The Lawmaking Power of the Federal Courts

Total Page:16

File Type:pdf, Size:1020Kb

The Lawmaking Power of the Federal Courts Pace Law Review Volume 12 Issue 2 Spring 1992 Article 3 April 1992 The Lawmaking Power of the Federal Courts Larry Kramer Follow this and additional works at: https://digitalcommons.pace.edu/plr Recommended Citation Larry Kramer, The Lawmaking Power of the Federal Courts, 12 Pace L. Rev. 263 (1992) Available at: https://digitalcommons.pace.edu/plr/vol12/iss2/3 This Article is brought to you for free and open access by the School of Law at DigitalCommons@Pace. It has been accepted for inclusion in Pace Law Review by an authorized administrator of DigitalCommons@Pace. For more information, please contact [email protected]. The Lawmaking Power of the Federal Courts Larry Kramer* My only previous encounter with the subject of federal com- mon law was casual: before beginning a clerkship with Henry Friendly, I made it a point to read his academic writings, includ- ing the deservedly famous In Praise of Erie.' My preliminary thoughts on the subject therefore began where the Judge's left off, which is to say with the idea that federal common law repre- sents a "centripetal tool incalculably useful to our federal sys- tem" and that, while we may have not yet achieved the best of all possible worlds with respect to the relationship between state and federal law, "the combination of Erie with Clearfield and Lincoln Mills has brought us to a far, far better one than we have ever known before." 2 At first, I just assumed that this must be correct. Judge Friendly was seldom wrong about such mat- ters, particularly when consideration of a problem led him to a judgment contrary to his naturally conservative tendencies re- specting federal jurisdiction. Imagine my suprise, then, to discover that Judge Friendly's belief in a sweeping power to make federal common law is any- * Professor of Law, University of Michigan Law School. Presented to the Federal Courts Section at the 1992 Meeting of the American Association of Law Schools. Having never written a word about federal common law, I was somewhat surprised when Don Doernberg invited me to join this panel (though it did cross my mind that he may have asked me precisely because I have never written on the subject). I agreed to participate for the same reason I have never written on federal common law, which is that I have never really thought about the problem much. And since I have often thought that I should think about it, the occasion provided a good excuse. I am grateful to participants for their comments. I am also grateful to Craig Allison, Akhil Amar, Lee Bollinger, Erwin Chemerinsky, Steven Croley, Heidi Feldman, Barry Friedman, Steve Gilles, Don Herzog, James Hopenfeld, Jeffrey Lehman, Lawrence Lessig, Angela Luera, Daniel Meltzer, Tom Merrill, Geoffrey Miller, Richard Pildes, Richard Posner, and Terrance Sandalow for reading and commenting on an earlier draft. 1. Henry J. Friendly, In Praise of Erie - And of the New Federal Common Law, 39 N.Y.U. L. REV. 383 (1964), reprinted in H. J. FRIENDLY, BENCHMARKS 155 (1967). 2. FRIENDLY, supra note 1, at 194-95. 1 PACE LAW REVIEW [Vol. 12:263 thing but uncontroversial. While he has a few fellow travel- lers - including Martha Field on this panel s - the journals are filled with articles questioning the legitimacy of even very conventional forms of federal common law. Martin Redish mounts the most extreme attack, arguing that the whole notion of lawmaking by federal judges is contrary to the principles on which the nation was founded." To be sure, Redish relies pri- marily on the Rules of Decision Act,' but the gist of his critique is that basic policy choices must be made by politically account- able actors,6 and federal common law violates that prescription even without a specific statutory prohibition. Tom Merrill, George Brown, and Don Doernberg take less extreme positions, but still treat federal common law as something questionable that ought to be circumscribed more narrowly than Judge Friendly believed or than has been true in practice.7 These arguments puzzled me. Could a practice so well es- tablished and so apparently useful really be illegitimate? On the 3. See Martha A. Field, Sources of Law: The Scope of Federal Common Law, 99 HARV. L. REV. 883 (1986). Louise Weinberg has also written in defense of an even broader federal common lawmaking power. See Louise Weinberg, Federal Common Law, 83 Nw. U. L. REV. 805 (1989). 4. See MARTIN H. REDISH, THE FEDERAL COURTS IN THE POLITICAL ORDER: JUDICIAL JURISDICTION AND AMERICAN POLITICAL THEORY 29-46 (1991). (Much of the chapter on federal common law was published earlier in Martin H. Redish, Federal Common Law, Political Legitimacy, and the Interpretive Process: An "Institutionalist"Perspective, 83 Nw. U. L. REV. 761 (1989)). 5. According to Redish, the Act's plain language prohibits federal judge-made law. REDISH, supra note 4, at 30. Other commentators disagree, finding the statute (especially its obscure reference at the end to cases "where they apply") anything but plain. Indeed, the consensus seems to be that the Rules of Decision Act does not limit federal common law. See, e.g., Peter Westen & Jeffrey S. Lehman, Is There Life for Erie After the Death of Diversity?, 78 MICH. L. REV. 311, 364-77 (1980); Weinberg, supra note 3, at 818-19. This apparently is also the view of the Supreme Court, which has studiously ignored the Act in its common law decisions. See, e.g., Boyle v. United Technologies Corp., 487 U.S. 500 (1988). Consequently, while debating how to read the Rules of Decision Act might be interesting, I do not propose to do so in this paper, but will instead limit myself to exploring the scope of the federal courts' constitutional powers to make common law. 6. REDISH, supra note 4, at 9-10. 7. See George D. Brown, Federal Common Law and the Role of the Federal Courts in Private Adjudication - A (New) Erie Problem?, 12 PACE L. REV. 229 (1992); George D. Brown, Of Activism and Erie - The Implication Doctrine's Implications for the Nature and Role of the Federal Courts, 69 IOWA L. REV. 617 (1984); Donald L. Doernberg, Judicial Chameleons in the "New Erie" Canal, 1990 UTAH L. REV. 759; Thomas Merrill, The Judicial Prerogative,12 PACE L. REV. 327 (1992); Thomas Merrill, The Common Law Powers of Federal Courts, 52 U. CHI. L. REV. i (1985). https://digitalcommons.pace.edu/plr/vol12/iss2/3 2 1992] FEDERAL COURTS SYMPOSIUM other hand, how does one justify letting federal courts make law? Here I found myself less than completely satisfied with proponents of federal common law. Professors Field and Wein- berg have made worthy contributions, but their articles rely on the fact that federal courts already engage in the practice with- out explaining why this has normative significance or should be permitted. Yet if longstanding practice alone justifies judicial lawmaking, Erie itself was wrongly decided, for one thing about the Swift doctrine that nobody doubted was that it was well established. Accordingly, in these brief comments I propose to consider the arguments for and against recognizing a broad constitutional power to make federal common law. There is, of course, a lot more to debate than whether the Constitution permits federal courts to make common law. After all, having a power does not require using it. (Congress has never come close to exercising all of its power under the Constitution.) So it does not automati- cally follow that federal courts should fashion federal common law whenever they can. But that raises questions of expediency and good policy - questions to be worked out in particular contexts and through give and take with the other branches of government. Here I wish only to describe and defend a fairly broad (though not limitless) conception of the lawmaking power of the federal courts, and in this way, hopefully, to refocus de- bate on the policy questions. I. The Benefits of Common Lawmaking The first thing we need to consider is why giving courts the power to make common law might be a good thing. To begin, then, put aside questions of federal versus state law and con- sider a more fundamental question: why let courts make com- mon law at all? Governance on a large scale requires establishing institutions to administer law and justice. The people create a government and give it sovereignty, by which I mean simply the power to make and enforce laws. In conferring this power, the 8. Talk about "the people" establishing a government is neither historically nor de- scriptively accurate, even in the United States. It is, rather, a rhetorical device that cap- tures our understanding of popular control as the basis for governmental legitimacy. I follow the convention here because nothing in this brief description turns on the details 3 PACE LAW REVIEW [Vol. 12:263 people must choose areas over which their government shall have authority. It is possible to give government unrestricted power to make rules respecting any and all spheres of life. How- ever, it is also possible to limit the areas in which government can act, preserving some matters for governance by private or non-governmental institutions. In addition, the people must al- locate whatever authority they give their government among its various departments. Indeed, establishing clear lines of author- ity is essential if government is to function properly and work for the citizenry rather than waste its time bickering about who is authorized to do what.9 (This aspect of separation of powers is often overlooked because of our excessive focus on separation as a means of preventing undue concentrations of power.) In democratic societies, formal authority to make law is typ- ically vested in representative bodies whose members are chosen by some form of popular mandate.
Recommended publications
  • Discontinuity and European Lawmaking – Another Deficit of EU
    Discontinuity: Another Source for the EU’s Democratic Deficit? Thomas König [email protected] Abstract: This study evaluates discontinuity that is induced by the two-stage lawmaking process of EU directives and discussed in the jurisprudential literature as another source for the EU’s democratic deficit. While directives must be transposed into national law, their lengthy transposition period has raised the normative question about the extent to which governments of today can politically and reliably commit domestic majorities of tomorrow. From a political science perspective, this jack-in-the-box-effect is particularly critical in systems with restrictive voting procedures and high agency loss because the parliamentary principal is unable to learn about the behaviour of the governmental agent and can hardly change or amend the decision of the former government. Hence, the empirical task is to identify the potential for discontinuity in EU lawmaking which requires measuring the governmental activities in the implementation process and to compare the preferences of the former and current majorities. This is the first study which empirically analyzes the potential of discontinuity by combining statistics on the implementation process in the 15 member states with preference indicators for their governments over a period of almost 20 years. The findings reveal that parliaments are almost excluded from this process. On closer inspection, the results show that the preferences of the former and the newly elected representatives differ drastically in about one third of all cases, in particular in Austria, Denmark, France, Sweden – and to a lesser extent – in Ireland, Greece and Luxembourg where public support for European integration has also notably decreased in recent years.
    [Show full text]
  • Due Process of Lawmaking Hans A
    Nebraska Law Review Volume 55 | Issue 2 Article 3 1975 Due Process of Lawmaking Hans A. Linde University of Oregon School of Law Follow this and additional works at: https://digitalcommons.unl.edu/nlr Recommended Citation Hans A. Linde, Due Process of Lawmaking, 55 Neb. L. Rev. 197 (1976) Available at: https://digitalcommons.unl.edu/nlr/vol55/iss2/3 This Article is brought to you for free and open access by the Law, College of at DigitalCommons@University of Nebraska - Lincoln. It has been accepted for inclusion in Nebraska Law Review by an authorized administrator of DigitalCommons@University of Nebraska - Lincoln. 197 By Hans A. Linde* Due Process Of Lawmaking I. INTRODUCTION When Edward S. Corwin wrote in the 1920s about the practice of American courts to review the substance of legislation, a topic which then occupied center stage in constitutional law, he prefaced one of his articles with this quotation from Mr. Justice Holmes: "Theory is the most important part of the dogma of the law, as the architect is the most important man who takes part in the build­ ing of a house."1 I have seized upon this quotation in anticipatory self-defense, specifically defense against that much more famous quotation from Holmes that the life of the law has not been logic but experience;2 for we are returning, a half-century later, to the same topic-the revival of substantive judicial review of legislation -and what we shall discuss will have more to do with the role of logic in the life of the law than with experience.
    [Show full text]
  • “Legislature” and the Elections Clause
    Copyright 2015 by Michael T. Morley Vol. 109 Northwestern University Law Review THE INTRATEXTUAL INDEPENDENT “LEGISLATURE” AND THE ELECTIONS CLAUSE Michael T. Morley* INTRODUCTION The Elections Clause of the U.S. Constitution is the Swiss army knife of federal election law. Ensconced in Article I, it provides, “The Times, Places and Manner of holding Elections for Senators and Representatives, shall be prescribed in each State by the Legislature thereof; but the Congress may at any time by Law make or alter such Regulations.”1 Its Article II analogue, the Presidential Electors Clause, similarly specifies that “[e]ach State shall appoint, in such Manner as the Legislature thereof may direct, a Number of Electors” to select the President.2 The concise language of these clauses performs a surprisingly wide range of functions implicating numerous doctrines and fields beyond voting rights, including statutory interpretation,3 state separation of powers and other issues of state constitutional law,4 federal court deference to state-court rulings,5 administrative discretion,6 and preemption.7 * Assistant Professor, Barry University School of Law. Climenko Fellow and Lecturer on Law, Harvard Law School, 2012–14; J.D., Yale Law School, 2003; A.B., Princeton University, 2000. Special thanks to Dr. Ryan Greenwood of the University of Minnesota Law Library, as well as Louis Rosen of the Barry Law School library, for their invaluable assistance in locating historical sources. I also am grateful to Terri Day, Dean Leticia Diaz, Frederick B. Jonassen, Derek Muller, Eang Ngov, Richard Re, Seth Tillman, and Franita Tolson for their comments and suggestions. I was invited to present some of the arguments from this Article in an amicus brief on behalf of the Coolidge-Reagan Foundation in Arizona State Legislature v.
    [Show full text]
  • Civics and Economics CE.6 Study Guide
    HISTORY AND SOCIAL SCIENCE STANDARDS OF LEARNING • Prepares the annual budget for congressional action CURRICULUM FRAMEWORK 2008 (NEW) Reformatted version created by SOLpass • Appoints cabinet officers, ambassadors, and federal judges www.solpass.org Civics and Economics • Administers the federal bureaucracy The judicial branch CE.6 Study Guide • Consists of the federal courts, including the Supreme Court, the highest court in the land • The Supreme Court exercises the power of judicial review. • The federal courts try cases involving federal law and questions involving interpretation of the Constitution of the United States. STANDARD CE.6A -- NATIONAL GOVERNMENT STRUCTURE The structure and powers of the national government. The Constitution of the United States defines the structure and powers of the national government. The powers held by government are divided between the national government in Washington, D.C., and the governments of the 50 states. What is the structure of the national government as set out in the United States Constitution? STANDARD CE.6B What are the powers of the national government? -- SEPARATION OF POWERS Legislative, executive, and judicial powers of the national government are distributed among three distinct and independent branches of government. The principle of separation of powers and the operation of checks and balances. The legislative branch • Consists of the Congress, a bicameral legislature The powers of the national government are separated consisting of the House of Representatives (435 among three
    [Show full text]
  • A Critical Introduction to International Criminal Law
    Downloaded from https://www.cambridge.org/core. IP address: 170.106.40.219, on 28 Sep 2021 at 17:55:18, subject to the Cambridge Core terms of use, available at https://www.cambridge.org/core/terms. https://www.cambridge.org/core/product/EFEDBED0B84359DFA281A9079047846F Downloaded from https://www.cambridge.org/core. IP address: 170.106.40.219, on 28 Sep 2021 at 17:55:18, subject to the Cambridge Core terms of use, available at https://www.cambridge.org/core/terms. https://www.cambridge.org/core/product/EFEDBED0B84359DFA281A9079047846F A CRITICAL INTRODUCTION TO INTERNATIONAL CRIMINAL LAW International criminal law has witnessed a rapid rise since the end of the Cold War. The United Nations refers to the birth of a new ‘age of accountability’, but certain historical objections, such as selectivity or victor’s justice, have never fully gone away, and many of the justice dimensions of international criminal law remain unexplored. Various critiques have emerged in sociolegal scholarship or globalization discourse, revealing that there is a stark discrepancy between reality and expectation. Linking discussion of legal theories, case law and practice to scholarship and opinion, A Critical Introduction to International Criminal Law explores these critiques through five main themes at the heart of contemporary dilemmas: • The shifting contours of criminality and international crimes • The tension between individual and collective responsibility • The challenges of domestic, international, hybrid and regional justice institutions • The foundations of justice procedures • Approaches towards punishment and reparation. The book is suitable for students, academics and professionals from multiple fields wishing to understand contemporary theories, practices and critiques of international criminal law.
    [Show full text]
  • Preface to LAWMAKING
    Preface to LAWMAKING 24th Biennial New Members’ Conference 2013 Illinois General Assembly Legislative Research Unit JOINT COMMITTEE ON LEGISLATIVE SUPPORT SERVICES Senate Republican Leader & Chairman Sen. Christine Radogno President of the Senate Sen. John J. Cullerton Speaker of the House Rep. Michael J. Madigan House Republican Leader Rep. Tom Cross LEGISLATIVE RESEARCH UNIT Co-Chairperson Sen. Pamela J. Althoff Co-Chairperson Vacant Executive Director Alan R. Kroner Associate Director Jonathan P. Wolff Senators Representatives Thomas Cullerton Adam Brown Sam McCann La Shawn K. Ford Julie A. Morrison Chad Hays Jim Oberweis Barbara Wheeler Martin A. Sandoval Vacant The Legislative Research Unit is the central general research agency for the General Assembly. A board of 12 legislators, ap- pointed by the Joint Committee on Legislative Support Services, supervises its operations. A staff of researchers handles inquiries from legislators, legisla- tive committees, and partisan staff. The staff’s areas of expertise include law generally, science and technology, taxation, educa- tion, local government, economics and fiscal affairs, and the political and social history of Illinois. Legislative Research Unit 222 S. College, Suite 301 Springfield, Illinois 62704-1894 Phone: 217/782-6851 Website: www.ilga.gov/commission/lru/lru_home.html Cover note: photos by Kevin Jones Preface to LAWMAKING Seventeenth Edition July 2013* Publication 373 Copyright © 2013 Illinois Legislative Research Unit Springfield, Illinois * Text as presented at the 24th
    [Show full text]
  • Arizona State Legislature V. Arizona Independent Redistricting Comm'n
    (Slip Opinion) OCTOBER TERM, 2014 1 Syllabus NOTE: Where it is feasible, a syllabus (headnote) will be released, as is being done in connection with this case, at the time the opinion is issued. The syllabus constitutes no part of the opinion of the Court but has been prepared by the Reporter of Decisions for the convenience of the reader. See United States v. Detroit Timber & Lumber Co., 200 U. S. 321, 337. SUPREME COURT OF THE UNITED STATES Syllabus ARIZONA STATE LEGISLATURE v. ARIZONA INDEPENDENT REDISTRICTING COMMISSION ET AL. APPEAL FROM THE UNITED STATES DISTRICT COURT FOR THE DISTRICT OF ARIZONA No. 13–1314. Argued March 2, 2015—Decided June 29, 2015 Under Arizona’s Constitution, the electorate shares lawmaking author- ity on equal footing with the Arizona Legislature. The voters may adopt laws and constitutional amendments by ballot initiative, and they may approve or disapprove, by referendum, measures passed by the Legislature. Ariz. Const., Art. IV, pt. 1, §1. “Any law which may be enacted by the Legislature . may be enacted by the people under the Initiative.” Art. XXII, §14. In 2000, Arizona voters adopted Proposition 106, an initiative aimed at the problem of gerrymandering. Proposition 106 amended Arizona’s Constitution, removing redistricting authority from the Ar- izona Legislature and vesting it in an independent commission, the Arizona Independent Redistricting Commission (AIRC). After the 2010 census, as after the 2000 census, the AIRC adopted redistricting maps for congressional as well as state legislative districts. The Ari- zona Legislature challenged the map the Commission adopted in 2012 for congressional districts, arguing that the AIRC and its map violated the “Elections Clause” of the U.
    [Show full text]
  • Teacher's Guide
    Teacher’s Guide State Lawmaking Time Needed: One to Two Class Learning Objectives. Students will be able to: Periods Illustrate how a bill becomes law Identify the role of state governments in policy-making Materials Needed: Student worksheets Explain the influence on the legislative process of political parties, interest groups, grass roots organizations, Copy Instructions: lobbyists, public opinion, and individual voters Reading (5 pages; class set) Analyze the effectiveness of citizen efforts to influence Activity (2 pages; class set) decisions of state and local governments Describe the processes of initiative and referendum STEP BY STEP ANTICIPATE by asking students to predict how many bills actually make it to the governor’s desk and receive a signature into law. Ask why they think the number is high or low? What might impact the success of a bill? DISTRIBUTE the “State Lawmaking” reading notes page and reading pages to each student. READ through the first page with the class, discussing each idea source and clarifying as needed. If your state has recently experienced a referendum or initiative, this is a great time to introduce it to the students. ASK students to continue to read the two pages that follow, using their reading notes to keep track of the legislative process. Then, return to the anticipation questions. Why would the system make the process of lawmaking so difficult? Is this a good thing or a bad thing? Discuss. READ the introduction to the “Spotlight on Interest Groups and Lobbying” with the class. ASK students to break down the definition in the space provided.
    [Show full text]
  • Law Making, the Rule of Law, and the Quality of Democracy in Greece Constantine P
    Law Making, the Rule of Law, and the Quality of Democracy in Greece Constantine P. Danopoulos1 The rule of law is arguable the single most essential dimension of quality democracy; it is virtually synonymous with democracy. It is the anchor upon which all other dimensions of the quality of democracy depend for substance, enforceability, effectiveness, and meaning. The literature on the rule of law leaves little room for doubt as to its seminal importance. Juan J. Linz and Alfred Stepan view the rule of law as an “indispensable condition.”2 Guillermo O’Donnell believes that “the rule of law works intimately with other dimensions of the quality of democracy.” In his mind, “the rule of law is among the essential pillars upon which any high quality democracy rests. Without a vigorous rule of law, defended by an independent judiciary, rights are not safe and the equality and dignity of all citizens are at risk.” He adds: only under the rule of law “will the various agencies of electoral, societal, and horizontal accountability function effectively, without obstruction and intimidation from powerful state actors.”3 Thomas Carothers sees a “profound” relationship between the rule of law and liberal democracy, asserting that “the rule of law makes possible individual rights, which are at the core of democracy.” Without the rule of law, he argues, “major economic institutions would not function, and the government’s multifaceted involvement in the economy would be unfair, inefficient, and opaque.”4 Larry Diamond and Leonardo Morlino are equally emphatic regarding the salience of the rule of law and its impact on other dimensions of democratic quality.
    [Show full text]
  • Congress and Lawmaking 3
    CHAPTER Congress and 1 Lawmaking ONGRESSIONAL RULES and procedures are a complex mix of intricate Cfeatures that can be used to expedite, slow down, or stop action on legislation. Adroit lawmakers may influence how expeditiously legisla- tion moves through Congress, but in doing so, they must navigate around procedural obstacles. This legislative reality typically means that measures move slowly through the congressional maze, or sometimes not at all. At times, members can employ parliamentary procedures to bypass lawmak- ing stages to accelerate even controversial measures through the usually slow-moving Congress. Crises may inspire swift legislative action as well, a classic example being the Depression-era emergencydistribute banking bill sent to Congress on March 9, 1933, by President Franklin D. Roosevelt. It passed both chambers in a matter of hours and was signedor into law that same day.1 Fast-forward to fall 2008, which witnessed the collapse of banking giants, the housing market, and Wall Street brokerage firms. In a 10-year anni- versary analysis of the economic implosion, a congressional scholar wrote that “the nation’s economy hovered perilously on the edge of an abyss.” Congress acted with dispatch, saidpost, the scholar, and “prevented a second Great Depression.”2 For example, Congress moved rapidly (January 26 to February 17, 2009) to enact the president’s nearly $800 billion economic stimulus package, bypassing committee consideration of the legislation (H.R. 1) in both chambers.3 Too much haste in passing major legislation can sometimes have pro- found and unforeseencopy, implications. Two classic examples highlight the dangers of insufficient deliberation by lawmakers and legislative speedi- ness, especially in granting the president the equivalent of a declaration of war.not In early August 1964, President Lyndon B.
    [Show full text]
  • The Rule of Law and the Law of Precedents
    Essay The Rule of Law and the Law of Precedents Daniel A. Farbert "Historycounts. The only significant question is how."1 The relationship between precedent and the rule of law is hotly contested. 2 On the one hand, consider the views of the late Justice Lewis Powell. According to Justice Powell, "[E]limination of constitutional stare decisis would represent an explicit endorsement of the idea that the Constitution is nothing more than what five Justices say it is. This would un- dermine the rule of law."3 He added that the "inevitability of change touches law as it does every aspect of life. But stability and moderation are uniquely important to the law."4 Powell concluded that "restraint in decisionmaking and respect for de- cisions once made are the keys to preservation of an independ- ent judiciary and public respect for the judiciary's role as a guardian of rights."5 On the other hand, stare decisis has also been portrayed as a betrayal of the judge's duty to follow the law and thus of the rule of law itself. Here, consider the view of a current Justice, t Sho Sato Professor of Law, University of California at Berkeley. 1. Henry Paul Monaghan, Stare Decisis and ConstitutionalAdjudication, 88 COLUM. L. REV. 723, 745 (1988). 2. For useful overviews, see generally Richard H. Fallon, Jr., Stare De- cisis and the Constitution:An Essay on Constitutional Methodology, 76 N.Y.U. L. REV. 570 (2001); Earl Maltz, The Nature of Precedent, 66 N.C. L. REV. 367 (1988); Monaghan, supra note 1; Frederick Schauer, Precedent, 39 STAN.
    [Show full text]
  • The “Regular Order”: a Perspective
    The “Regular Order”: A Perspective November 6, 2020 Congressional Research Service https://crsreports.congress.gov R46597 SUMMARY R46597 The “Regular Order”: A Perspective November 6, 2020 Many contemporary lawmakers urge a return to “regular order” lawmaking. In general, the regular order refers to a traditional, committee-centered process of lawmaking, very Walter J. Oleszek much in evidence during most of the 20th century. Today, Congress has evolved to Senior Specialist in become largely a party-centered institution. Committees remain important, but they are American National less important than previously as “gatekeepers” to the floor. This development Government represents a fundamental “then and now” change in the power dynamics of Capitol Hill. Regular order is generally viewed as a systematic, step-by-step lawmaking process that emphasizes the role of committees: bill introduction and referral to committee; the conduct of committee hearings, markups, and reports on legislation; House and Senate floor consideration of committee-reported measures; and the creation of conference committees to resolve bicameral differences. Many Members and commentators view this sequential pattern as the ideal or “best practices” way to craft the nation’s laws. Regular order is a lawmaking process that promotes transparency, deliberation, and the wide participation of Members in policy formulation. Significant deviations from the textbook model of legislating—common in this party-centric period—might be called “irregular,” “nontraditional,” “unorthodox,” or “unconventional” lawmaking. The well- known “Schoolhouse Rock” model of legislating still occurs, but its prominence has declined compared with the rise of newer, party leadership-directed processes. Regular or irregular procedures can successfully be used to translate ideas into laws.
    [Show full text]