Panpsychism in the West

Total Page:16

File Type:pdf, Size:1020Kb

Panpsychism in the West Panpsychism in the West Panpsychism in the West David Skrbina A Bradford Book The MIT Press Cambridge, Massachusetts London, England © 2005 Massachusetts Institute of Technology All rights reserved. No part of this book may be reproduced in any form by any elec- tronic or mechanical means (including photocopying, recording, or information storage and retrieval) without permission in writing from the publisher. MIT Press books may be purchased at special quantity discounts for business or sales promotional use. For information, please email [email protected] or write to Special Sales Department, The MIT Press, 5 Cambridge Center, Cambridge, MA 02142. The author’s email address is [email protected]. Set in Stone by The MIT Press. Printed and bound in the United States of America. Library of Congress Cataloging-in-Publication Data Panpsychism in the West p. cm. ISBN 0-262-19522-4 (alk. paper) 1. Panpsychism—History. BD560.P35 2005 41–dc21 2004056687 10987654321 dedicated to all those who seek alternatives to the mechanistic worldview Contents Acknowledgments ix 1 Panpsychism and the Ontology of Mind 1 1.1 The Importance of Panpsychism 1 1.2 Basic Concepts in Ontology and Mind 5 1.3 Background on Monism 8 1.4 Dualism and Interaction 12 1.5 Panpsychism Defined 15 2 Ancient Origins 23 2.1 Ancient Greece and the “Hylozoist” Tradition—The Pre-Socratics 23 2.2 Plato 34 2.3 Aristotle 45 2.4 Epicurus and the Atomic Swerve 51 2.5 Stoicism and the Pneuma 53 2.6 Remnants of Panpsychism in the Early Christian Era 58 3 Developments in the Renaissance (Sixteenth- and Seventeenth- Century Europe) 65 3.1 Transition to the Renaissance 65 3.2 Four Italian Naturalists: Cardano, Telesio, Patrizi, and Bruno 67 3.3 Gilbert and the Soul of the Magnet 76 3.4 Campanella and the Seventeenth Century 77 3.5 The Early Scientific Philosophers 81 3.6 Spinoza 87 3.7 Locke and Newton 91 3.8 Leibniz 95 4 Continental Panpsychism of the Eighteenth Century 101 4.1 French Vitalistic Materialism 101 4.2 Kant and Priestley 108 4.3 German Romanticism and the Naturphilosophie 112 viii Contents 5 Panpsychism, Mechanism, and Science in Nineteenth-Century Germany 117 5.1 Schopenhauer 117 5.2 Fechner 122 5.3 Other Scientist-Philosophers of the Age 126 5.4 A Survey of the Field 133 5.5 Nietzsche and the Will to Power 137 6 The Anglo-American Perspective 141 6.1 Anglo-American Panpsychism of the Late Nineteenth Century 141 6.2 William James 145 6.3 Royce, Peirce, and Other Sympathetic Thinkers 149 7 Panpsychism in the Twentieth Century, Part I: 1900–1950 157 7.1 Bergson and the Early-Twentieth-Century Panpsychists 157 7.2 Schiller 162 7.3 Alexander, Lossky, Troland, and Dewey 165 7.4 The Process Philosophers—Whitehead and Russell 174 7.5 Phenomenology 180 7.6 Teilhard de Chardin 182 8 Scientific Perspectives 185 8.1 Historical Arguments from the Scientific and Empirical Perspectives 185 8.2 Panpsychism in Early- and Mid-Twentieth-Century Science 188 8.3 Bateson 196 8.4 Recent Scientific Interpretations 198 8.5 Bohm and the Implicate Order 202 9 Panpsychism in the Twentieth Century, Part II: 1950–Present 207 9.1 Hartshorne 208 9.2 Developments in the 1960s and the 1970s 217 9.3 Mind in Nature: Panpsychism and Environmental Philosophy 223 9.4 Recent Thoughts, Pro and Con 235 10 Toward a Panpsychist Worldview 249 10.1 An Assessment of the Arguments 249 10.2 Opposing Views 255 10.3 Into the Third Millennium 265 Notes 271 Bibliography 291 Index 307 Acknowledgments There are of course many individuals, present and past, to whom I owe inspiration and gratitude. Those deserving special mention include Peter Reason, Brian Goodwin, Alan Rayner, and Chris Clarke. They offered sub- stantial encouragement when my ideas and research were still a work in progress. I also want to particularly acknowledge my long-time colleague Ken Brady and another great friend, supporter, and peerless source of inspira- tion, Henryk Skolimowski. Panpsychism in the West 1 Panpsychism and the Ontology of Mind 1.1 The Importance of Panpsychism The nature of mind has been an enigma since the beginning of recorded history. In many ways it is as much a mystery today as it was to the ancient Greeks. We now know much more than the Greeks did about the brain and human physiology, and we have intricate and detailed philosophical con- cepts, and yet we seem unable to reach any kind of consensus on what mind is or how it is related to the body or to matter in general. The enig- matic nature of mind is so pervasive and compelling that some current philosophers have given up on the problem, calling it intractable or unsolv- able in principle. The difficulties surrounding mind seem, at the very least, to call for a deep reexamination of the problem. Most current theorists carry with them two basic assumptions: (1) that mind is limited to humans and perhaps the “higher animals” and (2) that mind is somehow dependent on or reducible to the physical substrate of the human brain. (Others go to the opposite extreme and hold that mind is really a soul, something distinct from the body and fundamentally nonphysical; I will put this view aside for the moment.) Point 1 is usually taken for granted and rarely argued for. Point 2 implies a belief that there is something fundamentally unique about human and animal brains, and that they alone among all the physical structures of the universe can support mental processes. This second point is conceivably true, but no one has given a plausible account of why this might be so. Certainly there are unique physical characteristics of the human brain (the number and density of neural cells, the modes of input for sensory information, and so on) that most likely account for our uniquely human mental capabilities: our abilities to reason, to experience rich emotions and feelings, and to hold beliefs. But we have found nothing so unique as to alone account for the presence of a mind. What is at issue 2 Chapter 1 is not the nature of the uniquely human mental capabilities, but rather a general understanding of the phenomenon of mind in its largest sense. Many thinkers, past and present, have seen fit to challenge the above two assumptions. On the basis of their investigations of the natural world, they have viewed such assumptions as largely unfounded. For such thinkers there is no reason to limit mind to humans and (perhaps) higher animals; in fact, they have reasons—both intuitive and rational—to claim that mind is best conceived as a general phenomenon of nature. As such, mind would exist, in some form, in all things. This concept is called panpsychism. Panpsychism, roughly speaking, is the view that all things have mind or a mind-like quality.1 It is an ancient concept, dating back to the earliest days of both Eastern and Western civilizations. The term ‘panpsychism’, intro- duced by the Italian philosopher Patrizi in the sixteenth century, derives from the Greek ‘pan’ (all) and ‘psyche’ (mind or soul). The theological impli- cations of soul are largely set aside in the present work; at issue is the notion of mind as a naturalistic aspect of reality. Panpsychist theories generally attempt to address the nature and classes of things that possess mind and, perhaps more important, to address what precisely one means by ‘mind’. These two issues—the nature of things and the nature of mind—are, of course, central to many aspects of philosophy. Panpsychism, however, lies at a unique intersection of the two concepts, where mind is seen as fundamental to the nature of existence and being. If all things have mind, then any theory of mind is necessarily a theory about ontology, about the nature of extant things. Panpsychism is distinctive in two further ways. First, it is a unique kind of theory of mind. More correctly, it is a meta- theory of mind. It is a statement about theories, not a theory in itself. As a meta-theory, it simply holds that, however one conceives of mind, such mind applies to all things. For example, one could be a “panpsychist dual- ist,” holding that some Supreme Being has granted a soul or a mind to all things. One could be a “panpsychist functionalist,” interpreting the func- tional role of every object as mind, even if such a role is only to gravitate or to resist pressure. One could argue for a “panpsychist identism” in which mind is identical to matter, or a “panpsychist reductive materialism” in which the mind of each thing is reducible to its physical states. In fact panpsychism can parallel almost every current theory of mind. Nearly every concept of mind can be extended to apply to all things, whether living or nonliving. The only theories not applicable are those that deny mind alto- gether and those that argue explicitly that, because of some unique physi- ology, only biological organisms, or only Homo sapiens, can possess mind. Panpsychism and the Ontology of Mind 3 Such theories, though, are rare and unconvincing. In order to qualify as a complete theory, a panpsychist outlook must be complemented by a posi- tive theory of mind that explicitly describes how mind is to be conceived and how it is connected to physical objects. Some philosophers have expressed an intuitive belief that all things have minds, or that all are ani- mate, but then neglected to specify in detail a conception of mind that fits within this broad framework.
Recommended publications
  • 210 the Genesis of Neo-Kantianism
    SYNTHESIS PHILOSOPHICA Book Reviews / Buchbesprechungen 61 (1/2016) pp. (207–220) 210 doi: 10.21464/sp31116 of his book is that the movement’s origins are to be found already in the 1790s, in the Frederick Charles Beiser works of Jakob Friedrich Fries, Johann Frie- drich Herbart, and Friedrich Eduard Beneke. They constitute “the lost tradition” which pre- The Genesis of served the “empiricist-psychological” side of Neo-Kantianism Kant’s thought, his dualisms, and things-in- themselves against the excessive speculative idealism of Fichte, Schelling, and Hegel who Oxford University Press, tried to rehabilitate the dogmatic rationalist Oxford 2014 metaphysics of Spinoza, Leibniz, and Wolff after Kant’s critical project. Frederick Charles Beiser, professor of phi- The first chapter of the first part (pp. 23–88) losophy at Syracuse University (USA) whose is concerned with the philosophy of Fries field of expertise is the modern German phi- who tried to base philosophy on empirical losophy, is one of the most erudite historians psychology, and epistemology on psychol- of philosophy today. His first book The Fate ogy which could recognize the synthetic a of Reason: German Philosophy from Kant priori but not prove it. His book Reinhold, to Fichte (1987) didn’t only present a fresh Fichte und Schelling (1803) saw the history account of German philosophy at the end of of philosophy after Kant as the “struggle of th the 18 century, but it also introduced a new rationalism to free itself from the limits of method of historical research. His more re- the critique”. In his political philosophy Fries cent works, starting with The German His- was an anti-Semite, but gave the leading role toricist Tradition (2011) until the most recent to public opinion which could correct even Weltschmerz: Pessimism in German Philoso- the ruler, although he encountered problems phy, 1860–1900 (2016), have focused on the in trying to reconcile his liberal views with th main currents of the 19 century German the social injustice that liberalism created.
    [Show full text]
  • HISTORY AS the ORGANON of PHILOSOPHY: a LINK BETWEEN the CRITICAL METHOD and the PHILOSOPHY of HISTORY Jacinto Páez
    HISTORY AS THE ORGANON OF PHILOSOPHY: A LINK BETWEEN THE CRITICAL METHOD AND THE PHILOSOPHY OF HISTORY Jacinto Páez Abstract: In recent years, the Neo-Kantian movement has received wide acknowledgment as the hidden origin of several contemporary philo- sophical discussions. This paper focuses on one specific Neo-Kantian topic; namely, the idea of history put forward by Wilhelm Windelband (1848–1915). Even though this topic could be seen as one of the better- known Neo-Kantianism themes, there are certain unnoticed elements in Windelband’s treatment of history that merit further discussion. While the texts in which Windelband deals with the logical problems of the historical sciences have been studied at length, other texts, those in which history is studied in connection with the problem of the philosophical method, have not. This paper argues that, for Windelband, history is not merely an object of epistemological reflection but rather a key component of transcendental philosophy. Introduction This paper analyzes one aspect of Wilhelm Windelband’s idea of history; namely, the claim that history serves as the proper organon for the system of philosophical knowledge. In addressing this topic I have two goals in mind. On the one hand, I aim to clarify Windelband’s conception of the relationship between philosophical research and historical thinking. On the other hand, I intend to explain how Windelband came to ascribe such a preponderant role to history. By doing so, I will develop a critique of the way in which this Neo-Kantian author is commonly interpreted, and, more importantly, I will set the grounds to assess Windelband’s original contribution to the understanding of the transcendental method.
    [Show full text]
  • 2. Edmund Husserl by Dermot Moran in Sebastian Luft and Søren Overgaard, Eds., the Routledge Companion to Phenomenology
    2. Edmund Husserl By Dermot Moran In Sebastian Luft and Søren Overgaard, eds., The Routledge Companion to Phenomenology. London & New York: Routledge, 2011, pp. 28-39. As the leading theoretician of phenomenology as a radical “science of sciences” and as the founder of the phenomenological movement, Edmund Husserl (1859-1938) was one of the most influential philosophers of the twentieth century. Among his innovations are his generalization of Brentano's conception of intentionality, his account of categorical intuition, the identification of the natural attitude, the application of the procedures of the epoché and the transcendental-phenomenological reduction, noetic-noematic analysis, and his conceptions of the horizon) habituality and the pre-given "lifeworld” (Lebenswelt), Husserl's earlier descriptive phenomenology developed into full-blown transcendental idealism after 1907, causing many of his followers (including Heidegger) to reject his account of transcendental subjectivity, Husserl was born into a middle-class assimilated Jewish family on April 8, 1859, in Prossnitz, Moravia, then part of the Austrian Empire. His father owned a draper's store, Edmund initially attended a local school, then the Leopoldstädter Realgymnasium in Vienna and the Deutsches Staatsgymnasium in Olmütz. He graduated in 1876, showing some promise in mathematics, and entered the University of Leipzig to study mathematics, physics, and astronomy. There he attended Wilhelm Wundt's (1832-1920) philosophy lectures, which made little impression. Another philosophy student, Thomas Masaryk (1850-1937), the Czech nationalist who later became the first President of Czechoslovakia, encouraged him to read the British empiricists and was also influential in converting Husserl to Protestantism. In 1878 Husserl moved to Berlin to study mathematics with the prominent mathematicians Karl Weierstrass (1815-97) and Leopold Kronecker (1823-91).
    [Show full text]
  • Zur Rolle Und Rezeption Von Friedrich Paulsen (1846–1908) Im Deutsch-Amerikanischen Kulturaustausch
    Transatlantische Netzwerke im Kaiserreich: Zur Rolle und Rezeption von Friedrich Paulsen (1846–1908) im deutsch-amerikanischen Kulturaustausch Von der Fakultät für Geistes‐ und Erziehungswissenschaften der Technischen Universität Carolo‐Wilhelmina zu Braunschweig zur Erlangung des Grades Doktorin der Philosophie (Dr. phil.), genehmigte Dissertation von Daniela Bartholome aus Bad Karlshafen Eingereicht am: 16.04.2012 Mündliche Prüfung am: 26.06.2012 Referent: Herr Prof. Dr. Andreas von Prondczynsky Korreferent: Herr Prof. Dr. Daniel Tröhler Druckjahr: 2012 Danksagung Zum Gelingen der vorliegenden Arbeit haben zahlreiche Kolleginnen und Kollegen, Freunde und meine Familie entscheidend beigetragen. Ihnen allen möchte ich von Herzen danken. Sie haben mich durch ihre Unterstützung und ihren fachlichen Rat immer wieder bestätigt und ermutigt, diese Arbeit anzufertigen. Mein besonderer Dank gilt meinem Doktorvater Prof. Dr. Andreas von Prondczynsky, der mir die Möglichkeit gab, bei ihm zu promovieren. Er hat mich in vielfältiger Weise und in allen Belangen gefördert. Des Weiteren danke ich herzlich Herrn Prof. Dr. Daniel Tröhler (Universität Luxemburg), der sich bereit erklärt hat, als Zweitgutachter tätig zu werden. Danken möchte ich ebenfalls meinem Kollegen Dr. Franz Hespe (Marburg) und den studentischen Hilfskräften – insbesondere Margarete Kabara – im DFG-Projekt „Im Zentrum von Kultur und Bildung, Wissenschaftspolitik und Bildungsreform: Fried- rich Paulsen (1846–1908)“, die mir durch ihre Unterstützung und durch zahlreiche Diskussionen Denkanstöße zu meinem Thema gaben. Auch den Mitarbeiterinnen und Mitarbeitern des Instituts für Erziehungswissenschaft der Technischen Universi- tät Braunschweig – insbesondere Dr. Kirsten Aust, Dr. Daniel Blömer, Dr. Gernot Herzer (jetzt Friedrich-Schiller-Universität Jena), Viktoria Gräbe, Dr. des. Susanne Kannenberg (jetzt AutoUni Wolfsburg) und Dr. Simone Kibler (jetzt Universitätsbib- liothek der TU Braunschweig), Vanessa Schardt und Katrin Strauß – gilt mein herz- lichster Dank.
    [Show full text]
  • The Neo-Kantians and the Polemic on the History of Philosophy
    ISSN 2083-1978 3(10)/2019 e-ISSN 2391-775X http://dx.doi.org/10.12775/szhf.2019.028 Jacinto Páez Universidad Diego Portales, Chile e-mail: [email protected] ORCID: 0000-0003-3623-5517 The Neo-Kantians and the Polemic on the History of Philosophy 1. Introduction The nineteenth century has been widely acknowledged as the age of his- tory. Through the label “historical century”, for instance, Friedrich Paulsen opposed his own epoch to the philosophical eighteenth century1. Through this sharp separation, Paulsen stressed not only the sudden ascent of his- tory to the dignity of science but also to the dislocation that history brought into philosophical endeavors. The novel science of history demanded a new set of tasks that philosophers should accomplish, such us the grounding of historical objectivity and the elucidation of its proper methodology. But in as much as this novelty gained an ever increasingly preponderance, an unavoidable question gained momentum: Should philosophy in the end be measured too by the standards of history? Or, using a term that has become 1 Friedrich Paulsen, Immanuel Kant. Sein Leben und seine Lehre (Stuttgart: Fromman, 1899), 402. 5 JACINTO PÁEZ popular, should philosophy be historicized? Under the light of this question the opposition acquired a different meaning. While the expression saeculum philosophicum synthesizes an epoch concerned towards atemporal rational truths, the expression saeculum historicum refers to a tendency towards the factual and ephemeral. And this tendency of course undercut philosophy’s traditional assumptions and pretensions. Even the association of the quest for the eternal with a specific moment in human history, with a specific century, is not more than a veiled but unavoidable recognition of the fragility of phi- losophical thinking.
    [Show full text]
  • The Grim Probity of Arthur Schopenhauer and Ferdinand Tönnies
    The grim probity of Arthur Schopenhauer and Ferdinand Tönnies by Niall Bond (Lyon) Introduction The influence of the philosophy of Arthur Schopenhauer (1788–1860) on the sociology of its founder in Germany, Ferdinand Tönnies (1855–1936) has been addressed but not exhaustively explored.1 Jürgen Zander points out that Tönnies was a link between Schopenhauerian philosophy and German sociology of the turn of the nineteenth to the twentieth century2, without scrutinizing the seams between the metaphysics and the ethics of Schopenhauer, on the one hand, and the psychological sociology of Tönnies on the other. Cornelius Bickel notes that Tönnies had received elements of his concept of will from Schopenhauer which point to the philosophical anthropology of the 1920s3, but points above all to Tönnies’ reservations regarding Schopenhauer, thus obscuring Schopenhauer’s essential influence. We propose a broader and deeper exploration of the issues raised by those publications, considering the fundamental importance of Schopenhauer for Tönnies’ intellectual development and scrutinizing the lan- guage of either philosopher to uncover their affinities. Tönnies had, after all, declared Schopenhauer to be the most important philosopher of the nineteenth century well before Tönnies engaged in the study of those authors who have been seen as seminal for his sociology – Thomas Hobbes, Baruch Spinoza, Au- guste Comte, Herbert Spencer, Adam Smith and Karl Marx. Tönnies was de- monstrably familiar with virtually all of Schopenhauer’s work, and the inspira- tion he drew from Schopenhauer’s reflections on ethics was equal to that from Schopenhauer’s writing on the “will”. We take note of a few shared biographical 1 My thanks to Professor Birnbacher for his support and Professor Koßler for his helpful com- ments.
    [Show full text]
  • Husserl's Later Thinking
    View metadata, citation and similar papers at core.ac.uk brought to you by CORE provided by Sydney eScholarship HUSSERL'S LATER THINKING CONVERGING INTO A PHILOSOPHY OF HISTORY OR THE THEME OF HISTORICAL CONSCIOUSNESS IN HUSSERL'S LATER WRITINGS ESPECIALLY IN THE CRISIS OF EUROPEAN SCIENCES by Paulus Ryanto A THESIS SUBMITTED IN FULFILMENT OF THE REQUIREMENT OF THE DEGREE OF DOCTOR OF PHILOSOPHY UNIVERSITY OF SYDNEY 2007 Dedication to My Wife Adriana Sri D. Sutosandjojo Acknowledgement It is with grateful heart that I am presenting this thesis to the Faculty of Arts of the University of Sydney. I am grateful for the encouragement that I have received especially from my mentor and thesis supervisor, Prof. Dr. Garry W. Trompf Professor in History of Ideas, The Head of the Department of Studies in Religion, Dr. Carole Cusaxk, and the professorial staff of the Department. And Dr. Christopher Hartney the postgrad. Co-ordinator. This thesis has a long history, I like also to acknowledge the past contributions of my professors at Duquesne University, Pittsburgh, PA., USA., especially Prof. Dr. John Scanlon, Prof. Dr. Robert Madden, both Husserl-scholars, who have led me meticulously into the skill of exegesis of Husserl's texts. Prof. Dr. Eleonora Holveck, another Husserl-scholar, the Head of the Graduate School of Philosophy at the time. My thanks is also due to Rev. Dr. David Smith, the Director of the Husserl Archives, at the Simon Silverman Phenomenology Center, at Duquesne University. Thanks also to the Society of the Missionaries of the Sacred Heart, for its concrete support for me pursuing my higher studies.
    [Show full text]
  • Anti-Education
    NEW YORK REVIEW BOOKS CLASSIC S ANTI-EDUCATION FRIEDRICH NIETZSCHE (1844-1900) was born in Ri:ickenbei Liitzen,a farmingtown outside of Leipzig, to a long line of Lutheran ministers. After his father'searly death froma brain disease, the familyrelocated to Naumburg an der Saale. Nietzsche attended the Schulpfortaboarding school, where he became enamored with the music of Richard Wagnerand the writings of the German Romantics, before going on to study at the Universities of Bonn and Leipzig. As a university student, Nietzsche gained a reputation as a classical philologist and discovered Arthur Schopenhauer's lhe Worldas Will and Representation,the "cadaverous perfume" of which would hang over him throughout his career. Aftera period of compulsory military service, Nietzsche was appointed to the facultyof the University of Basel at the age of twenty-four. He published his first book, lheBirth ofTragedy, in 1872, but his deteriorating health soon forcedhim to retire fromacademia. In the itinerant period that followed,Nietzsche completed his most influential works, including ThusSpoke Zarathustra (1883-85), Beyond Good and Evil (1886), and lheAntichrist (1888). He suffereda mental breakdown in Turin on January 3, 1889-purportedly at the sight of a horse being beaten by a coachman. Beforecollapsing, Nietzsche is said to have thrown his arms around the horse's neck to shield it fromthe whip. Three days later, he wrote in a letter to his mentor Jacob Burckhardt that he would rather be "a Basel Professonhan God." He was subsequently hospitalized, and lived the rest of his lifean invalid in the care of his mother and sister.
    [Show full text]
  • Chapter Written by Peter Andras Varga, Published in the Oxford
    Chapter written by Peter Andras Varga, published in The Oxford Handbook of the History of Phenomenology (edited by Dan Zahavi, 2018), reproduced in accordance with the Author Reuse and Self-Archiving policy of the Oxford University Press. Penultimate version self-archived in the institutional repository of the Hungarian Academy of Sciences. Distribution or reuse without prior permission from the publisher is strictly forbidden. Scientific use only! Early Husserl Peter Andras Varga 1 Biography and Historiography Edmund (Gustav Albrecht) Husserl was born on 18 April, 1859, to a secular Jewish family of merchants whose ancestors had been living in the Moravian town of Prossnitz (Prostějov, today in the Czech Republic) since at least the seventeenth century. His future wife, Malvine née Steinschneider was similarly a descendent of a traditional, though more observant, Jewish family of Prossnitz, being born in 1860 while her father served in the Transylvanian city of Klausenburg (Kolozsvár / Cluj Napoca, today in Romania) at the other end of the Habsburg Empire. Husserl’s family developed strong ties to Vienna, the de facto capital of the multi-ethnic empire, where Husserl’s mother, brothers and sister lived and died. It was also in Vienna that he and Malvine were baptised and married. It is thus not surprising that Vienna constituted a focal point of Husserl’s scientific formation. During his academic peregrination, Husserl attended the Universities of Leipzig (WS 1876 – WS 1877), Berlin (SS 1878 – WS 1880/1881), and Vienna (SS 1881 – WS 1881/82). Even though the majority Husserl’s studies were dedicated to mathematics and sciences (inter alia with Karl Weierstraß and Leopold Kronecker, the demigods of contemporaneous mathematics), he also attended philosophy courses given by Wilhem Wundt in Leipzig, as well as by Johann Eduard Erdmann, Moritz Lazarus and Friedrich Paulsen in Berlin.
    [Show full text]