Book Review: the Capitalist Revolution: Fifty Propositions About Prosperity, Equality, and Liberty

Total Page:16

File Type:pdf, Size:1020Kb

Book Review: the Capitalist Revolution: Fifty Propositions About Prosperity, Equality, and Liberty Craig Calhoun Book review: the capitalist revolution: fifty propositions about prosperity, equality, and liberty. by Peter Berger Article (Published version) (Refereed) Original citation: Calhoun, Craig (1988) Book review: the capitalist revolution: fifty propositions about prosperity, equality, and liberty. by Peter Berger. American journal of sociology, 94 (3). pp. 666-669. ISSN 0002-9602 © 1988 University of Chicago Press This version available at: http://eprints.lse.ac.uk/42196/ Available in LSE Research Online: November 2012 LSE has developed LSE Research Online so that users may access research output of the School. Copyright © and Moral Rights for the papers on this site are retained by the individual authors and/or other copyright owners. Users may download and/or print one copy of any article(s) in LSE Research Online to facilitate their private study or for non-commercial research. You may not engage in further distribution of the material or use it for any profit-making activities or any commercial gain. You may freely distribute the URL (http://eprints.lse.ac.uk) of the LSE Research Online website. The Capitalist Revolution: Fifty Propositions About Prosperity, Equality, and Liberty. by Peter Berger Review by: Craig Calhoun American Journal of Sociology, Vol. 94, No. 3 (Nov., 1988), pp. 666-669 Published by: The University of Chicago Press Stable URL: http://www.jstor.org/stable/2780265 . Accessed: 23/11/2012 11:57 Your use of the JSTOR archive indicates your acceptance of the Terms & Conditions of Use, available at . http://www.jstor.org/page/info/about/policies/terms.jsp . JSTOR is a not-for-profit service that helps scholars, researchers, and students discover, use, and build upon a wide range of content in a trusted digital archive. We use information technology and tools to increase productivity and facilitate new forms of scholarship. For more information about JSTOR, please contact [email protected]. The University of Chicago Press is collaborating with JSTOR to digitize, preserve and extend access to American Journal of Sociology. http://www.jstor.org This content downloaded by the authorized user from 192.168.52.66 on Fri, 23 Nov 2012 11:57:29 AM All use subject to JSTOR Terms and Conditions AmericanJournal of Sociology The CapitalistRevolution: Fifty Propositions about Prosperity, Equality, and Liberty. By Peter Berger. New York: Basic, 1986. Pp. v+272. $17.95. Craig Calhoun Universityof North Carolina-Chapel Hill My departmentchairman is a greatbeliever in Churchill'snotion that not to be a socialistwhen one is youngshows lack of heartbut stillto be one in middleage showslack ofbrain. He sees thisvindicated in thecareers of neoconservativessuch as Daniel Bell and SeymourMartin Lipset and looks eagerlyfor signs that I may soon followtheir lead. When Robert Heilbronner'sfavorable review of The CapitalistRevolution appeared in ContemporarySociology, he quicklysought me out to show me (as he believed) that anotherleftist had come to his senses. Only a few days later,I acceptedthis review assignment. I am pleased to reportthat one does not have to be conservativeto findmerit in eitherPeter Berger's book or capitalismitself. Karl Marx, of course,considered capitalism the mostadvanced, pro- gressiveeconomic system the world had ever seen (and managed to re- main both brilliantand a socialistwell past middle age). Peter Berger does not attemptto constructa theoryas completeas Marx's. Rather,he proposesto "adumbrate"an eventualtheory of capitalismby layingout and clarifying50 propositionsthat he believesare supportedby empirical work. Perhaps a thirdof Berger'spropositions need neithersurprise nor troublea Marxist:that industrialcapitalism has generatedthe greatest productivepower in human history(PROPOSITION 1) is bothwhat Marx claimed and what mostWestern Marxists would grant,I think,after 70 yearsof putativesocialism in the SovietUnion, EasternEurope, and the Third World. About anotherthird of Berger'spropositions cause more troubleto Marxistanalyses, though Marxists differ in the subtletyand success of theirresponses to these difficulties.Berger is rightthat ad- vanced industrialcapitalism has generated,and continuesto generate, the highestmaterial standard of living for large masses of people in humanhistory (PROPOSITION 5). Moreover,there has notappeared so far any clear trendtoward eitherrelative or absolute immiserationof the workingclass in capitalistsocieties, though levels of inequalityare cer- tainlyhigh. Some Marxists(and othercritics of capitalism)ignore the evidenceof this;others incorporate it intoconvoluted efforts to maintain orthodoxy;still othersrecognize that historyhas dealt tellingblows to certainof Marx's politicaland economicpredictions but has hardlyin- validated all of his criticaltheory of capitalism. Remarkably,Peter Bergershows littleawareness in this book of the wide rangeof analyseson the Left;Marxism is trivializedas a foilfor his procapitalistarguments. To exemplify"neo-Marxist" sociological studies of stratification,Berger uses a book by Cromptonand Gubbay, with a 666 This content downloaded by the authorized user from 192.168.52.66 on Fri, 23 Nov 2012 11:57:29 AM All use subject to JSTOR Terms and Conditions Book Reviews singlepassing reference to Poulantzasand no mentionof Wright.Ernest Mandel and ImmanuelWallerstein are not giventhe opportunityto in- formBerger's chapter devoted to demolishingdependency theory (though Wallersteinrates a citationless,substanceless mention; the omission is all the more remarkablegiven that Berger makes directclaims that anti- capitalisttheorists have ignoredthe success of East Asian capitalism, which both Mandel and Wallersteinhave addressed). Habermas is granteda footnoteof joint dismissalwith Daniel Bell as a sponsorof the idea (a myth,says Berger)of a legitimationcrisis in moderncapitalism. In general,Berger offers very weak citationsin supportof verystrong claims. It is pointlessto dwell on his arbitraryuse of the scholarlylitera- ture,however, for this book is not mainlyintended for scholars. Rather, it is the effortof a public intellectual(something I do in factthink it is good to be) to put forwardan essentiallypolitical argument that draws support(intellectual as well as rhetorical)from more genuinely scholarly work (includingsome of Berger'sown). It is morestylish and generally betterthan most of its socialist counterparts; intellectually serious Marxist theoryis veryseldom presented in any formother than the most academ- ically arcane. As a socialist,this book gives me a good deal to think about, and in Berger the neoconservativemovement finds a far more intellectuallyworthy representative than George Gilder. But as a sociolo- gist,I learned a good deal less fromThe CapitalistRevolution (though considerablymore than nothing) and foundit disconcertinghow oftenthe politicalpurpose of the book dominatedthe analytic.Although Berger is a muchbetter writer and thinker,the ratio of scholarshipand analysisto ideologyis moretypical of Szymanskithan of Wallerstein; Berger is more comparableto Proudhonthan to Marx. This bringsup thefinal third of Berger's 50 propositions,the ones I find dubious. Most are not so much wrong as predicatedon arbitraryor prejudgmentaldefinitions. In what he presentsas a fairand balanced, descriptivebut not evaluative, empiricalcomparison of capitalismand socialism,the latter term is restrictedto self-proclaimedcommunist coun- tries. On this basis, comparisonof the policies and practicalresults of socialistand capitalistgovernments in WesternEurope is excluded,and PROPOSITION 43 finds"an intrinsiclinkage betweensocialism and au- thoritariangovernance." Berger takes stateplanning as so integralto the idea of socialismthat he assertsthat "the term'market socialism' is not meaningfultheoretically-a societydominated by marketmechanisms would not usefullybe called socialist" (p. 174). In general,socialism versuscapitalism is takento be a matterof categorical,either/or distinc- tion, not a continuum.The FrankfurtSchool analysisof Soviet "state capitalism"and otherMarxist critiquesof "actuallyexisting socialism" are neglected. There are some othersurprising assertions. For example,Berger ap- parentlyconsiders Latin Americato be partof the"non-Western world": "It is worthnoting that, following the end ofdictatorial regimes in Spain, 667 This content downloaded by the authorized user from 192.168.52.66 on Fri, 23 Nov 2012 11:57:29 AM All use subject to JSTOR Terms and Conditions AmericanJournal of Sociology Portugal, and Greece, all the cases of non-democraticcapitalism are found (at the time of writing)in the non-Westernworld" (p. 82). Or, "capitalismis an economicsystem and nothingelse (bycontrast, socialism is a comprehensiveview of human society)"(p. 206). This quotationis part of Berger'seffort to explainwhy socialismis a powerfulmyth, while capitalismsuffers "mythic deprivation." Berger does not, however,consider the distinctionbetween mythic legitimation for the capitaliststatus quo (of which the contemporaryUnited States offersplenty of examples, starting with Horatio Alger stories) and mythic motivationfor adherence to a movementagainst the statusquo (where socialismmay indeedhave an edge). Similarly,Berger argues (familiarly) that"the socialist project in itselfcontains a totalitariantendency, since it necessarilyprecludes the autonomyof the economicsector of societyvis- a-vis the politicalstructure" (p. 84) but does notnote how the watersare muddiedby the tendencyof economicconsiderations to exertcontrolling
Recommended publications
  • Civil Disobedience
    Civil Disobedience Henry David Toreau Civil Disobedience Henry David Toreau Foreword by Connor Boyack Libertas Institute Salt Lake City, Utah Civil Disobedience Thoreau’s essay is out of copyright and in the public domain; this version is lightly edited for modernization. Supplemental essays are copyrighted by their respective authors and included with permission. The foreword is licensed under a Creative Commons Attribution- ShareAlike 3.0 Unported License. LIBERTAS PRESS 770 E. MAIN STREET, SUITE 255 LEHI, UT 84043 Civil Disobedience / Henry David Toreau — 1st ed. First printing, June 2014 Cover Design by Ben Jenkins Manufactured in the United States of America For bulk orders, send inquiries to: [email protected] ISBN-13: 978-0-9892912-3-1 dedicated to Edward Snowden for doing what was right “Te most foolish notion of all is the belief that everything is just which is found in the customs or laws of nations. Would that be true, even if these laws had been enacted by tyrants?” “What of the many deadly, the many pestilential statutes which nations put in force? Tese no more deserve to be called laws than the rules a band of robbers might pass in their assembly. For if ignorant and unskillful men have prescribed deadly poisons instead of healing drugs, these cannot possibly be called physicians’ prescriptions; neither in a nation can a statute of any sort be called a law, even though the nation, in spite of being a ruinous regulation, has accepted it.” —Cicero Foreword by Connor Boyack Americans know Henry David Thoreau as the author of Walden, a narrative published in 1854 detailing the author’s life at Walden Pond, on property owned by his friend Ralph Waldo Emerson near Concord, Massachusetts.
    [Show full text]
  • Socialism in Europe and the Russian Revolution India and the Contemporary World Society Ofthefuture
    Socialism in Europe and II the Russian Revolution Chapter 1 The Age of Social Change In the previous chapter you read about the powerful ideas of freedom and equality that circulated in Europe after the French Revolution. The French Revolution opened up the possibility of creating a dramatic change in the way in which society was structured. As you have read, before the eighteenth century society was broadly divided into estates and orders and it was the aristocracy and church which controlled economic and social power. Suddenly, after the revolution, it seemed possible to change this. In many parts of the world including Europe and Asia, new ideas about individual rights and who olution controlled social power began to be discussed. In India, Raja v Rammohan Roy and Derozio talked of the significance of the French Revolution, and many others debated the ideas of post-revolutionary Europe. The developments in the colonies, in turn, reshaped these ideas of societal change. ian Re ss Not everyone in Europe, however, wanted a complete transformation of society. Responses varied from those who accepted that some change was necessary but wished for a gradual shift, to those who wanted to restructure society radically. Some were ‘conservatives’, others were ‘liberals’ or ‘radicals’. What did these terms really mean in the context of the time? What separated these strands of politics and what linked them together? We must remember that these terms do not mean the same thing in all contexts or at all times. We will look briefly at some of the important political traditions of the nineteenth century, and see how they influenced change.
    [Show full text]
  • The Limits of Nonviolence in Arendt's 'Civil Disobedience'
    From Resistance to Revolution: The Limits of Nonviolence in Arendt’s ‘Civil Disobedience’ Caroline Ashcroft Queen Mary University of London [email protected] Abstract: Arendt’s work on civil disobedience sets out an optimistic portrayal of the possibilities of such forms of action in re-energizing the spirit of American politics in the late twentieth century. Civil disobedience should not simply be tolerated, she argued, but incorporated into the legal structure of the American political system. Her work is usually seen to promote an idea of civil disobedience that is thus bound to existing constitutional principles and essentially nonviolent. However, by looking at Arendt’s discussion and critique of various practices of civil disobedience in 1960s and 1970s America, specifically in relation to the nonviolence movement influenced by Martin Luther King, and on the other side, the more militant Black Power movement, a different idea of civil disobedience emerges. This paper argues that whilst, for Arendt, civil disobedience within America certainly possesses the constitutionally restorative potential she assigns to it, in a broader sense – theoretically, globally, and even in terms of alternative ideologies within America – her conception of civil disobedience is in itself neither necessarily constitutional, nor nonviolent. It is, instead, a form of revolutionary action, whose limits are set only by politics itself, and specifically, Arendt’s criterion of publicity. Keywords: Hannah Arendt, Civil Disobedience, America, Publicity, Martin Luther King, James Forman 1 From Resistance to Revolution: The Limits of Nonviolence in Arendt’s ‘Civil Disobedience’ 1. The Legitimacy of Civil Disobedience Hannah Arendt famously saw in civil disobedience a means by which to reenergize the American political system: to restore to it its original spirit through the political actions of the people.
    [Show full text]
  • Quong-Left-Libertarianism.Pdf
    The Journal of Political Philosophy: Volume 19, Number 1, 2011, pp. 64–89 Symposium: Ownership and Self-ownership Left-Libertarianism: Rawlsian Not Luck Egalitarian Jonathan Quong Politics, University of Manchester HAT should a theory of justice look like? Any successful answer to this Wquestion must find a way of incorporating and reconciling two moral ideas. The first is a particular conception of individual freedom: because we are agents with plans and projects, we should be accorded a sphere of liberty to protect us from being used as mere means for others’ ends. The second moral idea is that of equality: we are moral equals and as such justice requires either that we receive equal shares of something—of whatever it is that should be used as the metric of distributive justice—or else requires that unequal distributions can be justified in a manner that is consistent with the moral equality of persons. These twin ideas—liberty and equality—are things which no sound conception of justice can properly ignore. Thus, like most political philosophers, I take it as given that the correct conception of justice will be some form of liberal egalitarianism. A deep and difficult challenge for all liberal egalitarians is to determine how the twin values of freedom and equality can be reconciled within a single theory of distributive justice. Of the many attempts to achieve this reconciliation, left-libertarianism is one of the most attractive and compelling. By combining the libertarian commitment to full (or nearly full) self-ownership with an egalitarian principle for the ownership of natural resources, left- libertarians offer an account of justice that appears firmly committed both to individual liberty, and to an egalitarian view of how opportunities or advantages must be distributed.
    [Show full text]
  • 'Populism': Armenia's “Velvet Revolution”
    The Armenian Studies Program and the Institute of Slavic, East European, and Eurasian Studies present the 42nd Educator Outreach Conference Authoritarianism, Democratization, and ‘Populism’: Armenia’s “Velvet Revolution” in Perspective Saturday, May 1, 2021 Livestream on YouTube University of California, Berkeley From end March to early May 2018, a series of peaceful protests and demonstration led to the resignation of Prime Minister (PM) Serzh Sargsyan, whom the then ruling Republican Party he chaired had newly nominated for that office. Having completed his two terms as President, from 2008 to 2018, Serzh Sargsyan’s attempt to remain in power became obvious. This attempt also made it evident that the amended 2015 Constitution, which he had promoted to invigorate democratization by shifting power from the office of the President to the Parliament and the office of the Prime Minister, was merely a ploy to extend his rule. It was also the proverbial “last straw that broke the camel’s back.” A kleptocratic, semi-authoritarian regime that appeared to control all the levers of power and of the economy suddenly, and unexpectedly, collapsed. This regime change—which the leader of the protests and incoming new prime minister, Nikol Pashinyan, referred to as a “Velvet Revolution”—was peaceful, something unusual for a post-Soviet republic. Subsequent parliamentary elections brought to power a new generation, younger deputies mostly between the ages of twenty-five to forty. A similar generation change also characterized the formation of the government. Youth, however, also means inexperience as almost none of the new deputies and ministers had held any political position in the past.
    [Show full text]
  • Two Views of Civil Disobedience: Henry David Thoreau and Martin Luther King, Jr
    TWO VIEWS OF CIVIL DISOBEDIENCE: HENRY DAVID THOREAU AND MARTIN LUTHER KING, JR, A Monograph Presented to the Faculty of the School of Humanities Morehead State University In Partial Fulfillment of the Requirements for the Degree Master of Arts -i' by James Dewey Reeder June 1970 Accepted by the faculty of the School of Humanities, Morehead State University, in partial fulfillment of the requirements for the Master of Arts degree. Master' s Committee: ~)'· lc!f;;t Chairman '4}c ~' ~,<L" (iate) ACKNOWLEDGEMENT The author gratefully acknowledges the kind assistance 'I of the eminent Thoreauvian scholar Professor Walter R. i Harding, University Professor, State University Teachers\ I College, Geneseo, New York. Professor Harding suggested the use of numerous source materials necessary to the development and completion of this monograph. TABLE OF CONTENTS ACKNOWLEDGEMENT • • • • • • • • • • • • • • • • • • • CHAPTER I. INTRODUCTION • • • • • • • • • • • • • • • • 1 II. THE VIEW FROM CONCORD • I • • • • • • • • • • • 14 III. THE VIEW FROM BIRMINGHAM I • • • • • • • • • • 27 IV. I "ONE HONEST MAN" OR "WORLD HOUSE" • • • • • • 39 BIBLIOGRAPHY • •••••••••••••• I • • • • • • 43 I I CHAPTER I INTRODUCTION I Both Henry David Thoreau and Martin Luther King, Jr~, I believed in the power of civil disobedience as a form ofj justifiable protest against certain laws and functions of government. Both men practiced nonviolent resistance, aJd both were convinced of its workability, but there are distinctions in their ultimate objectives for its use. These distinctions relate primarily to the role of the . individual in society and his involvement with or detachment from the state. The subject of this monograph is to stud~ I . two views of civil disobedience, a subject which in itself I implies a divergence of opinion.
    [Show full text]
  • Rothbard's Time on the Left
    ROTHBARD'S TIME ON THE LEFT MURRAY ROTHBARD DEVOTED HIS life to the struggle for liberty, but, as anyone who has made a similar commitment realizes, it is never exactly clear how that devotion should translate into action. Conse- quently, Rothbard formed strategic alliances with widely different groups throughout his career. Perhaps the most intriguing of these alliances is the one Rothbard formed with the New Left in the rnid- 1960s, especially considering their antithetical economic views. So why would the most free market of free-market economists reach out to a gaggle of assorted socialists? By the early 1960s, Roth- bard saw the New Right, exemplified by National Review, as perpet- ually wedded to the Cold War, which would quickly turn exponen- tially hotter in Vietnam, and the state interventions that accompanied it, so he set out looking for new allies. In the New Left, Rothbard found a group of scholars who opposed the Cold War and political centralization, and possessed a mass following with high growth potential. For this opportunity, Rothbard was willing to set economics somewhat to the side and settle on common ground, and, while his cooperation with the New Left never altered or caused him to hide any of his foundational beliefs, Rothbard's rhetoric shifted distinctly leftward during this period. It should be noted at the outset that Rothbard's pro-peace stance followed a long tradition of individualist intellectuals. Writing in the early 1970s, Rothbard described the antiwar activities of turn-of-the- century economist William Graham Sumner and merchant Edward Atkinson during the American conquest of the Philippines, and noted: In taking this stand, Atkinson, Surnner, and their colleagues were not being "sports"; they were following an anti-war, anti-imperial- ist tradition as old as classical liberalism itself.
    [Show full text]
  • Camus, Albert. (1956) “Rebellion and Art [Excerpts].” the Rebel. New York: Vintage
    Camus, Albert. (1956) “Rebellion and Art [excerpts].” The Rebel. New York: Vintage. Art is the activity that exalts and denies simultaneously. "No artist tolerates reality," says Nietzsche. That is true, but no artist can get along without reality. Artistic creation is a demand for unity and a rejection of the world. But it rejects the world on account of what it lacks and in the name of what it sometimes is. Rebellion can be observed here in its pure state and in its original complexities. Thus art should give us a final perspective on the content of rebellion1. In every rebellion is to be found the metaphysical demand for unity, the impossibility of capturing it, and the construction of a substitute universe. Rebellion, from this point of view, is a fabricator of universes. This also defines art. The demands of rebellion are really, in part, aesthetic demands. All rebel thought, as we have seen, is expressed either in rhetoric or in a closed universe. The rhetoric of ramparts in Lucretius, the convents and isolated castles of Sade, the island or the lonely rock of the romantics, the solitary heights of Nietzsche, the primeval seas of Lautreamont, the parapets of Rimbaud, the terrifying castles of the surrealists, which spring up in a storm of flowers, the prison, the nation behind barbed wire, the concentration camps, the empire of free slaves, all illustrate, after their own fashion, the same need for coherence and unity. In these sealed worlds, man can reign and have knowledge at last. This tendency is common to all the arts.
    [Show full text]
  • What Revolutionary Socialism Means. by Carl D
    Thompson: What Revolutionary Socialism Means [Oct. 1903] 1 What Revolutionary Socialism Means. by Carl D. Thompson Published in The Vanguard [Green Bay, WI], v. 2, no. 2 (Oct. 1903), pp. 13- Socialism is not a reform, it is a revolution. And first of all, let it be clearly understood This is the position held by all scientific Socialists everywhere that by revolution Socialists do not everywhere. But such a statement made without mean violence or bloodshed. It is safe to say that explanation with a non-Socialist or in a lecture to every scientific Socialist in the world would re- an ordinary audience is certain to be misunder- gard it a calamity to the cause, as well as to hu- stood. When the word “revolution” is spoken the manity, to have a violent upheaval in society. The common run of people think of violence, future may see violence of bloodshed, of armies and navies. It does and war, as has the past. not matter what the “scientific” and “dic- Our present social prob- tionary” definition of the term is, common lem may involve this people don’t carry an unabridged dictio- nation and others in se- nary with them as a rule. To use the term rious trouble, but it is without explanation is to get one’s self and quite evident that if one’s cause seriously misunderstood. And such should be the case sometimes while listening to the speech of it would be not the re- Socialists one cannot but feel that they are sult of the teaching of not always entirely clear themselves as to Socialism, but rather the just what is meant by the expression “revo- result of the refusal of lutionary Socialism.” the rulers to accept the And yet we need some designation Socialistic program.
    [Show full text]
  • Civil Disobedience
    Page 1 of 2 Civil Disobedience June 21, 2014 World Focus FRANK SHATZ WILLIAMSBURG In the early 1960s, the United States was engaged in a global struggle for the hearts and minds of newly independent nations, particularly in Africa and Asia, and images of oppression coming out of Birmingham, Ala., caused our nation tremendous embarrassment. In response, on June 11, 1963, President John F. Kennedy delivered a televised civil rights address ± one of the most important speeches of his SUHVLGHQF\´ said Professor Davison Douglas, in an interview with the Gazette. 'RXJODVLVWKHGHDQRI:LOOLDPDQG0DU\¶s Law School and the Arthur B. Hanson professor of law. He is RQHWKHQDWLRQ¶s leading constitutional historians, an eminent scholar of civil rights law, and the author or co-author of seven books. He is not an ivory-tower scholar who perceives things only as they ought to be. He is a realist who analyzes events as they occur. ³,QP\YLHZWKe tipping point in the struggle for civil rights came when powerful groups, such as Congress and the president of the 8QLWHG6WDWHVHPEUDFHG0DUWLQ/XWKHU.LQJ¶s civil right goals, recognizing that progress on FLYLOULJKWVZDVLQWKHQDWLRQDOLQWHUHVW´KHVDLG ³King was able to use civil disobedience to appeal to the interest of certain Americans with the requisite power and influence to help facilitate racial change. This convergence of interest, more than anything else, accounts for his VXFFHVV´ According to a declaration by the Martin Luther King Jr. Center for Nonviolent Social Change, ³Civil disobedience is the active, public, conscientious breach of the law to bring about a change in law or public policy..
    [Show full text]
  • In the Shadow of Revolution: a Decade of Authoritarian Hardening in Azerbaijan*
    In the Shadow of Revolution: A Decade of Authoritarian Hardening in Azerbaijan* Cory Welt George Washington University [email protected] July 2014 WORKING PAPER * For citation as a working paper. 1 Over the last ten years, Azerbaijan’s ranking on the “democracy index” of the U.S.-based nongovernmental organization Freedom House has reflected the country’s slide from a “semi- consolidated” authoritarian regime to a “consolidated” authoritarian one.1 This change in regime type has not come suddenly. It has been the result of a gradual hardening of authoritarian governance since 2003, the year Ilham Aliyev became president. It might be difficult at first to grasp the significance of this shift in classification. Azerbaijan was hardly democratic under President Aliyev’s father, Heydar Aliyev, from 1993 to 2003. During the senior Aliyev’s rule, however, the regime allowed at least some freedom to civil society and media. Since then, the regime has become increasingly authoritarian across all indicators, but the collapse of space for nongovernmental forces to engage freely in the public sphere has been especially pronounced. Azerbaijan’s slide into consolidated authoritarianism has coincided with a decade of regime change from below in Azerbaijan’s two neighborhoods of post-Soviet Eurasia and the Middle East. From the color revolutions of 2003-2005 to the Arab Spring of 2010-2011 and Ukraine’s EuroMaidan of 2013-2014, the Azerbaijani government repeatedly has witnessed the fall of less consolidated authoritarian governments all around it. While it is difficult to determine precisely how much the power of these examples has contributed to Azerbaijan’s authoritarian hardening, a few connections are clear.
    [Show full text]
  • Anarchism: What It Really Stands For
    Emma Goldman, Anarchism and Other Essays (Third revised edition, New York: Mother Earth Publishing Association, 1917) ANARCHISM: WHAT IT REALLY STANDS FOR ANARCHY. Ever reviled, accursed, ne'er understood, Thou art the grisly terror of our age. "Wreck of all order," cry the multitude, "Art thou, and war and murder's endless rage." O, let them cry. To them that ne'er have striven The truth that lies behind a word to find, To them the word's right meaning was not given. They shall continue blind among the blind. But thou, O word, so clear, so strong, so pure, Thou sayest all which I for goal have taken. I give thee to the future! Thine secure When each at least unto himself shall waken. Comes it in sunshine? In the tempest's thrill? I cannot tell--but it the earth shall see! I am an Anarchist! Wherefore I will Not rule, and also ruled I will not be! JOHN HENRY MACKAY. THE history of human growth and development is at the same time the history of the terrible struggle of every new idea heralding the approach of a brighter dawn. In its tenacious hold on tradition, the Old has never hesitated to make use of the foulest and cruelest means to stay the advent of the New, in whatever form or period the latter may have asserted itself. Nor need we retrace our steps into the distant past to realize the enormity of opposition, difficulties, and hardships placed in the path of every progressive idea. The rack, the thumbscrew, and the knout are still with us; so are the convict's garb and the social wrath, all conspiring against the spirit that is serenely marching on.
    [Show full text]