020 7490 7300 Fax: 020 7490 0080 [email protected]

Total Page:16

File Type:pdf, Size:1020Kb

020 7490 7300 Fax: 020 7490 0080 Inquiries@Duckworth-Publishers.Co First published in 2008 by Gerald Duckworth & Co. Ltd. 90-93 Cowcross Street, London EC1M 6BF Tel: 020 7490 7300 Fax: 020 7490 0080 [email protected]. uk www.ducknet.co.uk Editorial arrangement @ 2008 by Patricia O'Grady The contributors retain copyright in their individual chapters. All rights reserved. No part of this publication may be reproduced, stored in a retrieval system, or transmitted, in any form or by any means, electronic, mechanical, photocopying, recording or otherwise, without the prior permission of the publisher. A catalogue record for this book is available from the British Library ISBN 978 0 7156 3695 4 Typeset by Ray Davies Printed and bound in Great Britain by MPG Books, Bodmin Cornwall 12 Isocrates Contents Doug AI-Maini Contributors vii Acknowledgements viii Isocrates of Athens (436-338 BC) was a contemporary of Plato (429-347 BC), Introduction Patricia O'Grady 1 although Isocrates was both born earlier and lived longer than the famous 1. What is a Sophist? Patricia O'Grady 9 philosopher. Growing up in a wealthy family (his father Theodorus made a fortune 2. The Political Background of the Sophists at Athens 21 in flute production), Isocrates received a fine education, with reports coming down Steven R. Robinson to us of his studying with some of the famous intellectuals of the day, most 3. Protagoras Jonathan Lavery 30 probably with Gorgias, although Protagoras and Socrates are also mentioned as 4. Gorgias Colin Higgins 45 figures with whom Isocrates spent time. The family fortune was destroyed by 5. Hippias Patricia O'Grady 56 events following the Peloponnesian War, and Isocrates was forced to write 6. Prodicus Craig Cooper 71 speeches for use in the law-courts in order to earn a living. He continued to write 7. Antiphon Andrew Shortridge and Dirk Baltzly 83 speeches for the rest of his adult life, although he eventually rejected his early 8. Thrasymachus Daniel Silvermintz 93 courtroom speeches in favour of more politically and educationally oriented work. 9. Callicles Louis Groarke 101 As a result of these later speeches, Isocrates has come to be known as one of the 10. Critias Sabatino DiBernardo 111 'Ten Attic Orators', a canonical list of men who encapsulate the great rhetorical 11. Euthydemus and Dionysodorus Geoff Bowe 121 achievements of Athens. 12. Isocrates Doug Al-Maini 129 Public speaking was very important to Athenian political life and to Classical 13. The Anonymus lamblichi and the Double Arguments 138 Patricia O'Grady and Daniel Silvermintz Greek culture in general (Vernant 1982, 46-50); oratory is the name we give to 14. Minor Sophists Trevor Curnow 152 examples of discourse that are made with the intention of educating or persuading 15. Was Socrates a Sophist? Christine Farmer 164 people on some matter. Isocrates is best known for his contribution to this area of 16. Plato: The Sophist Paul Groarke 175 Athenian culture. Aristotle famously divides oratory into three categories: judicial, 17. Were the Sophists Philosophers? Trevor Curnow 185 which covers all speeches concerned with the courts; deliberative, which is 18. Law against Nature? Andrew Shortridge 194 concerned with proper planning generally and which finds its civic example in the 19. The Sophists and Natural Theology George Arabatzis 204 oratory that.takes place in the Assembly; and display, which can be understood to 20. Can Virtue Be Taught? Glenn Rawson 214 include every oration not belonging in an obvious way to either the jadicial or 21. The Case against Teaching Virtue for Pay Geoff Bowe 226 deliberative categories (Rhetoric 1.3). More helpfully, display (epideictic) speeches are 22. The Relevance of the Sophists Today Seamus Sweeney 241 orations that do not call for a specific action on the part of the audience, but rather are meant as depictions of oratorical skill or as amusements of some sort. It is to the last category, display pieces, that Isocrates made his greatest contributions. Map Bevin Boden 248 Isocrates' fame as a speechwriter was such that he was able to open a school in Index 249 Athens sometime around 392 BC (there are reports that, having been forced to flee Athens in 404 because of the Peloponnesian War, he established a school of rhetoric on the island of Chios at an earlier time). Education is a common theme in Isocrates' work, and it is important to v 129 realise that Isocrates characterised himself as a teacher of philosophy and his school while in the sophists' enterprise. In this chapter I wish to explore this. question of as a school of philosophy. Isocrates established his school before Plato set up the whether or not Isocrates qualifies as a sophist and what the arguments are on Academy, and though it is Plato's school that tradition associates with the origins of either side of the case. institutionalised higher learning, Isocrates would dispute this claim. The two schools Because of the breadth of Isocrates' endeavours, in order to confront this competed with each other, and it is clear that some of Isocrates' work is meant both question it will be useful to set the category of sophist off against the related terms to defend his own understanding of what philosophy consists of and to castigate of philosopher and speechwriter. As this brief introduction has shown, Isocrates other, more theoretically-based, notions of philosophy that are championed by Plato, has some reason to be considered as a member of all three of these professions. I among others. So we see that Isocrates, as well as being a speech writer, also has hope that the notion of what a sophist is will become clearer by means of this some right to the title of philosopher. comparison, and that seeing how Isocrates both conforms to and breaks the The fees charged at his school are now thought to have been very high, and are conventions of these three professions will give us both a better understanding of one source of the fortune he amassed. Life at the school was devoted to preparing his life and a better appreciation of the other figures in this book. In any event, it is for participation in civic affairs, and this meant being able to engage in public worth exploring Isocrates as a figure who exists on the fringes of the category of discourse. Isocrates could with some justification claim to be a trainer of speakers 'sophist': he provides an excellent test case that shows where the borders between and politicians generally, developing his students' skill at composing effective sophist, philosopher and speechwriter lie, and this is because of the way he arguments intended to persuade juries and assemblymen. Indeed, he worried that he combines his moral life with his chosen professional activities. would be known as someone who is 'able to make the weaker cause the stronger' To begin with, then, we shall approach Isocrates as a philosopher, a perspective (Isocrates, Antidosis 313), invoking the famous description of Protagoras the sophist. which, as we have seen, he himself was inclined to adopt. Famously, the word Furthermore, Isocrates is at home in the tradition of the sophists who extol pan- 'philosophy' itself comes to us from ancient Greek, combining the words philos Hellenic virtues. In other words, Isocrates champions the attitude of Greeks thinking meaning 'love' and sophos meaning wise. A philosopher is thus a lover of wisdom, of themselves primarily as Greeks, as opposed to the non-Greeks who surrounded and the overlap between our two categories of philosopher and sophist is apparent them (such as the Persians and the Egyptians), and possibly even more so than as from their etymology: they both are concerned with wisdom. The names also citizens of any particular city or polis. These descriptions of Isocrates' activities, indicate a certain humbleness on the part of the philosopher that the sophist does charging high fees for teaching others how to make clever speeches, pan-Hellenism, not share; thus the philosopher is only a lover of wisdom. Indeed, if we are to and especially the ability to invert the relative power of arguments are the hallmarks accept the assertion of Socrates in Plato's Symposium that all love is a desire for of a sophist. something of which one is in need, then philosophers are as good as admitting that However, Isocrates takes great pains to distance himself from the sophists. An they do not have wisdom (Plato has Socrates defend this claim about love being a early speech of his, entitled Against the Sophists, contains these lines: lack of something at Symposium 200a-c), while the sophist professes actually to be a 'wise one'. By Isocrates' time, the name 'sophist' had some disrepute attached to it Indeed, who can fail to abhor, yes to contemn, those teachers, in the first (e.g. Plato, Meno 91c), but it had not by any means become simply a pejorative place, who devote themselves to disputation, since they pretend to search for term; rather it is better to understand the term 'sophist' as taking on both positive truth, but straightaway at the beginning of their professions attempt to deceive and negative connotations. It seems that at this point in history the meaning. of the us with lies? (291). term 'philosopher' is still vague enough to be open to clarification. Indeed, recent scholarship has indicated that establishing a clearer meaning for the word It is fair enough to perceive in this castigation similarities with Hamlet's mother 'philosophy' was 'a valued prize well worth contending for' among the intellectual Gertrude who protested too much, and one question that arises when trying to elite of this time, and Isocrates was one obvious competitor (Ober 1998, 251n.7; understand the life of Isocrates is whether or not he is a sophist.
Recommended publications
  • Teachers' Pay in Ancient Greece
    University of Nebraska - Lincoln DigitalCommons@University of Nebraska - Lincoln Papers from the University Studies series (The University of Nebraska) University Studies of the University of Nebraska 5-1942 Teachers' Pay In Ancient Greece Clarence A. Forbes Follow this and additional works at: https://digitalcommons.unl.edu/univstudiespapers Part of the Arts and Humanities Commons This Article is brought to you for free and open access by the University Studies of the University of Nebraska at DigitalCommons@University of Nebraska - Lincoln. It has been accepted for inclusion in Papers from the University Studies series (The University of Nebraska) by an authorized administrator of DigitalCommons@University of Nebraska - Lincoln. Teachers' Pay In Ancient Greece * * * * * CLARENCE A. FORBES UNIVERSITY OF NEBRASKA STUDIES Ma y 1942 STUDIES IN THE HUMANITIES NO.2 Note to Cataloger UNDER a new plan the volume number as well as the copy number of the University of Nebraska Studies was discontinued and only the numbering of the subseries carried on, distinguished by the month and the year of pu blica tion. Thus the present paper continues the subseries "Studies in the Humanities" begun with "University of Nebraska Studies, Volume 41, Number 2, August 1941." The other subseries of the University of Nebraska Studies, "Studies in Science and Technology," and "Studies in Social Science," are continued according to the above plan. Publications in all three subseries will be supplied to recipients of the "University Studies" series. Corre­ spondence and orders should be addressed to the Uni­ versity Editor, University of Nebraska, Lincoln. University of Nebraska Studies May 1942 TEACHERS' PAY IN ANCIENT GREECE * * * CLARENCE A.
    [Show full text]
  • Chapter 3. the Power of the Sophist to Attack Plato, Turn to His Ancient Enemies for Advice
    By way of an Introduction: These pages contain individual chapters from my 1990 book, Postmodern Sophistications. I have obtained the rights to the essays am making them available separately. The entire text of the book is also available on Research Gate. The underlying aim of this collection of essays was to question the opposition between the Sophists and Plato. That classic dispute has been the model for many discussions of tensions within our society:: on the one hand you have the clever manipulative salesmen who care nothing about truth. On the other hand the rigorous scientific investigation that never quite makes contact with politics. Rootless nihilism vs. naturally grounded values. Anarchy vs. Rules. In this book I developed a pragmatic middleground, using themes from Heidegger and Dewey; in later writings I rely more on Hegel. But the point remains the same: don't listen to the Straussians and others who try to force on our politics or art or philosophy a simple opposition between truth-loving traditionalists (Socrates) and flaky relativistic postmoderns (the Sophists). It was not so simple in Greece and it's not so simple today. Part of the book deals with postmodern critiques of rational knowledge, with Lyotard and Habermas on center stage. Their opposition between postmodern and modern views remains relevant, although post-1990 developments in deconstruction and critical theory have widened and deepened the debate. The points made in these essays remain useful, if not complete. The second part of the book deals with architecture. The word postmodern has gone out of fashion in architecture.
    [Show full text]
  • Plato's Denunciation of Rhetoric in the "Phaedrus" Author(S): Brad Mcadon Source: Rhetoric Review, Vol
    Plato's Denunciation of Rhetoric in the "Phaedrus" Author(s): Brad McAdon Source: Rhetoric Review, Vol. 23, No. 1 (2004), pp. 21-39 Published by: Taylor & Francis, Ltd. Stable URL: http://www.jstor.org/stable/20176594 Accessed: 22/09/2010 21:38 Your use of the JSTOR archive indicates your acceptance of JSTOR's Terms and Conditions of Use, available at http://www.jstor.org/page/info/about/policies/terms.jsp. JSTOR's Terms and Conditions of Use provides, in part, that unless you have obtained prior permission, you may not download an entire issue of a journal or multiple copies of articles, and you may use content in the JSTOR archive only for your personal, non-commercial use. Please contact the publisher regarding any further use of this work. Publisher contact information may be obtained at http://www.jstor.org/action/showPublisher?publisherCode=taylorfrancis. Each copy of any part of a JSTOR transmission must contain the same copyright notice that appears on the screen or printed page of such transmission. JSTOR is a not-for-profit service that helps scholars, researchers, and students discover, use, and build upon a wide range of content in a trusted digital archive. We use information technology and tools to increase productivity and facilitate new forms of scholarship. For more information about JSTOR, please contact [email protected]. Taylor & Francis, Ltd. is collaborating with JSTOR to digitize, preserve and extend access to Rhetoric Review. http://www.jstor.org Brad McAdon University of Memphis Plato's Denunciation of Rhetoric in the Phaedrus Contrary to a prevailing view within rhetoric and composition circles thatfinds a positive view of rhetoric in the Phaedrus, / contend that Plato mockingly de nounces rhetoric in the Phaedrus.
    [Show full text]
  • The Role of Doxa in the Philosophical Pedagogy of Isocrates and Plato
    The Role of Doxa in the Philosophical Pedagogy of Isocrates and Plato This paper explores the function of doxa as a pedagogical and philosophical concept in the contemporary Greek authors Plato and Isocrates, with special attention to the relationship between epistēmē and doxa. The term doxa (‘notion, opinion, judgment’) derives from the verb dokew (‘to think, suppose, imagine’) (Held 117). By the time of Plato and Isocrates, doxa had acquired at least two different significations. In the political sphere it denoted an imprecise, secularized form of situational decision making, while in the philosophico-religious tradition it signified judgments about the world which could be true or false (Poulakos 2001: 66-67; Poulakos 2004: 44-48). To uncover the place of doxa in Isocrates’ thought and Plato’s, the paper begins with an examination of the different historical and theoretical associations of the term current at the time. Next, a comparison is made of the ways Isocrates and Plato use the concept of doxa within the broader context of their philosophy and pedagogy. Plato’s much-debated reference to Isocrates in the Phaedrus is examined briefly, with special attention to Howland 1937 and Brown and Coulter 1971. Plato’s understanding of doxa and its relation to epistēmē is elaborated through a close reading of The Republic Bk. 5, 471a-480a, with reference to several other dialogues (e.g. Theatetus 194b; Meno 97b-c; Gorgias 11-13). By drawing together Isocrates’ comments in the Antidosis (e.g. 183-84,271) and Against the Sophists (esp. 2-8,17-18), it is shown that Isocrates, unlike Plato, places doxa above epistēmē (cf.
    [Show full text]
  • Hypatia of Alexandria and Her Communities Cara Minardi Georgia State University
    Georgia State University ScholarWorks @ Georgia State University English Dissertations Department of English 5-7-2011 Re-Membering Ancient Women: Hypatia of Alexandria and her Communities Cara Minardi Georgia State University Follow this and additional works at: http://scholarworks.gsu.edu/english_diss Recommended Citation Minardi, Cara, "Re-Membering Ancient Women: Hypatia of Alexandria and her Communities." Dissertation, Georgia State University, 2011. http://scholarworks.gsu.edu/english_diss/67 This Dissertation is brought to you for free and open access by the Department of English at ScholarWorks @ Georgia State University. It has been accepted for inclusion in English Dissertations by an authorized administrator of ScholarWorks @ Georgia State University. For more information, please contact [email protected]. RE-MEMBERING ANCIENT WOMEN: HYPATIA OF ALEXANDRIA AND HER COMMUNITIES by Cara A. Minardi Under the Direction of Lynée Lewis Gaillet ABSTRACT Re-Membering Ancient Women: Hypatia of Alexandria and Her Communities is a recovery of Hypatia of Alexandria (355-415 ACE) as a skilled rhetorician and instructor of note who taught in Alexandria, Egypt. This work addresses Hypatia as a missing female figure from the history of rhetoric and follows the work of feminist historiographers in the field of Rhetoric and Composition including Andrea Lunsford, Jan Swearingen, Susan Jarratt, and Cheryl Glenn (among others) who note the exclusion of women from ancient schools of rhetoric, yet assert their participation in rhetorical activities. In its recovery of Hypatia, the work recreates the historical milieu of Roman Alexandria including Alexandria‟s ethnically and religiously diverse population. As a woman of Greco-Egyptian decent, Hypatia‟s public work was supported by Egyptian, Greek, and Roman legal and social customs that enabled her to lecture in public and private, administer her own school, and advise high-level political leaders.
    [Show full text]
  • Introduction
    Cambridge University Press 978-0-521-87863-0 - Plato on the Rhetoric of Philosophers and Sophists Marina McCoy Excerpt More information 1 Introduction I. This book explores how Plato separates the philosopher from the sophist through the dramatic opposition of Socrates torhetoricians and sophists. In one way, its thesis is simple. Plato distinguishes Socrates from the sophistsbydifferences in character and moral intention. In the broadest terms, Plato might agree with Aristotle’s claim in the Rhetoric that what defines a sophist is “not his faculty, but his moral purpose” (1355b 17– 18). In another way, the problem is difficult, for the philosopher and the sophist share many characteristicsinhowthey speak and act; these simi- larities are not superficial but go to the very heart of what Plato presentsas philosophy, sophistry, and rhetoric. The tendencyofcontemporary schol- arship has been to emphasize the distinctiveness of Socratic or Platonic philosophy in terms of a technical method separable from rhetoric.1 1 Commentators who have emphasized a technical method in Socrates’ or Plato’s thought in distinction from sophistry include Gregory Vlastos, Socratic Studies (Cambridge: Cam- bridge University Press, 1994); Terence Irwin, Plato’s Gorgias, translated withnotes (Oxford: Clarendon Press, 1979); Jacques Bailly, “What You Say, What You Believe, and What You Mean,” Ancient Philosophy 19 (1999): 65–76;Richard Robinson, Plato’s Earlier Dialectic (Oxford: Clarendon Press, 1953); and W. K. C. Guthrie, A History of Greek Phi- losophy, Volume IV: Plato the Man and His Dialogues, Earlier Period (Cambridge: Cambridge University Press, 1986). Guthrie emphasizes the differencebetween eristic and dialectic in Socrates’ thought but admits that Socrates often uses eristics to best his opponents.
    [Show full text]
  • 2L the Case Against Teaching Virtue for Pay Geoff Boute
    in The Sophists, ed. P.F. O’Grady (Duckworth, 2008) 21. The Caseagairust Teach.ing Virtue for pay purview of relativistic sophistry wherein virtue ought to be concervedas somethingartificial and subjective(a nomos).My stfigestion r. tt ut some_ thing natural 2l needstc.be acquiredorganicalv u"a'o"".; i;"g period time' whereas of somethingartificial might be constructe* ana conveyed much more easily.If the sophist seesviitue as artificial, he alsosees it as The Case against Teaching Virtue for Pay freely.and quickly distributabre for a fee. Finaily, I want to suggestthat there is a deeperphilosophicar argument that slggests,in a-way that GeoffBoute consistent is if not commensuratewith the foregoin!'corrrid"rutio.r.r,p..di- lections and prejudices, that forced attempts to suppry rhetorical skills to those not naturally disposeclto virtue, is seenby plato and lsocrates One point that scholars unfailingly make in talking about the sophists is have to monstrous results, resurts that harm both pupil and that they took pay for instruction.' Plato himself refers to the earnings of' sophistic teacheralike. The sophistwho must sacrificehis freeiom the sophists no less than thirty-one times (Harrison 1964, Ly accepting 191n.44). whoeverpays the fee also sacrificeshis soul. Xenophon and Aristotle also make frequent reference to the fact that tho sophists take pay. At his trial and elsewhere in Plato and Xenophon, it is emphasised that Socrates did not, and it would seem that the practice of' Culture, context and citizenship taking pay for teaching is regarded with a disdain meant to separate Somescholars have suggestedthat the invidiousremarks aboutteaching Socrates from the sophists.
    [Show full text]
  • A Cross-Disciplinary Study of Ancient Greek Kairos, Circa 3000–146 Bce
    FROM NATURE TO THE IDEAL: A CROSS-DISCIPLINARY STUDY OF ANCIENT GREEK KAIROS, CIRCA 3000–146 BCE A DISSERTATION SUBMITTED TO THE GRADUATE SCHOOL IN PARTIAL FULFILLMENT OF THE REQUIREMENTS FOR THE DEGREE DOCTOR OF PHILOSOPHY BY NICOLE RUTH CARDASSILARIS DISSERTATION ADVISOR: DR. PAUL W. RANIERI BALL STATE UNIVERSITY MUNCIE, INDIANA MAY 2019 To my intellectual DNA, and to my biological DNA, but especially to my son, Nicholas 2 CONTENTS PAGE Acknowledgements ………………………………………………………………… 4 List of Figures …………………………………………………………………….. 7 Chapter 1. Introduction …………………………………………………………….. 10 Chapter 2. Denotations and Connotations of Ancient Greek Kairos: A Review of Literature in Three Academic Disciplines ……………. 36 Chapter 3. Towards a Prehistory of Ancient Greek Kairos: What Constituted the Greeks’ Understanding of “a Moment in Time” between 3000-600 BCE? …………………………………………… 81 Chapter 4. The Expansion and Organization of Expression: Kairos in Transition, 800-400 BCE ………………………………… 124 Chapter 5. From Nature to Humankind: Framing the Conventional and Ideal Kairos, 400-146 BCE ……………………………………... 181 Chapter 6. Conclusion ……………………………………………………………….. 231 Bibliography …………………………………………………………………………. 245 3 ACKNOWLEDGEMENTS First I would like to thank the professors who sat on my dissertation committee. Thank you Professors Paul Ranieri (Rhetoric and Writing), Robert Habich (American Literature), Christine Shea (Classical Studies), and Richard King (Classical Studies). Robert Habich advised the approach and structure of my research, while providing expert feedback and expert advice for revisions. Christine Shea and Richard King advised on the sociocultural aspects of ancient Greece, Greek mythology, and various philological corrections and recommendations on translations of ancient Greek. I thank each one of you for your encouragement to complete this project. For my cross-disciplinary study of ancient Greek kairos, I feel fortunate for the cross- disciplinary make-up of my committee.
    [Show full text]
  • Of the Sophist in the Time After Plato. the Impact of Form Typology in Sophistic Teaching and Writing on Interdisciplinary Scholarly Work Ágora
    Ágora. Estudos Clássicos em debate ISSN: 0874-5498 [email protected] Universidade de Aveiro Portugal HAASE, FEE-ALEXANDRA Style and the ‘Idea’ of the Sophist in the Time after Plato. The Impact of Form Typology in Sophistic Teaching and Writing on Interdisciplinary Scholarly Work Ágora. Estudos Clássicos em debate, núm. 11, 2009, pp. 33-54 Universidade de Aveiro Aveiro, Portugal Available in: http://www.redalyc.org/articulo.oa?id=321027642003 How to cite Complete issue Scientific Information System More information about this article Network of Scientific Journals from Latin America, the Caribbean, Spain and Portugal Journal's homepage in redalyc.org Non-profit academic project, developed under the open access initiative Style and the ‘Idea’ of the Sophist in the Time after Plato. The Impact of Form Typology in Sophistic Teaching and Writing on Interdisciplinary Scholarly Work 1 FEE-ALEXANDRA HAASE University of Balamand Abstract: Sophists acted among the educated persons and scholars in the Mediterranean after the 1st Sophistic in many regards as a special and distinct group. Since many examples show that they acted not only as sophists, but also performed other activities, we will examine here several cases were we see similarities and differences between them and other groups of scholars. Our three basic questions ‘what, how and why did the sophists teach and write?’ we answer examining diachronically the major forms and genres of writings they produced (‘What’), the ‘How’ will be answered looking at their performance as a communicative activity beyond borders of contemporary disciplines, and the ‘Why’ we try to answer emphasizing the necessity of sophistical activity in the contemporary socialization and education of late antiquity.
    [Show full text]
  • Feminist Rhetorical Pedagogies for a Deliberative Democracy
    University of South Carolina Scholar Commons Theses and Dissertations Summer 2020 Reviving Rhetoric Through Conversation: Feminist Rhetorical Pedagogies for a Deliberative Democracy Sadie Suzanne Carr Follow this and additional works at: https://scholarcommons.sc.edu/etd Part of the English Language and Literature Commons Recommended Citation Carr, S. S.(2020). Reviving Rhetoric Through Conversation: Feminist Rhetorical Pedagogies for a Deliberative Democracy. (Master's thesis). Retrieved from https://scholarcommons.sc.edu/etd/6076 This Open Access Thesis is brought to you by Scholar Commons. It has been accepted for inclusion in Theses and Dissertations by an authorized administrator of Scholar Commons. For more information, please contact [email protected]. REVIVING RHETORIC THROUGH CONVERSATION: FEMINIST RHETORICAL PEDAGOGIES FOR A DELIBERATIVE DEMOCRACY by Sadie Suzanne Carr Bachelor of Arts Christopher Newport University, 2017 Submitted in Partial Fulfillment of the Requirements For the Degree of Master of Arts in English College of Arts and Sciences University of South Carolina 2020 Accepted by: Gina L. Ercolini, Director of Thesis Hannah J. Rule, Reader Cheryl L. Addy, Vice Provost and Dean of the Graduate School © Copyright by Sadie Carr, 2020 All Rights Reserved. ii ACKNOWLEDGEMENTS I would first like to thank my thesis advisor, Dr. Gina Ercolini of the English Department at the University of South Carolina. Dr. Ercolini’s patience, kindness, keen listening skills, and knowledge of rhetorical theory and practice were instrumental to the completion of this project. Her course on “medieval to modern rhetoric” helped me tie many of the loose ends of this project together, and I am so glad I was able to complete this journey under her guidance.
    [Show full text]
  • Of the Sophist in the Time After Plato. the Impact of Form Typology in Sophistic Teaching and Writing on Interdisciplinary Scholarly Work
    Style and the ‘Idea’ of the Sophist in the Time after Plato. The Impact of Form Typology in Sophistic Teaching and Writing on Interdisciplinary Scholarly Work 1 FEE-ALEXANDRA HAASE University of Balamand Abstract: Sophists acted among the educated persons and scholars in the Mediterranean after the 1st Sophistic in many regards as a special and distinct group. Since many examples show that they acted not only as sophists, but also performed other activities, we will examine here several cases were we see similarities and differences between them and other groups of scholars. Our three basic questions ‘what, how and why did the sophists teach and write?’ we answer examining diachronically the major forms and genres of writings they produced (‘What’), the ‘How’ will be answered looking at their performance as a communicative activity beyond borders of contemporary disciplines, and the ‘Why’ we try to answer emphasizing the necessity of sophistical activity in the contemporary socialization and education of late antiquity. Claiming that style was the idea of the sophists, we put Plato’s concept of ideas critically in the context of the concept of ideas derived from contemporary and later sophists focusing on the function of visuality from early sophistic works to the late antique era represented by Philostatus’ Imagines. Keywords: Rhetoric; Sophistry; Late Antiquity; Mediterranean; Style; Idea. Introduction: Idea and the Melting of Philosophy, Rhetoric, and Sophistry in Historical Examples Idea and form, even though occurring in literal context, belong to visual and theoretical phenomena. Recently, in studies of visual culture, also ancient cultures have become objects of interest in this relatively new branch.
    [Show full text]
  • Research and Experiment in Early Greek Thought by Tyler Mayo A
    Research and Experiment in Early Greek Thought by Tyler Mayo A dissertation submitted in partial fulfillment of the requirements for the degree of Doctor of Philosophy (Classical Studies) in the University of Michigan 2019 Doctoral Committee: Professor Francesca Schironi, Chair Professor Sara Ahbel-Rappe Professor Richard Janko Associate Professor Ian Moyer Tyler Edward Mayo [email protected] ORCID iD: 0000-0002-2442-7127 To my mother and father ii ACKNOWLEDGMENTS First, ad consuetudinem maiorum, I would like to begin by acknowledging and expressing my gratitude to the members of my committee: Professors Richard Janko, Ian Moyer, and Sara Abhel-Rappe. Their suggestions and criticisms helped me to rethink some, and alter other, points within this dissertation to its improvement, and saved me from numerous errors within the text, many of which surely still lurk within these pages and are my responsibility alone. However, I owe a special debt to my chair, Francesca Schironi, whose support not only made this dissertation possible, but who acted as a mentor throughout my entire time at Michigan. Her honesty and counsel were always welcome, and her careful philology can be seen within these pages, although I fear only as an imperfect reflection. Outside Angell Hall, others made my studies in Ann Arbor possible. The Posch family— John, Dyanna, Isabel, and most recently, Jude—acted as a family away from home, not least for their generous hospitality in boarding me. I shall always remember and cherish their ξενία. My wife Liz is certainly owed a place of honor in the beginning of this dissertation. Her support was essential in its creation as in all other things.
    [Show full text]