Local Theory of Sets As a Foundation for Category Theory and Its Connection with the Zermelo–Fraenkel Set Theory

Total Page:16

File Type:pdf, Size:1020Kb

Local Theory of Sets As a Foundation for Category Theory and Its Connection with the Zermelo–Fraenkel Set Theory Journal of Mathematical Sciences, Vol. 138, No. 4, 2006 LOCAL THEORY OF SETS AS A FOUNDATION FOR CATEGORY THEORY AND ITS CONNECTION WITH THE ZERMELO–FRAENKEL SET THEORY V. K. Zakharov, E. I. Bunina, A. V. Mikhalev, and P. V. Andreev UDC 510.223, 512.581 CONTENTS Introduction..............................................5764 1. First-Order Theories and LTS ....................................5767 1.1. Language of first-order theories ................................5767 1.2. Deducibility in a first-order theory . ............................5768 1.3.Aninterpretationofafirst-ordertheoryinasettheory...................5770 2.LocalTheoryofSets.........................................5772 2.1.Properaxiomsandaxiomschemesofthelocaltheoryofsets................5772 2.2.Someconstructionsinthelocaltheoryofsets........................5775 3. Formalization of the Naive Category Theory within the Framework oftheLocalTheoryofSets.....................................5776 3.1.Definitionofalocalcategoryinthelocaltheoryofsets...................5776 3.2. Functors and natural transformations and the “category of categories” and the “category of functors” in the local theory of sets generated by them . ................5777 4. Zermelo–Fraenkel Set Theory and Mirimanov–von Neumann Sets ................5779 4.1.TheproperaxiomsandaxiomschemesoftheZFsettheory................5779 4.2.OrdinalsandcardinalsintheZFsettheory.........................5782 4.3.Mirimanov–vonNeumannsetsintheZFsettheory.....................5786 5. Universes, Ordinals, Cardinals, and Mirimanov–von Neumann Classes intheLocalTheoryofSets.....................................5791 5.1. The relativization of formulas of the LTS to universal classes. The interpretation of the ZF set theory in universal classes . ............................5791 5.2. The globalization of local constructions ............................5793 5.3.Ordinalsandcardinalsinthelocaltheoryofsets......................5795 5.4. Mirimanov–von Neumann classes in the local theory of sets and their connection with universal classes . ........................................5798 5.5. The structure of the assemblies of all universal classes and all inaccessible cardinals in the localtheoryofsets.......................................5801 6.RelativeConsistencybetweenLTSandtheZFTheory......................5803 6.1.AdditionalaxiomsoninaccessiblecardinalsintheZFtheory................5803 6.2. “Forks” of relative consistency . ................................5807 7.ProofofRelativeConsistencybytheMethodofAbstractInterpretation............5816 7.1.Abstractsofasettheory....................................5816 7.2.Theabstractinterpretationofafirst-ordertheoryinasettheory.............5817 8. Undeducibility of Some Axioms in LTS . ............................5818 8.1. The undeducibility of the axiom scheme of replacement . ................5818 Translated from Itogi Nauki i Tekhniki, Seriya Sovremennaya Matematika i Ee Prilozheniya. Tematicheskie Obzory. Vol. 119, Set Theory, 2004. 1072–3374/06/1384–5763 c 2006 Springer Science+Business Media, Inc. 5763 8.2.ThenondependenceofaxiomICUontheaxiomsoftheLTS................5826 8.3. Locally-minimal theory of sets . ................................5827 References . ............................................5828 Introduction The crises that arose in naive set theory at the beginning of the 20th century brought to the fore some strict axiomatic constructions of theories of mathematical totalities. The most widely used of them are the theory of sets in Zermelo–Fraenkel’s axiomatics (ZF) (see [23]) and the theory of classes and sets in von Neumann–Bernays–G¨odel’s axiomatics (NBG) (see [20] and [28]). These axiomatic theories eliminated all the known paradoxes of naive set theory at the expense of a sharp restriction on possible expressive means. At the same time, they provided an opportunity to include almost all the then existing mathematical objects and constructions within the framework of these theories. In 1945, a new mathematical notion of category was introduced by Eilenberg and MacLane in the initial paper [11]. From that time, category theory became an independent field of mathematics. But from the very beginning of its origin, category theory encountered the unpleasant circumstance that it did not fall not only within the framework of the theory of sets in Zermelo–Fraenkel’s axiomatics but even within the framework of the theory of classes and sets in von Neumann–Bernays–G¨odel’s axiomatics (NBG) (see [11]). For this reason, in 1959, in the paper [25], MacLane pose the general problem of constructing a new and more flexible axiomatic set theory that could serve as an adequate logical foundation for the whole naive category theory. Different variants of new axiomatic theories of mathematical totalities, adjusted for one or another need of category theory, were proposed by Ehresmann [10], Dedecker [9], Sonner [29], Grothendieck [14], da Costa ([6] and [7]), Isbell [18], MacLane ([26] and [27]), Feferman [12], Herrlich and Strecker [17], and others. Ehresmann, Dedecker, Sonner, and Grothendieck introduced an important notion of (categorical) uni- verse U, i. e., a totality of objects which satisfies the following properties of closedness: (1) X ∈ U ⇒ X ⊂ U (Ehresmann–Dedecker did not propose this property); (2) X ∈ U ⇒P(X), ∪X ∈ U; (3) X, Y ∈ U ⇒ X ∪ Y,{X, Y }, X, Y ,X × Y ∈ U; (4) X ∈ U ∧ (F ∈ U X ) ⇒ rng F ∈ U; (5) ω ∈ U (ω = {0, 1, 2,...} is here the set of all finite ordinal numbers). Within the framework of such a universe, it is possible to develop a quite rich category theory, in particular, the theory of categories with direct and inverse limits. To satisfy all needs of category theory, these authors proposed to strengthen the ZF or NBG set theories by the strong universality axiom pos- tulating that every set belongs to some universal set. In MacLane’s axiomatics, the existence of at least one universal set is postulated. Similar versions were proposed by Isbell and Feferman. Herlich–Srecker’s axiomatics dealt with objects of three types: sets, classes, and conglomerations. Within the framework of each of these axiomatics, some definitions of category and functor are given. But the notions of category given in [12, 17, 18, 26, 27] are not closed with respect to such important operations of naive category theory as the “category of categories” and the “category of functors” (see [16], 8.4). Within the framework of the axiomatic theories [9, 10, 14, 29] the definition of U-category, U-functor, and natural U-tranformation consisting of subsets of a universal set U is given. This notion of category is closed with respect to such operations as the V-category of U-categories and the V-category of U-functors, where V is some universal set containing the universal set U as an element. 5764 The axiomatics from [6] and [7] also give definitions of a category and a functor closed under the mentioned operations of naive category theory. But da Costa uses the logic with the nonconstructive rule of deduction ϕ(V1), ϕ(V2), ϕ(V3), ··· ∀tϕ(t), where V1,V2,...,Vn,... is an infinite sequence of constants, which denotes universes like the NBG-universe (see [7]). In connection with the logical difficulties of conctructing a set-theoretical foundation for the whole naive category theory, different attempts to construct purely arrow-axiomatic foundations were undertaken (see Lawvere [24], Blanc and Preller [2], and Blanc and Donadieux [3]). But in attempts at an arrow- axiomatic description of indexed categories and fiber categories, their own logical difficulties appeared (see [16], 8.4). Now let us consider more precisely what the formulation of MacLane’s problem mentioned above means. To do this, we need to have a strict definition of category. This definition became possible after the elementary (≡ first-order) category theories Tc took shape. There are many such theories, two-sorted and one-sorted (see, for example, [27, I.3, I.8], [16, 8.2], [30, 2.3, 11.1]). But for every set theory S, there exist canonical one-to-one correspondences between the totalities of models of these theories in the theory S. Therefore, for the strict definition of a category one can use any elementary theory Tc. According to the definition of Lawvere [24] (see also [16, 8.2]), a category in some set theory S is any model of the theory Tc in the S theory (see 1.3 below). The complete (partial) formalization of naive category theory C in the set theory S is an adequate translation of all (some) notions and constructions of naive category theory C into strict notions and constructions for categories (as models of the theory Tc) in the set theory S. Along with the notion of a category in the set theory S, there also exists the notion of abstract category in S.Anabstract category in the set theory S is any abstract model of the theory Tc in the set theory S (see 7.1. below). The complete (partial) abstract formalization of naive category theory C in the set theory S is an adequate translation of all (some) notions and constructions of naive category theory C into strict notions and constructions for abstract categories (as abstract models of the theory Tc) in the S set theory. According to these definitions abstract categories in the ZF set theory can be considered also on classes (as abstracts of the ZF theory), and abstract categories in the NBG set theory can be considered also on assemblies (as abstracts of the NBG theory). However, the complete abstract formalization of naive category theory C in any S set theory is impossible, because
Recommended publications
  • Notes on Set Theory, Part 2
    §11 Regular cardinals In what follows, κ , λ , µ , ν , ρ always denote cardinals. A cardinal κ is said to be regular if κ is infinite, and the union of fewer than κ sets, each of whose cardinality is less than κ , is of cardinality less than κ . In symbols: κ is regular if κ is infinite, and κ 〈 〉 ¡ κ for any set I with I ¡ < and any family Ai i∈I of sets such that Ai < ¤¦¥ £¢ κ for all i ∈ I , we have A ¡ < . i∈I i (Among finite cardinals, only 0 , 1 and 2 satisfy the displayed condition; it is not worth including these among the cardinals that we want to call "regular".) ℵ To see two examples, we know that 0 is regular: this is just to say that the union of finitely ℵ many finite sets is finite. We have also seen that 1 is regular: the meaning of this is that the union of countably many countable sets is countable. For future use, let us note the simple fact that the ordinal-least-upper-bound of any set of cardinals is a cardinal; for any set I , and cardinals λ for i∈I , lub λ is a cardinal. i i∈I i α Indeed, if α=lub λ , and β<α , then for some i∈I , β<λ . If we had β § , then by i∈I i i β λ ≤α β § λ λ < i , and Cantor-Bernstein, we would have i , contradicting the facts that i is β λ β α β ¨ α α a cardinal and < i .
    [Show full text]
  • Equivalents to the Axiom of Choice and Their Uses A
    EQUIVALENTS TO THE AXIOM OF CHOICE AND THEIR USES A Thesis Presented to The Faculty of the Department of Mathematics California State University, Los Angeles In Partial Fulfillment of the Requirements for the Degree Master of Science in Mathematics By James Szufu Yang c 2015 James Szufu Yang ALL RIGHTS RESERVED ii The thesis of James Szufu Yang is approved. Mike Krebs, Ph.D. Kristin Webster, Ph.D. Michael Hoffman, Ph.D., Committee Chair Grant Fraser, Ph.D., Department Chair California State University, Los Angeles June 2015 iii ABSTRACT Equivalents to the Axiom of Choice and Their Uses By James Szufu Yang In set theory, the Axiom of Choice (AC) was formulated in 1904 by Ernst Zermelo. It is an addition to the older Zermelo-Fraenkel (ZF) set theory. We call it Zermelo-Fraenkel set theory with the Axiom of Choice and abbreviate it as ZFC. This paper starts with an introduction to the foundations of ZFC set the- ory, which includes the Zermelo-Fraenkel axioms, partially ordered sets (posets), the Cartesian product, the Axiom of Choice, and their related proofs. It then intro- duces several equivalent forms of the Axiom of Choice and proves that they are all equivalent. In the end, equivalents to the Axiom of Choice are used to prove a few fundamental theorems in set theory, linear analysis, and abstract algebra. This paper is concluded by a brief review of the work in it, followed by a few points of interest for further study in mathematics and/or set theory. iv ACKNOWLEDGMENTS Between the two department requirements to complete a master's degree in mathematics − the comprehensive exams and a thesis, I really wanted to experience doing a research and writing a serious academic paper.
    [Show full text]
  • Abstract Consequence and Logics
    Abstract Consequence and Logics Essays in honor of Edelcio G. de Souza edited by Alexandre Costa-Leite Contents Introduction Alexandre Costa-Leite On Edelcio G. de Souza PART 1 Abstraction, unity and logic 3 Jean-Yves Beziau Logical structures from a model-theoretical viewpoint 17 Gerhard Schurz Universal translatability: optimality-based justification of (not necessarily) classical logic 37 Roderick Batchelor Abstract logic with vocables 67 Juliano Maranh~ao An abstract definition of normative system 79 Newton C. A. da Costa and Decio Krause Suppes predicate for classes of structures and the notion of transportability 99 Patr´ıciaDel Nero Velasco On a reconstruction of the valuation concept PART 2 Categories, logics and arithmetic 115 Vladimir L. Vasyukov Internal logic of the H − B topos 135 Marcelo E. Coniglio On categorial combination of logics 173 Walter Carnielli and David Fuenmayor Godel's¨ incompleteness theorems from a paraconsistent perspective 199 Edgar L. B. Almeida and Rodrigo A. Freire On existence in arithmetic PART 3 Non-classical inferences 221 Arnon Avron A note on semi-implication with negation 227 Diana Costa and Manuel A. Martins A roadmap of paraconsistent hybrid logics 243 H´erculesde Araujo Feitosa, Angela Pereira Rodrigues Moreira and Marcelo Reicher Soares A relational model for the logic of deduction 251 Andrew Schumann From pragmatic truths to emotional truths 263 Hilan Bensusan and Gregory Carneiro Paraconsistentization through antimonotonicity: towards a logic of supplement PART 4 Philosophy and history of logic 277 Diogo H. B. Dias Hans Hahn and the foundations of mathematics 289 Cassiano Terra Rodrigues A first survey of Charles S.
    [Show full text]
  • Axioms of Set Theory and Equivalents of Axiom of Choice Farighon Abdul Rahim Boise State University, [email protected]
    Boise State University ScholarWorks Mathematics Undergraduate Theses Department of Mathematics 5-2014 Axioms of Set Theory and Equivalents of Axiom of Choice Farighon Abdul Rahim Boise State University, [email protected] Follow this and additional works at: http://scholarworks.boisestate.edu/ math_undergraduate_theses Part of the Set Theory Commons Recommended Citation Rahim, Farighon Abdul, "Axioms of Set Theory and Equivalents of Axiom of Choice" (2014). Mathematics Undergraduate Theses. Paper 1. Axioms of Set Theory and Equivalents of Axiom of Choice Farighon Abdul Rahim Advisor: Samuel Coskey Boise State University May 2014 1 Introduction Sets are all around us. A bag of potato chips, for instance, is a set containing certain number of individual chip’s that are its elements. University is another example of a set with students as its elements. By elements, we mean members. But sets should not be confused as to what they really are. A daughter of a blacksmith is an element of a set that contains her mother, father, and her siblings. Then this set is an element of a set that contains all the other families that live in the nearby town. So a set itself can be an element of a bigger set. In mathematics, axiom is defined to be a rule or a statement that is accepted to be true regardless of having to prove it. In a sense, axioms are self evident. In set theory, we deal with sets. Each time we state an axiom, we will do so by considering sets. Example of the set containing the blacksmith family might make it seem as if sets are finite.
    [Show full text]
  • First-Order Logic in a Nutshell Syntax
    First-Order Logic in a Nutshell 27 numbers is empty, and hence cannot be a member of itself (otherwise, it would not be empty). Now, call a set x good if x is not a member of itself and let C be the col- lection of all sets which are good. Is C, as a set, good or not? If C is good, then C is not a member of itself, but since C contains all sets which are good, C is a member of C, a contradiction. Otherwise, if C is a member of itself, then C must be good, again a contradiction. In order to avoid this paradox we have to exclude the collec- tion C from being a set, but then, we have to give reasons why certain collections are sets and others are not. The axiomatic way to do this is described by Zermelo as follows: Starting with the historically grown Set Theory, one has to search for the principles required for the foundations of this mathematical discipline. In solving the problem we must, on the one hand, restrict these principles sufficiently to ex- clude all contradictions and, on the other hand, take them sufficiently wide to retain all the features of this theory. The principles, which are called axioms, will tell us how to get new sets from already existing ones. In fact, most of the axioms of Set Theory are constructive to some extent, i.e., they tell us how new sets are constructed from already existing ones and what elements they contain. However, before we state the axioms of Set Theory we would like to introduce informally the formal language in which these axioms will be formulated.
    [Show full text]
  • A Dictionary of PHILOSOPHICAL LOGIC
    a dictionary of a dictionary of PHILOSOPHICAL LOGIC This dictionary introduces undergraduate and graduate students PHILOSOPHICAL LOGIC in philosophy, mathematics, and computer science to the main problems and positions in philosophical logic. Coverage includes not only key figures, positions, terminology, and debates within philosophical logic itself, but issues in related, overlapping disciplines such as set theory and the philosophy of mathematics as well. Entries are extensively cross-referenced, so that each entry can be easily located within the context of wider debates, thereby providing a dictionary of a valuable reference both for tracking the connections between concepts within logic and for examining the manner in which these PHILOSOPHICAL LOGIC concepts are applied in other philosophical disciplines. Roy T. Cook is Assistant Professor in the Department of Philosophy at Roy T. Cook the University of Minnesota and an Associate Fellow at Arché, the Philosophical Research Centre for Logic, Language, Metaphysics and Epistemology at the University of St Andrews. He works primarily in the philosophy of logic, language, and mathematics, and has also Cook Roy T. published papers on seventeenth-century philosophy. ISBN 978 0 7486 2559 8 Edinburgh University Press E 22 George Square dinburgh Edinburgh EH8 9LF www.euppublishing.com Cover image: www.istockphoto.com Cover design: www.paulsmithdesign.com 1004 01 pages i-vi:Layout 1 16/2/09 15:18 Page i A DICTIONARY OF PHILOSOPHICAL LOGIC 1004 01 pages i-vi:Layout 1 16/2/09 15:18 Page ii Dedicated to my mother, Carol C. Cook, who made sure that I got to learn all this stuff, and to George Schumm, Stewart Shapiro, and Neil Tennant, who taught me much of it.
    [Show full text]
  • Logic of Paradoxes in Classical Set Theories
    Logic of Paradoxes in Classical Set Theories Boris Culinaˇ Department of Mathematics University of Applied Sciences Velika Gorica Zagrebaˇcka cesta 5, 10410 Velika Gorica, Croatia e-mail: [email protected] Logistic is not sterile; it engenders antinomies. H. Poincar´e Abstract According to Georg Cantor [Can83, Can99] a set is any multitude which can be thought of as one ("jedes Viele, welches sich als Eines denken l¨aßt”)without contradiction { a consistent multitude. Other multitudes are inconsistent or paradoxical. Set theoretical paradoxes have common root { lack of understanding why some multitudes are not sets. Why some multitudes of objects of thought cannot themselves be objects of thought? Moreover, it is a logical truth that such multitudes do exist. However we do not understand this logical truth so well as we understand, for example, the logical truth 8x x = x. In this paper we formulate a logical truth which we call the productivity principle. Bertrand Rusell [Rus06] was the first one to formulate this principle, but in a restricted form and with a different purpose. The principle explicates a logical mechanism that lies behind paradoxical multitudes, and is understandable as well as any simple logical truth. However, it does not explain the concept of set. It only sets logical bounds of the concept within the framework of the classical two valued 2 - language. The principle behaves as a logical regulator of any theory we formulate to explain and describe sets. It provides tools to identify paradoxical classes inside the theory. We show how the known paradoxical classes follow from the productivity principle and how the principle gives us a uniform way to generate new paradoxical classes.
    [Show full text]
  • Axioms and Models for an Extended Set Theory
    AXIOMS AND MODELS FOR AN EXTENDED SET THEORY ANDREAS BLASS AND D L CHILDS Abstract. We present the axioms of extended set theory (XST) and the ideas underlying the axioms. We also present an interpre- tation of XST in ZFC plus “there exist arbitrarily large inaccessible cardinals,” thereby proving the consistency of XST relative to this mild large-cardinal extension of ZFC. 1. Introduction This paper presents an extended set theory (XST) and proves its consistency relative to the classical Zermelo-Fraenkel set theory with the axiom of choice (ZFC) and an axiom asserting the existence of arbitrarily large inaccessible cardinals (also known as Grothendieck’s axiom of universes). The original motivation for this development of XST was to provide an improved, flexible mathematical foundation for certain constructions, like tuples and functions, that play important roles in computing. Subsequent developments revealed that XST also provides a smooth way of handling the set-class distinction that turns up especially in category theory. We shall comment on these matters in more detail after the axioms of XST have been introduced. The extended set theory XST differs from Zermelo-Fraenkel set the- ory ZFC in three major ways (and several minor ways). The biggest difference between XST and ZFC is that the fundamental membership relation of XST is a ternary relation, written x ∈s y and read “x is an element of y with scope s.” Most of the axioms of XST are analogs of traditional ZFC axioms, modified to account for membership scopes, and allowing atoms (also called urelements). This aspect of XST can be interpreted in ZFC quite straightforwardly.
    [Show full text]
  • Arxiv:2101.01698V4 [Math.LO] 16 Mar 2021
    Broad Infinity and Generation Principles Paul Blain Levy, University of Birmingham March 17, 2021 Abstract This paper introduces Broad Infinity, a new and arguably intuitive axiom scheme. It states that “broad numbers”, which are three-dimensional trees whose growth is controlled, form a set. If the Axiom of Choice is assumed, then Broad Infinity is equivalent to the Ord-is-Mahlo scheme: every closed unbounded class of ordinals contains a regular ordinal. Whereas the axiom of Infinity leads to generation principles for sets and fam- ilies and ordinals, Broad Infinity leads to more advanced versions of these prin- ciples. The paper relates these principles under various prior assumptions: the Axiom of Choice, the Law of Excluded Middle, and weaker assumptions. 1 Introduction 1.1 Summary of the Paper This paper has three main contributions: • To introduce a new axiom scheme, called Broad Infinity. • To show that Broad Infinity provides generation principles for families, and— provided the Axiom of Choice (AC) is assumed—for sets and ordinals. • To show that—again provided AC is assumed—Broad Infinity is equivalent to a previously studied principle called Ord-is-Mahlo [20, 39, 16]. arXiv:2101.01698v4 [math.LO] 16 Mar 2021 In the course of this introduction, we present the new axiom scheme (Section 1.4), and the generation priniciples for sets (Section 1.5), families (Section 1.6) and ordinals (Section 1.7). Section 1.8 explains the connection to Ord-is-Mahlo. Following the introduction, we come to the main part of the paper. It begins (Sec- tion 2) by formulating a base theory that is weak enough to let us track various as- sumptions in our proofs, such as the Law of Excluded Middle.
    [Show full text]
  • Logic and Set Theory
    Part II | Logic and Set Theory Based on lectures by I. B. Leader Notes taken by Dexter Chua Lent 2015 These notes are not endorsed by the lecturers, and I have modified them (often significantly) after lectures. They are nowhere near accurate representations of what was actually lectured, and in particular, all errors are almost surely mine. No specific prerequisites. Ordinals and cardinals Well-orderings and order-types. Examples of countable ordinals. Uncountable ordi- nals and Hartogs' lemma. Induction and recursion for ordinals. Ordinal arithmetic. Cardinals; the hierarchy of alephs. Cardinal arithmetic. [5] Posets and Zorn's lemma Partially ordered sets; Hasse diagrams, chains, maximal elements. Lattices and Boolean algebras. Complete and chain-complete posets; fixed-point theorems. The axiom of choice and Zorn's lemma. Applications of Zorn's lemma in mathematics. The well- ordering principle. [5] Propositional logic The propositional calculus. Semantic and syntactic entailment. The deduction and completeness theorems. Applications: compactness and decidability. [3] Predicate logic The predicate calculus with equality. Examples of first-order languages and theories. Statement of the completeness theorem; *sketch of proof*. The compactness theorem and the Lowenheim-Skolem theorems. Limitations of first-order logic. Model theory. [5] Set theory Set theory as a first-order theory; the axioms of ZF set theory. Transitive closures, epsilon-induction and epsilon-recursion. Well-founded relations. Mostowski's collapsing theorem. The rank function and the von Neumann hierarchy. [5] Consistency *Problems of consistency and independence* [1] 1 Contents II Logic and Set Theory Contents 0 Introduction 3 1 Propositional calculus 4 1.1 Propositions . .4 1.2 Semantic entailment .
    [Show full text]
  • MATH 320 SET THEORY Contents 0. Prelude 0.1. Some Historical
    MATH 320 SET THEORY BURAK KAYA Abstract. These are the lecture notes I used for a 14-week introductory set theory class I taught at the Department of Mathematics of Middle East Tech- nical University during Spring 2018. In order to determine the course content and prepare the lecture notes, I mainly used the textbook by Hrbacek and Jech [1], which I also listed as a supplementary resource for the course. Contents 0. Prelude 0.1. Some historical remarks. 0.2. The language of set theory and well-formed formulas 0.3. What are sets anyway? 0.4. Classes vs. Sets 0.5. Notational remarks 1. Some axioms of ZFC and their elementary consequences 1.1. And G said, \Let there be sets"; and there were sets. 1.2. Constructing more sets 2. From Pairs to Products 2.1. Relations 2.2. Functions 2.3. Products and sequences 2.4. To choose or not to choose 3. Equivalence Relations and Order Relations 3.1. Equivalence relations, partitions and transversals. 3.2. A Game of Thrones, Prisoners and Hats. 3.3. Order relations 3.4. Well-orders. 3.5. Well-founded relations and the Axiom of Foundation 4. Natural Numbers 4.1. The construction of the set of natural numbers 4.2. Arithmetic on the set of natural numbers 5. Equinumerosity 5.1. Finite sets 5.2. To infinity and beyond 6. Construction of various number systems 6.1. Integers 6.2. Rational numbers 6.3. Real numbers 7. Ordinal numbers 7.1. How do the ordinals look like? BURAK KAYA 7.2.
    [Show full text]
  • Codomain from Wikipedia, the Free Encyclopedia Contents
    Codomain From Wikipedia, the free encyclopedia Contents 1 Algebra of sets 1 1.1 Fundamentals ............................................. 1 1.2 The fundamental laws of set algebra .................................. 1 1.3 The principle of duality ........................................ 2 1.4 Some additional laws for unions and intersections .......................... 2 1.5 Some additional laws for complements ................................ 3 1.6 The algebra of inclusion ........................................ 3 1.7 The algebra of relative complements ................................. 4 1.8 See also ................................................ 5 1.9 References ............................................... 5 1.10 External links ............................................. 5 2 Axiom of choice 6 2.1 Statement ............................................... 6 2.1.1 Nomenclature ZF, AC, and ZFC ............................... 7 2.1.2 Variants ............................................ 7 2.1.3 Restriction to finite sets .................................... 7 2.2 Usage ................................................. 8 2.3 Examples ............................................... 8 2.4 Criticism and acceptance ....................................... 8 2.5 In constructive mathematics ..................................... 9 2.6 Independence ............................................. 10 2.7 Stronger axioms ............................................ 10 2.8 Equivalents .............................................. 10 2.8.1 Category
    [Show full text]