociology were left unclear; do questions about ‘mathematical truth’ fall under the domain of the sociology of knowledge? I describe the strong programme and how it addresses these questions. The strong programme is a sociology of knowledge that enables itself to deal not just with failed theories, but also with successful ones. This is as opposed to the view that sociology is not applicable to successful theories, because the latter are successful due to their truthfulness or accuracy in representing nature, and therefore the particular social settings in which these theories are derived are of no relevance to the contents of the theories themselves.1 The strong programme is causal, impartial, reflexive and symmetric:2 • Causality establishes that identification of the causes of beliefs is the goal of the sociology of knowl- edge. • Impartiality guarantees that no exceptions should be made for the beliefs held by the investigator. • Reflexivity asserts that the sociology of knowledge should explain its own emergence. • Symmetry asserts that true and false beliefs are generated by the same types of causes.
    [Show full text]
  • Science and Meta-Science
    Science and Meta-Science Literary & Translation Agency Author: Mohsen Abbasnejad Subject: Non-Fiction (Science and Religion) Year of publishing: 2014 No. of Pages: 478/Paperback Size: 16.5× 22.5 ISBN: 9786005538120 • Sample English text is available Mohsen Abbasnejad Mohsen Abbasnejad 1972-Mashhad Mohsen Abbasnejad was took his BS in Mechanical Engineering but continued his studies in Philosophy. Having studied Islamic Jurisprudence and Usool in seminary under the great contemporary jurist and philosophy under a distinguished philosopher of the eastern world, he passed the highest levels of the seminary with flying colors. Having authored number of works in such field as philosophy, philosophy of science and Hadith, and Jurisprudence, Abbasnejad is now serving on Quran and epistemology, and the director of the Quranic Research Foundation. In addition to penning a six-volume collection on the basics of inter- relating science and the religion, some of his other books are as follow: -Principles and basics of the Quran and Modern Science, -Imam Ali (A.S.) Managerial Approach, -Imam Ali (A.S.) Personal Lifestyle, -Basic Rights within religious Approach, -Some Elaborations on the Principles of Islamic Jurisprudence (3 Vols.) About the book: The present book examines the relationship between science, values, metaphysics, and culture. In the section devoted to the philosophy to science. The characteristics of the positivistic epistemology as well as the critical views of Popper and Cohen regarding the influence of meta-scientific affairs such as values and metaphysics on science are carefully examined. Reviewing the ideas of such sociologists of knowledge as Marx, Dilthey, Nietzsche, Max Scheler, and Karl Mannheim as well as the strong project in the sociology of knowledge and the social identity of knowledge are examined in another section.
    [Show full text]