GOD, TIME, and ETERNITY GOD, TIME, and ETERNITY the Coherence of Theism 11: Eternity
Total Page:16
File Type:pdf, Size:1020Kb
GOD, TIME, AND ETERNITY GOD, TIME, AND ETERNITY The Coherence of Theism 11: Eternity by William Lane Craig Talbot School ofTheology, La Mirada, CA, U.S.A. SPRINGER-SCIENCE+BUSINESS MEDIA, B.V. A C.I.P. Catalogue record for this book is available from the Library of Congress. ISBN 978-90-481-5823-2 ISBN 978-94-017-1715-1 (eBook) DOI 10.1007/978-94-017-1715-1 Printed on acid{ree paper Cover: Salvador Dali (1904-1989), The Crucifixion. Oil on canvas. Photo graph © 1987 The Metropolitan Museum of Art, Gift of The Chester Dale Collection, 1955. (55.5) All Rights Reserved © 2001 Springer Science+Business Media Dordrecht Originally published by Kluwer Academic Publishers in 2001 Softcover reprint ofthe hardcover 1st edition 2001 No part of the material protected by this copyright notice may be reproduced or utilized in any form or by any means, electronic or mechanical, including photocopying, recording, or by any information storage and retrieval system, without written pennission from the copyright owner. To ALVIN PLANTINGA who by his work and his life has pointed the way TABLE OF CONTENTS Preface ix PART I. TIIE NATURE OF DIVINE ETERNITY Section 1: Arguments for Divine Timelessness Chapter 1 The Case for Divine Timelessness 3 Section 2: Arguments for Divine Temporality Chapter 2 Timelessness and Personhood 43 Chapter 3 Timelessness and Divine Action 56 Chapter 4 Timelessness and Divine Knowledge 112 Conclusion l34 PARTII. GODANDTIME Seetion 1: God, Time, and its Measures Chapter 5 The Classical Concept ofTime 143 Chapter 6 God's Time and Relativistic Time 163 Chapter 7 God, Time, and Relativity 197 Seetion 2: God, Time, and Creation Chapter 8 Creatio ex nihilo 247 Chapter 9 God and the Beginning of Time 256 Conclusion 281 Bibliography 285 Subject Index 311 Proper Name Index 315 vii PREFACE hose who think about time are thinking deeply. Those who think about God T are thinking even more deeply still. Those who try to think about God and time are pressing the very limits of human understanding. Undaunted, this is precisely the project which we have set for ourselves in this study: to try to grasp the nature of divine eternity, to understand what is meant by the amnnation that God is etemal, to fonnulate a coherent doctrine ofGod's relationship with time. This study, the second installment of a long-range research pro gram devoted to a philosophical analysis of the principal attributes of God, flows naturally out of my previous exploration of divine omniscience.! For the most contentious issue with respect to God's being omniscient concerns divine foreknowledge of future contingents, such as free acts of human agents. The very concept of foreknowledge presupposes that God is temporal, and a good many thinkers, from Boethius to certain contemporary philosophers, have thought to avoid the alleged incompatibility of divine foreknowledge and human freedom by afflnning the timelessness of God. Thus, in examining the complex of issues surrounding the foreknowledge question, we found ourselves already immersed in the question of divine eternity. In this study, I shall not return to the discussion of the bearing which God's temporal status has on His knowledge of future contingents; rather we wish to press on to consider other arguments aimed at showing that God's eternity is best construed as either temporal or atemporal and to explore how one's answer to this question affects in turn one's understanding of God's relationship to time. Although the biblical data are underdeterminative with respect to the nature of God's eternity, historically the conception of divine eternity as timelessness has, through the influence of Platonie thought-the Church Father Origen and the Neo Platonist Plotinus were both pupils of Ammonius Saccus in Alexandria-, dominated Christian theology until lohn Duns Scotus, who offered an incisive critique of Thomas Aquinas's own defense of divine timelessness. As I have elsewhere briefly surveyed the thinking of several key Christian theologians from Augustine to Suarez on the nature of divine eternity/ the present study shall forego a historical exposition of the doctrine and focus immediatelyon a critical discussion of the arguments. Unfortunately, the works of contemporary theologians will be of little help here, for the lack of analytical tools or the theological anti-realism which has in recent years blighted systematic theology foil or prevent a significant grappling with the William Lane Craig. The Problem ofDilline Foreknowledge and Future Contingents from Aristotle (0 Suarez, Brill's Studies in Intellectual History 7 (Leiden: E. 1. Brill, 1988); idem, Dilline Foreknowledge and Human Freedom: The Coherence of Theism I: Omniscience, Brill's Studies in Intellectual History 19 (Leiden: E. 1. Brill, 1990). 2 Craig, Problem of Dilline Foreknowledge and Future Contingents. See also Alan G. Padgett, God, Eternity and the Nature ofTime (New Vork: St. Martin's, 1992), chap. 3. ix x issues on their part. 3 Fortunately, there has been during the last two decades a burst of interest in the doctrine of divine eternity, no doubt due in large part to the stimulus of the foreknowledge-freedom debate, among analytic philosophers of religion. The construal of divine eternity in terms of infinite omnitemporality has been greatly advanced during the twentieth century through the influence of Whitehead and Hartshome's process theology and its critique of the c1assic conception of God as pure actuality, simple, impassible, immutable, and timeless. For many years, Nelson Pike's God and Timelessness (1970), in which he argued that the doctrine of divine timeless eternity is incoherent, remained the only monograph on the subject. The dearth of material on divine eternity is evidenced by the fact that no entries on this subject were inc1uded in Wainwright's Philosophy 0/ Religion: an Annotated Bibliography 0/ Twentieth Century Writings in English (1978). Then in 1981 Eleonore Stump and Norman KretZInann published in the Journal 0/ Philosophy an artic1e entitled simply "Eternity," in which they defended a conception of divine eternity as atemporal and sought to speil out how a timeless being could be related to temporal entities. Their artic1e sparked a revival of interest in the nature of God's eternity and His relation to time. Since 1987, when I first began this study, a steady stream of monographs (not to speak of journal articles or book chapters) on the problem have issued from the presses: Paul Helm, Eternal God (1988), William Hasker, God, Time, and Knowledge (1989), lohn Yates, The Timelessness o/God (1990), Brian Leftow, Time and Eternity (1991), Alan Padgett, God, Eternity and the Nature 0/ Time (1992), Robert Neville, Eternity and Time 's Flow (1993), Lawrence Fagg, The Becoming o/Time (1995), all conspiring to rob me of anything to say! I hope to show that much original work, especially of an integrative nature, One can only agree, for example, with Jantzen when she concludes that the writing of Karl Barth on the subject of God's etemity (Church Dogmatics [Edinburgh: T. & T. Clark, 1936] vol. 2, pt. I, pp. 608- 677) amounts to little more than "edifying nonsense" (Grace M. Jantzen, God's Warld, God's Body [London: Darton, Longman, & Todd, 1984], p. 59). Even so level-headed a theologian as Pannenberg is of little help, for he seems to reject the mere timelessness of God in favor of timelessness with a relation to time; but he never explains how this is possible (Wolfhart Pannenberg, Systematic Theology, vol. I, trans. Geoffery Bromiley [Grand Rapids, Mich.: Wm. B. Eerdmans, 1991], pp. 402-409). At least Pannen berg does not repeat his earlier obscure doctrine that God somehow exists in the future, which is unfortunately adopted by Ted Peters, God-the Wor/d's Future (Minneapolis: Fortress Press, 1992). Although Peters says, "God creates from the future, not the past" (lbid., p. 134), what he really describes is God' s bestowing on us a future, i. e., continued existence, hope, etc. EIsewhere he interprets the dictum "God creates from the future" in terms of God's transcending the whole spacetime manifold, such that creation is "a single event incorporating the whole history of the cosmos" (Idem, "Cosmos as Creation," in Cosmos as Creation, ed. T. Peters [Nashville: Abingdon Press, 1989], pp. 88-89), a comprehensible doctrine, but insufficiently supported by argument on Peters' spart. By contrast I do not even understand what Robert Neville is talking about when he says, "Etemity ... is the togethemess of the modes of time past, present, and future-so that each can be its temporal self' (Robert C. Neville, Eternity and Time 's F/ow, [Albany, N. Y.: SUNY Press, 1993], p. 60). One might think this a garbled affirmation of a tenseless theory of time, except that Neville also says that "Without etemity, time can be conceived only as a static dimension like space ... "; etemity is the "non-temporal togethemess of past, present, and future" (Ibid., pp. 12, 28}-which is just unintelligible. Perhaps the most comprehensible theologian writing on divine etemity today is the process thinker Keith Ward with whose views I shall interact. For arecent survey of theological thought on etemity, focusing on Heim, Barth, and Tillich, see Karl Hinrich Manzke, Ewigkeit und Zeitlichkeit, Forschungen zur systematischen und ökumenischen Theologie 63 (Göttingen: Vandenhoeck & Ruprecht, 1992). xi bringing together discussions of the philosophy of time and space, philosophy of language, phenomenology, philosophy of science, Special and General Relativity, classical cosmology, quantum mechanics, and so forth, with the concems of philosophy ofreligion and theology, remains to be done. I initially attempted to carry out such an integrative study in a single work. The book grew to two large volumes, which, though having philosophical theology as their central concem, tumed out to be very much like an introduction to the problems of time and space.