Theistic Ethics : Toward a Christian Solution
Total Page:16
File Type:pdf, Size:1020Kb
Load more
Recommended publications
-
Habermas, Taylor, and Connolly on Secularism, Pluralism, and the Post-Secular Public Sphere
Article Habermas, Taylor, and Connolly on Secularism, Pluralism, and the Post-Secular Public Sphere Spyridon Kaltsas Department of Political Science and Public Administration, National and Kapodistrian University of Athens, 106 78 Athens, Greece; [email protected] Received: 17 June 2019; Accepted: 31 July 2019; Published: 1 August 2019 Abstract: The main purpose of this paper is to explore and understand the relationships between secularism, pluralism, and the post-secular public sphere in the thought of Jürgen Habermas, Charles Taylor, and William Connolly. The three authors develop a thorough critique of secularism which implies a radical break with the dogmatic idea of removing religion from the public sphere. My main objective is to show that this critique is related to a normative understanding of our post- secular situation and requires a rethinking of the boundaries of the public sphere in relation to the predicament of pluralism. Arguing against the post-metaphysical conception of secularism, Taylor develops a critique of Habermas’s “institutional translation proviso”, and Connolly stresses the agonistic dimension of the post-secular public sphere. I take these criticisms into account, while arguing that Taylor and Connolly are unable to provide a sound basis for the legitimacy of our institutional settings. In contrast to Taylor and Connolly, I propose a reading of Habermas’s theory based on the internal relationship between universal justification and the everyday contexts of pre- political solidarity. I conclude with a focus on the need to take into account the agonistic dimension of the post-secular public sphere. Keywords: post-secular society; secularism; public sphere; pluralism; legitimation; ethics of citizenship; Jürgen Habermas; Charles Taylor; William Connolly 1. -
The Reality of Moral Imperatives in Liberal Religion
University of Pennsylvania Carey Law School Penn Law: Legal Scholarship Repository Faculty Scholarship at Penn Law 1-23-2013 The Reality of Moral Imperatives in Liberal Religion Howard Lesnick University of Pennsylvania Carey Law School Follow this and additional works at: https://scholarship.law.upenn.edu/faculty_scholarship Part of the Ethics and Political Philosophy Commons, Ethics in Religion Commons, Jurisprudence Commons, Law and Society Commons, Public Law and Legal Theory Commons, and the Religion Law Commons Repository Citation Lesnick, Howard, "The Reality of Moral Imperatives in Liberal Religion" (2013). Faculty Scholarship at Penn Law. 339. https://scholarship.law.upenn.edu/faculty_scholarship/339 This Article is brought to you for free and open access by Penn Law: Legal Scholarship Repository. It has been accepted for inclusion in Faculty Scholarship at Penn Law by an authorized administrator of Penn Law: Legal Scholarship Repository. For more information, please contact [email protected]. THE REALITY OF MORAL IMPERATIVES IN LIBERAL RELIGION HOWARD LESNICK Fordham Professor of Law University of Pennsylvania Abstract This paper uses a classic one-liner attributed to Dostoyoevski’s Ivan Karamozov, "Without God everything is permitted," to explore some differences between what I term traditional and liberal religion. The expansive connotations and implications of Ivan’s words are grounded in the historic association of wrongfulness and punishment, and in a reaction against the late modern challenge to the inexorability of that association, whether in liberal religion or in secular moral thought. The paper argues that, with its full import understood, Ivan’s claim begs critical questions of the meaning and source of compulsion and choice, and of knowledge and belief regarding the specific content of religiously grounded moral norms. -
Moral Relativism and Absolutism 2
Jewish Contemporary Ethics Part 4: Moral Relativism and Absolutism II by Rabbi Dr Moshe Freedman, New West End Synagogue The last article described the The 18th century Scottish philosopher David drawbacks of deriving ethical Hume noted that there is something qualitatively behaviour through reason different between factual observations about alone. Mankind is subjective, the world (‘is’ statements), and prescriptive ethnocentric and biased statements about how individuals ‘ought’ to towards specific vested act. Known as the ‘is-ought fallacy’ or interests. In contrast, the Hume’s guillotine, as Oxford philosopher and Jewish perspective on psychologist Brian Earp puts it: “there is no morality is that God is the objective arbiter of way to reason from facts about the way the human ethical behaviour, the absolute truth of world is, to statements about the way the world which is woven into the reality of creation. should be. You can’t derive values from data”. One might argue that mankind does have the One contemporary attempt to apply scientific capacity to agree on global moral standards, objectivity to secular ethics was suggested by such as the Universal Declaration of Human the American philosopher, neuroscientist and Rights. However, as British philosopher Simon neo-atheist Sam Harris. In his book The Ethical Blackburn puts it, “there will be a little voice Landscape, Harris claims that well-being could saying that we are ‘merely’ imposing our wills on be measured scientifically, such that any given others … it will not silence the relativistic imp on action could be impartially tested for how it our shoulders”. promotes human happiness. -
021 Existentialism-Sartre.Doc READINGS: EXISTENTIALISM
021_Existentialism-Sartre.doc READINGS: EXISTENTIALISM (SARTRE) Thomas Mann, Doktor Faustus Primo Levi, The Drowned and the Saved Jean-Paul Sartre, Existentialism Simone de Beauvoir, The Second Sex Schoenberg, Survivor of Warsaw Selections from Thomas Mann, Doktor Faustus According to Schleppfuss all this -- evil, the Evil One himself -- was a necessary emanation and inevitable accompaniment of the Holy Existence of God, so that vice did not consist in itself but got its satisfaction from the defilement of virtue, without which it would have been rootless; in other words, it consisted in the enjoyment of freedom, the possibility of sinning, which was inherent in the act of creation itself. Herein was expressed a certain logical incompleteness of the All-powerfulness and All-goodness of God; for what He had not been able to do was to produce in the creature, in that which he had liberated out of Himself and which was now outside Him, the incapacity for sin. That would have meant denying to the created being the free will to turn away from God -- which would have been an incomplete creation, yes, positively not a creation at all, but a surrender on the part of God.... Evil contributed to the wholeness of the universe, without it the universe would not have been complete; therefor God permitted it.... St. Augustine, at least, had gone so far as to say that the function of the bad was to make the good stand out more strongly... We wrote that down in our notebooks, that we might go home more or less cheered. The real vindication of God, in view of the pains of creation, so we added to Schleppfuss’s dictation, consisted in His power to bring good out of evil…. -
Can We Share Ethical Views with Other Religions?
Western Michigan University ScholarWorks at WMU Center for the Study of Ethics in Society Papers Center for the Study of Ethics in Society 11-1993 Can We Share Ethical Views with Other Religions? Robert Hannaford Ripon College Follow this and additional works at: https://scholarworks.wmich.edu/ethics_papers Part of the Bioethics and Medical Ethics Commons, Business Law, Public Responsibility, and Ethics Commons, Ethics and Political Philosophy Commons, Ethics in Religion Commons, and the Legal Ethics and Professional Responsibility Commons WMU ScholarWorks Citation Hannaford, Robert, "Can We Share Ethical Views with Other Religions?" (1993). Center for the Study of Ethics in Society Papers. 97. https://scholarworks.wmich.edu/ethics_papers/97 This Complete Issue is brought to you for free and open access by the Center for the Study of Ethics in Society at ScholarWorks at WMU. It has been accepted for inclusion in Center for the Study of Ethics in Society Papers by an authorized administrator of ScholarWorks at WMU. For more information, please contact wmu- [email protected]. WES fER'\ MICHIGAN UNIVERSI1Y Center for the Study of Ethics in Society [Papers publi.-;hed by the Ceoter] Volume 7, No.2 November, 1993 CAN WE SHARE ETHICAL VIEWS WITH OTHER RELIGIONS? Robert Hannaford Center for the Study of Ethics in Society Western Michigan University Kalamazoo, MI 49008 The purpose of WMU's Center for the Study of Ethics is to encourage and support research, teaching, and seiVice to the university and community in areas of applied and professional ethics. These areas include, but are not restricted to: business, education, engineering, government, health and human seiVices, law, media, medicine, science, and technology. -
The Church and Social Responsibility
Southern Methodist University SMU Scholar Religious Studies Theses and Dissertations Religious Studies Spring 5-18-2019 The Church and Social Responsibility: Contributions to Contemporary Social Ethics from the Ecumenical Social Method of the Oxford Conference on Church, Community, and State of 1937 Gary B. MacDonald Southern Methodist University, [email protected] Follow this and additional works at: https://scholar.smu.edu/religious_studies_etds Part of the Christianity Commons, Ethics in Religion Commons, Missions and World Christianity Commons, and the Practical Theology Commons Recommended Citation MacDonald, Gary B., "The Church and Social Responsibility: Contributions to Contemporary Social Ethics from the Ecumenical Social Method of the Oxford Conference on Church, Community, and State of 1937" (2019). Religious Studies Theses and Dissertations. 12. https://scholar.smu.edu/religious_studies_etds/12 This Dissertation is brought to you for free and open access by the Religious Studies at SMU Scholar. It has been accepted for inclusion in Religious Studies Theses and Dissertations by an authorized administrator of SMU Scholar. For more information, please visit http://digitalrepository.smu.edu. THE CHURCH AND SOCIAL RESPONSIBILITY: CONTRIBUTIONS TO CONTEMPORARY SOCIAL ETHICS FROM THE ECUMENICAL METHOD OF THE OXFORD CONFERENCE ON CHURCH, COMMUNITY, AND STATE OF 1937 Approved by: ____________________________________ Dr. Robin W. Lovin Professor Emeritus in Ethics ____________________________________ Dr. Charles E. Curran Professor -
Early Medieval Ethics G
University of Richmond UR Scholarship Repository Religious Studies Faculty Publications Religious Studies 1992 Early Medieval Ethics G. Scott aD vis University of Richmond, [email protected] Follow this and additional works at: http://scholarship.richmond.edu/religiousstudies-faculty- publications Part of the Christianity Commons, Ethics in Religion Commons, History of Christianity Commons, and the History of Religion Commons Recommended Citation Davis, G. Scott. "Early Medieval Ethics." In A History of Western Ethics, edited by Lawrence C. Becker and Charlotte B. Becker, 45-53. New York: Garland Press, 1992. This Book Chapter is brought to you for free and open access by the Religious Studies at UR Scholarship Repository. It has been accepted for inclusion in Religious Studies Faculty Publications by an authorized administrator of UR Scholarship Repository. For more information, please contact [email protected]. Copyright © 1992 from A History of Western Ethics by Lawrence C. Becker and Charlotte B. Becker. Reproduced by permission of Taylor and Francis, LLC, a division of Informa plc. Early Medieval Ethics 5 Scott Davis "Medieval" and its cognates arose as terms of opprobrium, used by the Italian humanists to characterize more a style than an age. I Ience it is difficult at bestto distinguish late antiquity from the early middle ages. It is equallydifficultto determine the properscope of 'ethics,' the philosophical schools of late antiquity having become purveyors of ways of life in the broadest sense, not dearly to be distinguished from the more intellectually oriented versions of their religious rivals. This chapter will begin with the emergence of philosophically informed reflection on the nature of life, its ends and responsibilities in the writings of the Latin Fathers and dose with the twelfth century, prior to the systematic reintroduction and study of the Aristotelian corpus. -
Christian and Secular Ethics: a Distinct Relationship
International Journal of Philosophy and Theology September 2014, Vol. 2, No. 3, pp. 75-91 ISSN: 2333-5750 (Print), 2333-5769 (Online) Copyright © The Author(s). 2014. All Rights Reserved. Published by American Research Institute for Policy Development DOI: 10.15640/ijpt.v2n3a6 URL: http://dx.doi.org/10.15640/ijpt.v2n3a6 Christian and Secular Ethics: A Distinct Relationship Miltiadis Proios1 & Ioannis M. Proios1 Abstract Ethics is a concept used by people in everyday life. Apart from ethics existing in the wider social environment (secular ethics), another form of ethics found in a specific environment has been supported, that of Christian Ethics. While secular ethics has been studied quite intensely through a variety of theories, the issue of Christian Ethics especially within the framework of Orthodox Church did not evoke strong interest. The aim of the present study was to investigate the existence of a distinct relationship among the two forms of ethics (secular and Christian). This relationship was studied through the theoretical framework of cognitive-developmental theory. The findings of the present study support the fact that the course of Christian ethics growth presents similar characteristics to that of secular ethics. Additionally, Christian ethics, via a proper preparation could constitute an evaluative measure for people. Keywords: Moral, Christian ethics, Cognitive growth, Moral perfection Introduction Christian ethics, as part of the wider concept of ethics, is a new scientific field that studies proper human behavior. This results into a number of questions, such as what “Christian ethics” exactly is as a spiritual practice or whether it is identical or totally different from moral philosophy (Green, 1978; Gustafson, 1998; Lovin & Reynolds, 1985; Reeder, 1998; Schweiker, 2005; Stout, 1998). -
Yale Forum on Religion and Ecology Jainism and Ecology Bibliography
Yale Forum on Religion and Ecology Jainism and Ecology Bibliography Bibliography by: Christopher Key Chapple, Loyola Marymount University, Allegra Wiprud, and the Yale Forum on Religion and Ecology Ahimsa: Nonviolence. Directed by Michael Tobias. Produced by Marion Hunt. Narrated by Lindsay Wagner. Direct Cinema Ltd. 58 min. Public Broadcasting Corporation, 1987. As the first documentary to examine Jainism, this one-hour film portrays various aspects of Jain religion and philosophy, including its history, teachers, rituals, politics, law, art, pilgrimage sites, etc. In doing so, the film studies the relevance of ancient traditions of Jainism for the present day. Ahimsa Quarterly Magazine. 1, no. 1 (1991). Bhargava, D. N. “Pathological Impact of [sic] Environment of Professions Prohibited by Jain Acaryas.” In Medieval Jainism: Culture and Environment, eds. Prem Suman Jain and Raj Mal Lodha, 103–108. New Delhi: Ashish Publishing House, 1990. Bhargava provides a chart and short explanation of the fifteen trades that both sects of Jainism forbid and that contribute to environmental pollution and pathological effects on the human body. Caillat, Colette. The Jain Cosmology. Translated by R. Norman. Basel: Ravi Kumar. Bombay: Jaico Publishing House, 1981. Chapple, Christopher Key. “Jainism and Ecology.” In When Worlds Converge: What Science and Religion Tell Us about the Story of the Universe and Our Place In It, eds. Clifford N. Matthews, Mary Evelyn Tucker, and Philip Hefner, 283-292. Chicago: Open Court, 2002. In this book chapter, Chapple provides a basic overview of the relationship of Jainism and ecology, discussing such topics as biodiversity, environmental resonances and social activism, tensions between Jainism and ecology, and the universe filled with living beings. -
The Role and Function of the Scriptures in Moral Theology
THE ROLE AND FUNCTION OF THE SCRIPTURES IN MORAL THEOLOGY The function of the Scriptures in moral theology has been a perennial question for the science of moral theology. Today the question assumes even greater importance and urgency in the light of two tendencies in contemporary theology which may even repre- sent contradictory trends. On the one hand, the biblical renewal has made a great contribution to the development of moral theology in the last decade. The contemporary moral theologian has re- jected the moral manuals of the past for many reasons, but the failure to find a basic orientation and grounding in the Scriptures frequently is mentioned as a most important lack in the older text- books. On the other hand, there has been another trend which has expanded the concept of revelation to cover much more than just the word of God in the Scriptures. An increasing emphasis, at some times in an exaggerated way, has been given to this world and the wisdom which persons in this world can acquire from one another and from their worldly existence. Theologians have recently been asking what if anything is distinctive about Christian ethics which has its primary source in the Scriptures. In the midst of a plurality of sources of ethical wisdom what are the role and function of the Scriptures? This paper will discuss the question from three different aspects: the advantages that have accrued to Catholic moral theology in the last decades because of a greater emphasis on the Scriptures; the inherent limitations of the use of the Scriptures in moral theology; two fundamental methodological questions governing the use of the Scriptures in moral theology. -
7 Ethics Needs
“Ethics Needs God.” Paul Copan In Debating Christian Theism. Edited by J.P. Moreland, Chad V. Meister, and Khaldoun Sweis. Oxford: Oxford University Press, 2013. Pages 85-100. A MORAL ARGUMENT 7 Ethics Needs God Paul Copan Let me briefly clarify what I do and do not defend in this chapter. My argument will not advance the following points: Objective moral values exist. Both sides here represented assume this.1 Belief in God is required for recognizing moral truths. Properly functioning naturalists, Buddhists, Confucians, and theists know the right thing to do. Atheists/nontheists cannot live decently or be kind to others. Indeed, some may exhibit greater moral virtue than some professing theists. Atheists/nontheists cannot formulate ethical systems that overlap or mesh with theologically oriented ones. Certain Old Testament practices, actions, or regulations are historically and contextually confined and should not be taken as normative and universal. Frequently critiques of theism include inferior moral practices, laws, and actions in the Old Testament—and fall prey to many misunderstandings and misrepresentations. I thoroughly address this topic elsewhere.2 What I am arguing is this: Theism offers a far more likely context than naturalism/nontheism for affirming objective moral values and duties. Naturalism does not lead us to expect the emergence of human rights and universal benevolence—a point equally applicable to other nontheistic worldviews. Many naturalists themselves observe that naturalism’s context simply cannot lead us to human rights/dignity and moral duties. Theism offers a more plausible context than atheism/nontheism for affirming a cluster of features related to human dignity and moral duties. -
The Antichrist As a Guide to Nietzsche's Mature Ethical Theory
The Antichrist as a guide to Nietzsche’s mature ethical theory Paul Katsafanas Draft To appear in Routledge Philosophy Minds: Nietzsche, ed. Paul Katsafanas There’s one thing that’s perfectly obvious about Nietzsche: he’s critical of traditional ethics. His books are full of impassioned attacks on traditional values: he argues that modern morality may be the “danger of dangers” (GM Preface 6); he claims to show that traditional morality undermines life, health, and power (A 6; GM Preface 6; KSA 12:2[190]); he tells us that “the whole of our European morality” is on the verge of “collapse” (GS 343); and he warns us that “the deeper one looks, the more our valuations disappear—meaninglessness approaches!” (KSA 11:25[505]). In passages of this sort, Nietzsche isn’t just complaining about the details of particular ethical theories. True, he thinks the traditional types of moral theory—virtue theories, sentimentalist theories, utilitarian theories, Kantian and rationalist theories—are failures.1 But his critique is more wide ranging: he thinks that many of the concerns and concepts that play central roles in modern ethical life must be rejected. Thus, it’s not just that Kant’s argument for the Categorical Imperative fails (nearly everyone can agree with that); it’s also that the very aspiration for equal consideration, for the equal dignity of persons, for universalization—all of these aspirations, to which the Categorical Imperative is supposed to give expression, are rejected as well.2 Kant and his followers aren’t just wrong in the details, Nietzsche thinks, but also in the ideals and assumptions that motivate their theories.