§ 3.2 Causation: the Requirements for Holding an Actor Accountable for a Result 125

Total Page:16

File Type:pdf, Size:1020Kb

§ 3.2 Causation: the Requirements for Holding an Actor Accountable for a Result 125 122 Chapter 3. Objective Requirements of an Offense a circumstance, purpose requires only that one the same set out for the 10 In other req[uir·ement of purpose req:uin:ment of knowledge. classified as results, but Thus, if "obstructs" is inter~ § 3.2 Causation: The Requirements for Holding an for example, the state need ouly Actor Accountable for a Result satisfy the special requirements of obstruction would not have occurred § 3.2.1 Requirements of Causation: Factual and Proximate Cause if "obstructs" is viewed as embodying Factual ("but-for") cause: scientific inquiry result element, then the state must prove Alternative sufficient-cause test responsible for bringing about a resulting Proximate (legal) cause: normative inquiry Proximity examples Proposed definitions seem consistent with the spirit and Foreseeability as factor in determining proximate cause Penal Code scheme. Define "conduct" elements Vagueness in the proximate-cause standard actual physical acts of the actor. Define all char- § 3.2.2 Causing Another Person to Cause a Result to be separate "circumsta ements; similarly, Intervening actor's volitional act breaks chain by the conduct should be de separate "result" Influencing intervening actor's exercise of volition "result" elements to be any e in the surrounding Continuum of volition brought about by the offend nduct, that the offense Causing another's crime as form of complicity occur. As with conduct, define aracteristics of a result to § 3.2.3 Multiple Causes "circumstance" dements. 13 Imputing co-criminal's causal conduct mustration: "obstructing an offense of "obstructing lie highway" would essentially "Combined effect" analysis a highway" proof that the actor "engage conduct that caused the obstruc- Dangers of "combined effect" of a public highway." "Obst on" would be a result element; the Serial vs. intersecting causes state would have to prove that t or's conduct caused the obstruction, Assessing serial dimension with proximate-cause test which is a change in circumsta required under the offense (prior to the Assessing accountability among intersecting causes offense conduct the highway not obstructed, afterward it was). On the Necessary-cause test and simultaneous sufficient causes other hand, the requirem fa "public highway'' would be a circum- Necessary-cause test and intervening sufficient cause stance element, as it w involve the context in which t Accountability dependent on sufficiency of other cause occurred rather than a ge the actor brought about-the way exists both befo after the offense. The "conduct" Whenever an offense definition includes a result element-as, for example, Causation an issue only in many offenses, re homicide requires a resulting death-a causation requirement also is when offense includes a result element required, other th implied. That is, it must not ouly be shown that the prohibited result occurred, but also that the actor's conduct caused that result. This required relationship between the actor's conduct and the result derives from our pes" or desires that a circumstance exis to a result or <iuct being on actor's "conscious obj ' notions of causal accountability. A result ought to affect an actor's liability posely" as to rcumstance, but is not required. For fu ouly if the actor is responsible for it, and responsibility demands some and similar issues- such as the failure to define the co with respect to conduct elements- see § 4.1. 11 See Model Penal Code § 2.03. 12 This includes, for example, the requirement e result be "not too remote or acci- 14 For a more detailed description of this proposal and the reasons for it, see 1 Paul H. dental in its occurrence to have a [just] bearing o e actor's liability or on the gravity of his Robinson, Criminal Law Defenses§ 6l(c) (1984); Robinson & Grall, Element Analysis, supra offense." For a discussion of the special req · nts for establishing an adequate causal note 8, at 719-25. connection between an actor's conduct and t, see§ 3.2. For a discussion of the act requirement, see § 3.3. 13 Not everyone would agree that the pr response to the Code's failure to define its 15 But see Cook v. State, 884 S.W.2d 485,487 (Tex. Crim. App. 1994) (apparently adapting categories is to provide such definitions. The English Law Reform Commission found the narrow interpretation of'' conduct" element, consistent with suggestions made here); Lugo­ Model Penal Code's distinctions awkward and conceptually dubious. Law Conunission, Lugo v. State, 650 S.W.2d 72, 88-87 (Tex. Crim. App. 1983); Mcqueen v. State, 781 S.W.2d Attempt and Impossibility!! 2.14-2.17 (Law Comm'n Rep. No. 102, HMSO !980). 600, 603 (Tex. Crim. App. 1989). 124 Chapter 3. Objective Requirements of an Offense § 3.2 Causation: the Requirements for Holding an Actor Accountable for a Result 125 causal connection. Causation doctrine provides the rules that determine how also would not have occurred. Second, the conduct must be a legal, or much of a causal connection is required to hold an actor legally accouutable proximate, cause of the result, meaning that it must relate to the result for the occurrence of some harm. in a sufficiently strong way: as a common formulatiOn puts tt, the resultmg t: harm must not be "too remote or accidental in its occurrence to have a ~· 1 [just] bearing on the actor's liability or on the gravity of his offense." Some I ... HYPOTIIETICAL t> MANNY THE MASTER states also add to this the requirement that the resulting harm "not be too ... dependent on another's volitional act."2 An informant in the police department reports that Prosecutor Baylor is Conduct is a factual cause of a result if the result would not have Factual ("but-fo,..) being investigated for taking bribes to forgo prosecutions. Kenny "The occurred but for the conduct (hence the term "but-for causation"). cause: scientific inquiry '., Hat," the local uuderworld boss, suspects that if Baylor is arrested he In other words, the conduct is a factual cause if it was necessary for the 'I will reveal all to the authorities. Kenny decides to have Baylor killed. result to occur. The factual-cause inquiry is essentially scientific, though To be sure that the job gets done, he gives contracts to both Squeeze also hypothetical. It asks what the world would have been like if the actor and Manny. Squeeze, who is somewhat brighter and more experienced had not performed his conduct. Specifically, would the result still have than her competitor Manny, arranges to poison Prosecutor Baylor at the occurred when it did?3 If not, then the actor's conduct was necessary for corner hotdog stand where he frequently eats. Manny is tailing Baylor the result- it was a but-for cause. In the "Manny the Master" hypothetical looking for an opportunity. When he sees Squeeze at the hotdog stand, above, Manny's conduct is a necessary cause of Baylor's death. Because he suspects he has been outdone. Squeeze glides over with a smile. "He ate Baylor died from the fall and would have died then whether he had been enough to kill an elephant," she tells Manny. "He'll be dead in 45 minutes. poisoned or not, Squeeze's poisoning is not a but-for cause of Baylor's Better luck next time." death (unless the poisoning, or her telling Manny about tt, mduced Manny is not giving up so easily. He scurries after Baylor, who has Manny to formulate his platform-push plan in an effort to kill Baylor finished his hotdog and is headed down to the subway. Manny spots Baylor right away, in which case it would be a but-for cause). at the edge of the platform and positions himself several feet behind him in This necessary-cause test is not the only possible formulation of the Alternative sufficient· the crowd. As the train approaches, he pushes another waiting passenger factual-cause requirement. Criticisms of some results of the necessary­ cause test into Baylor, so that Baylor will be pushed in front of the train and killed cause test-such as Squeeze's escape from causal accountability for Bay­ instantly. But as Manny pushes, the crowd surges, and his push sends the lor's death-may lead one to examine whether other formulations, such as wrong person off the platform. His push is also much too early. The fallen a sufficient-cause test, might be preferable. A sufficient-cause test similarly passenger scrambles back onto the platform before the train arrives. Manny presents a scientific and hypothetical inquiry, but a different inquiry: turns to leave, angry and humiliated. Maybe he should go to computer Would the actor's conduct have been enough, by itself, to cause the result? school, he thinks, recalling an ad he saw on a matchbook cover. Screams In contrast to the scientific inquiry of the factual-cause requirement, Proximate (legal) cause: from the track malce him tum. People are milling about, peering under the the proximate (legal) cause requirement presents an essentially normative normative inquiry I train. He learns from others that a man straining to see the fallen passenger inquiry. Deciding whether a result is "too remote or accidental in its occur­ leaned out too far and was hit by the oncoming train. He presses forward to rence, or "too dependent on another's volitional act" calls for an exercise II see the dead man. Could he be so lucky? They pull Prosecutor Baylor from of evaluative judgment. The inquiry cannot be resolved by examining the under the train. Manny turns and heads for the exit, full of himself. Squeeze facts more closely or having a more advanced uuderstanding of the science won't be making fun of him today.
Recommended publications
  • Without Causation, Fraud and Subsequent Loss Are Not Adequate Grounds for Recovery Tom O'connor
    Loyola Consumer Law Review Volume 9 | Issue 4 Article 4 1997 Without Causation, Fraud and Subsequent Loss are Not Adequate Grounds for Recovery Tom O'Connor Follow this and additional works at: http://lawecommons.luc.edu/lclr Part of the Consumer Protection Law Commons Recommended Citation Tom O'Connor Without Causation, Fraud and Subsequent Loss are Not Adequate Grounds for Recovery, 9 Loy. Consumer L. Rev. 309 (1997). Available at: http://lawecommons.luc.edu/lclr/vol9/iss4/4 This Recent Case is brought to you for free and open access by LAW eCommons. It has been accepted for inclusion in Loyola Consumer Law Review by an authorized administrator of LAW eCommons. For more information, please contact [email protected]. RECENT CA SES Without Causation, Fraud and Subsequent Loss Are Not Adequate Grounds for Recovery by Tom O'Connor In Mark Law v. Medco Research September 1, 1992 should have a new drug was "on track." These Inc., 113 F.3d 781 (7th Cir. 1997), provided "storm warnings" to articles reported that: (1) Defen- Mark Law ("Plaintiffs") filed a class investors and satisfied the notice dants' supplier of pharmaceuticals, action suit for similarly situated requirement. These articles called Fujisawa, was suing the company investors in Medco Research Inc. Defendants an "overpriced hype which sold Fujisawa the production ("Defendants"), claiming Defen- job" whose stock was bought by facilities for Defendants' drug, and dants defrauded their investors. The "idiots." In reviewing this argu- (2) Fujisawa's production facility United States Court of Appeals for ment, the court noted that these had quality and regulatory problems the Seventh Circuit dismissed the articles were not given credence by in producing a number of its drugs.
    [Show full text]
  • The Boundaries of Vicarious Liability: an Economic Analysis of the Scope of Employment Rule and Related Legal Doctrines
    University of Chicago Law School Chicago Unbound Journal Articles Faculty Scholarship 1987 The Boundaries of Vicarious Liability: An Economic Analysis of the Scope of Employment Rule and Related Legal Doctrines Alan O. Sykes Follow this and additional works at: https://chicagounbound.uchicago.edu/journal_articles Part of the Law Commons Recommended Citation Alan O. Sykes, "The Boundaries of Vicarious Liability: An Economic Analysis of the Scope of Employment Rule and Related Legal Doctrines," 101 Harvard Law Review 563 (1987). This Article is brought to you for free and open access by the Faculty Scholarship at Chicago Unbound. It has been accepted for inclusion in Journal Articles by an authorized administrator of Chicago Unbound. For more information, please contact [email protected]. VOLUME 101 JANUARY 1988 NUMBER 3 HARVARD LAW REVIEW1 ARTICLES THE BOUNDARIES OF VICARIOUS LIABILITY: AN ECONOMIC ANALYSIS OF THE SCOPE OF EMPLOYMENT RULE AND RELATED LEGAL DOCTRINES Alan 0. Sykes* 441TICARIOUS liability" may be defined as the imposition of lia- V bility upon one party for a wrong committed by another party.1 One of its most common forms is the imposition of liability on an employer for the wrong of an employee or agent. The imposition of vicarious liability usually depends in part upon the nature of the activity in which the wrong arises. For example, if an employee (or "servant") commits a tort within the ordinary course of business, the employer (or "master") normally incurs vicarious lia- bility under principles of respondeat superior. If the tort arises outside the "scope of employment," however, the employer does not incur liability, absent special circumstances.
    [Show full text]
  • Criminal Law--Conspiracy and the Felony Murder Doctrine in Kentucky J
    Kentucky Law Journal Volume 29 | Issue 1 Article 14 1940 Criminal Law--Conspiracy and the Felony Murder Doctrine in Kentucky J. Wirt Turner Jr. University of Kentucky Follow this and additional works at: https://uknowledge.uky.edu/klj Part of the Criminal Law Commons, and the State and Local Government Law Commons Right click to open a feedback form in a new tab to let us know how this document benefits you. Recommended Citation Turner, J. Wirt Jr. (1940) "Criminal Law--Conspiracy and the Felony Murder Doctrine in Kentucky," Kentucky Law Journal: Vol. 29 : Iss. 1 , Article 14. Available at: https://uknowledge.uky.edu/klj/vol29/iss1/14 This Comment is brought to you for free and open access by the Law Journals at UKnowledge. It has been accepted for inclusion in Kentucky Law Journal by an authorized editor of UKnowledge. For more information, please contact [email protected]. KENTUCKY LAw JOURNAL In conclusion, it is submitted that the felony murder doctrine in Kentucky is based on the same principles as the negligent murder doctrine, since to convict a defendant of murder for a death occuring during the commission of a felony there must first be a felony dangerous to life and, secondly, the death of the victim must be the necessary or natural consequence of the felony. J. GRiANVILLE CLARK CRIMINAL LAW-CONSPIRACY AND THE FELONY MURDER DOCTRINE IN KENTUCKY* Defendant was indicted jointly with two others for the crime of wilful murder by setting fire to a house and burning a child to death. The evidence showed that defendant was not near enough to aid and abet in the crime.
    [Show full text]
  • Vicarious Liability and Liability for the Actions of Others II
    InDret Vicarious Liability and Liability for the Actions of Others II Pablo Salvador Coderch Professor of Law Universitat Pompeu Fabra, Barcelona (Spain) [email protected] Carlos Ignacio Gómez Ligüerre Assistant Professor of Law Universitat Internacional de Catalunya, Barcelona (Spain) [email protected] July 2002 www.indret.com InDret 03/2002 Pablo Salvador and Carlos Gómez Summary 1. Vicarious liability or liability for the actions of others as a mean of overcoming the principle of individual liability 2. Civil and Criminal Rules governing Civil liability for the actions of others 2.1. Reasons for the existence of two sets of rules that are almost identical, one in section 1903 of the Civil Code and the other in section 120 of the Criminal Code 2.2. Liability due to personal dependency: parents and tutors 2.3. Liability stemming from professional dependency: employers and school owners and teachers a) Relationship of Dependency b) Performance of their liabilities and services c) Reimbursement in favor of the principal 3. From Dependency to Control 4. Bibliography 2 InDret 03/2002 Pablo Salvador and Carlos Gómez Abstract The two traditional branches that regulate civil liability in Spain are the Spanish Civil Code of 1889 (sections 1902, 1903 and 1904) and the Spanish Criminal Code of 1995 (section 120), they determine the harm caused by actions or omissions that are neither crimes nor misdemeanors and those deemed to be, respectively. This work analyzes vicarious liability or liability for the actions of others as one of the legal mechanisms anticipated to overcome civil liability once it has been determined that the principle of individual liability –due to negligence or strict liability– is impractical given the limited solvency of the majority of individuals responsible for a damage.
    [Show full text]
  • Dressler Criminal Law Outline
    DRESSLER CRIMINAL LAW OUTLINE I. INTRODUCTORY POINTS A. Sources of Criminal Law. 1. Common Law. 2. Statutes Derived from Common Law. 3. Model Penal Code. 4. (Bill of Rights) B. Criminal Law v. Civil Law 1. Criminal a. Defendant is punished (incarcerated) b. The criminal conviction itself says defendant is a moral wrongdoer. It is a condemnation by the community/ “a morality play.” → (Moral blameworthiness) • Usually about things you are not supposed to do as opposed to things you must do • 2. Civil a. Defendant pays victim. (compensation) b. Defendant is not morally stigmatized. (tort claims) C. Theories of Punishment. 1. Retributivism “Is it more about desert” a. People should get what they deserve. b. Humans have free will. If they choose to do wrong, it is appropriate to punish them. c. Looks backwards. Only punishes to the extent of the wrongdoing. d. Justice for the victim • The moral desert of an offender is a sufficient reason to punish him or her which is a necessary condition of punishment • Wouldn’t want to punish someone mentally ill bc they are not morally culpable • Rests on moral culpability 2. Utilitarianism – “What good does it do” • Focuses on what punishing that particular person accomplishes a. All forms of pain are bad. Punishment is not good, but neither is crime. Punishment is proper if imposition of pain will reduce the likelihood of future crimes. b. Punishment is justified in so far as it produces some net social benefit. Forward Looking c. Forms of utilitarianism. i. General deterrence: ● convince the general community to avoid criminal conduct in the future ii.
    [Show full text]
  • Vicarious Criminal Liability and the Constitutional Dimensions of Pinkerton Alex Kreit [email protected]
    American University Law Review Volume 57 | Issue 3 Article 2 2008 Vicarious Criminal Liability and the Constitutional Dimensions of Pinkerton Alex Kreit [email protected] Follow this and additional works at: http://digitalcommons.wcl.american.edu/aulr Part of the Constitutional Law Commons, and the Criminal Law Commons Recommended Citation Kreit, Alex. “Vicarious Criminal Liability and the Constitutional Dimensions of Pinkerton.” American University Law Review 57, no.3 (February, 2008): 585-639. This Article is brought to you for free and open access by the Washington College of Law Journals & Law Reviews at Digital Commons @ American University Washington College of Law. It has been accepted for inclusion in American University Law Review by an authorized administrator of Digital Commons @ American University Washington College of Law. For more information, please contact [email protected]. Vicarious Criminal Liability and the Constitutional Dimensions of Pinkerton Abstract This article considers what limits the constitution places on holding someone criminally liable for another's conduct. While vicarious criminal liability is often criticized, there is no doubt that it is constitutionally permissible as a general matter. Under the long-standing felony murder doctrine, for example, if A and B rob a bank and B shoots and kills a security guard, A can be held criminally liable for the murder. What if, however, A was not involved in the robbery but instead had a completely separate conspiracy with B to distribute cocaine? What relationship, if any, does the constitution require between A's conduct and B's crimes in order to hold A liable for them? It is clear A could not be punished for B's crimes simply because they are friends.
    [Show full text]
  • The Law of Conspiracy and Collective Reason Jens David Ohlin
    Journal of Criminal Law and Criminology Volume 98 Article 4 Issue 1 Fall Fall 2007 Group Think: The Law of Conspiracy and Collective Reason Jens David Ohlin Follow this and additional works at: https://scholarlycommons.law.northwestern.edu/jclc Part of the Criminal Law Commons, Criminology Commons, and the Criminology and Criminal Justice Commons Recommended Citation Jens David Ohlin, Group Think: The Law of Conspiracy and Collective Reason, 98 J. Crim. L. & Criminology 147 (2007-2008) This Criminal Law is brought to you for free and open access by Northwestern University School of Law Scholarly Commons. It has been accepted for inclusion in Journal of Criminal Law and Criminology by an authorized editor of Northwestern University School of Law Scholarly Commons. 0091-4169/07/9801-0147 THE JOURNALOF CRIMINAL LAW & CRIMINOLOGY Vol. 98, No. I Copyright 0 2008 by Northwestern University, Schoolof Law Printed in U.S.A. GROUP THINK: THE LAW OF CONSPIRACY AND COLLECTIVE REASON JENS DAVID OHLIN* Although vicarious liability for the acts of co-conspirators is firmly entrenched in federal courts, no adequate theory explains how the act and intention of one conspiratorcan be attributed to another, simply by virtue of their criminal agreement. This Article argues that the most promising avenue for solving the Pinkerton paradox is an appeal to the collective intention of the conspiratorialgroup to commit the crime. Unfortunately, misplaced skepticism about the notion of a "group will" has prevented criminal scholars from embracing the notion of a conspiracy's collective intention to commit a crime. However, positing group intentions requires only that the criminal law recognize the rational relationships between individuals who decide to collectivize reason to pursue a common criminal goal; no burdensome theory of corporate animals with unified minds is required.
    [Show full text]
  • Causation and Harm in Data Breach Litigation
    Causation and Harm In Data Breach Litigation Demonstrating that a data breach has resulted in an injury-in-fact can be difficult, because it is not always clear what has happened or will happen with the stolen data. by Brian Ellman and Jee-Yeon Lehmann; Analysis Group, Inc. Originally published in Cybersecurity Law & Strategy Brian Ellman Jee-Yeon Lehmann Data breaches can have substantial adverse impacts on firms, not only in the form of negative publicity or harm to a company’s brand and revenues, but through liti- gation that may result. A key point of contention in data breach litigation has been whether plaintiffs have met the injury-in-fact standing requirement of Article III of the Constitution. Demonstrating that a data breach has resulted in an injury-in-fact can be difficult, because it is not always clear what has happened or will happen with the stolen data. For example, suppose hackers gained access to consumers’ personal information but the information has not yet been misused. In that case, the breach will not have resulted in actual economic harm to the consumers even though risk for future harm from the breach may remain. As a result of this dynamic, plaintiffs in data breach litigation typ- ically allege harm in terms of something that could happen (i.e., an increased risk of future injury) rather than something that did happen. The determination of standing under Article III also hinges on whether the pres- ent or future alleged harm was caused by the data breach in question, as opposed to another independent event or factor.
    [Show full text]
  • CAUSATION and FEDERAL SECURITIES FRAUD Lexisnexis
    ARTICLE: CAUSE FOR CONCERN: CAUSATION AND FEDERAL SECURITIES FRAUD March, 2009 Reporter 94 Iowa L. Rev. 811 Length: 29006 words Author: Jill E. Fisch* * Professor of Law, University of Pennsylvania Law School. Much of this Article was written while the author was the T.J. Maloney Professor of Business Law, Fordham Law School, and Director of the Fordham Corporate Law Center. Copyright 2009 by Jill E. Fisch. I am grateful to Paul Miller for helpful conversations, to Jennifer Arlen, Bill Bratton, Victor Brudney, Allen Ferrell, Jesse Fried, Jeff Gordon, Marc Gross, Elizabeth Nowicki, Dan Richman, Cathy Sharkey, Richard Squire, Jane Stapleton, David Tabak, and Ben Zipursky for probing comments on earlier drafts, and to Sriram Kilapakkam, Columbia Law School LL.M. Class of 2008, for excellent research assistance. I presented earlier drafts of this Article to seminars and faculty workshops at Columbia Law School, Harvard Law School, University of California, Berkeley, School of Law, the University of Pennsylvania Law School, Fordham Law School, UCLA Law School, Boston University Law School, and Georgetown University Law Center. I received many valuable suggestions at each session. LexisNexis Summary … Although the Third Restatement does incorporate the negligence requirement that the defendant's tortious conduct increase the risk of harm, in practice, few cases even consider something akin to a loss causation analysis. … Causal Complexity in Securities Litigation The courts' application of tort law causation principles, particularly complex
    [Show full text]
  • Causation and the Excuses
    Causation and the Excuses Michael S. Mooret My target in this paper is a theory of excuse that I call the causal theory. The causal theory is partly descriptive and partly normative. The descriptive part asserts that the established excuses of Anglo-Ameri- can criminal law can best be understood in terms of causation. Accord- ing to this part of the theory, when an agent is caused to act by a factor outside his control, he is excused; only those acts not caused by some factor external to his will are unexcused. The normative part of the the- ory asserts that the criminal law is morally right in excusing all those, and only those, whose actions are caused by factors outside their control. In a nutshell, the causal theory of excuse regards causation as the core of both legal and moral excuse. I shall urge that we must reject the causal theory of excuse. It neither describes accurately the accepted excuses of our criminal law nor provides a morally acceptable basis for deciding what conditions ought to qualify as excuses from criminal liability. I shall approach my thesis gradually, for some preliminary work must be done. In Part I below, I examine what a theory of excuse is. To do this I shall ask first what the excuses are and how they differ both from one another and from justifica- tions. I shall then ask what a theory of excuse might be and how one might argue for or against such a theory. In Part II, I attempt to show why the causal theory of excuse is so widely accepted.
    [Show full text]
  • Appendix Case 18-163, Document 190, 03/02/2021, 3047020, Page1 of 120
    Petitioner’s Appendix Case 18-163, Document 190, 03/02/2021, 3047020, Page1 of 120 18-163-cr United States v. Scott In the United States Court of Appeals for the Second Circuit AUGUST TERM 2020 No. 18-163-cr UNITED STATES OF AMERICA, Appellant, v. GERALD SCOTT, Defendant-Appellee. On Appeal from the United States District Court for the Southern District of New York ARGUED EN BANC: NOVEMBER 6, 2020 DECIDED: MARCH 2, 2021 Before: LIVINGSTON, Chief Judge, LEVAL, CABRANES, POOLER, KATZMANN, RAGGI, CHIN, LOHIER, CARNEY, SULLIVAN, BIANCO, PARK, NARDINI, and MENASHI, Circuit Judges.* ___________ * Judge Hall did not participate in the consideration of this en banc appeal. Judge Leval, Judge Katzmann, and Judge Raggi, who are senior judges, participated in this en banc decision pursuant to 28 U.S.C. § 46(c) and 28 U.S.C. § 294(c). 1 CERTIFIED COPY ISSUED ON 03/02/2021 Pet. App. 1a Case 18-163, Document 190, 03/02/2021, 3047020, Page2 of 120 18-163-cr United States v. Scott RAGGI, J., filed the majority opinion in which LIVINGSTON, C.J., CABRANES, CHIN, SULLIVAN, BIANCO, PARK, and NARDINI, JJ., joined in full, and in which MENASHI, J., joined in part. PARK, J., filed a concurring opinion in which LIVINGSTON, C.J., CABRANES, SULLIVAN, and NARDINI, JJ., joined. MENASHI, J., filed an opinion concurring in part and concurring in the judgment. LEVAL, J., filed a dissenting opinion in which KATZMANN, LOHIER and CARNEY, JJ., joined in full, and in which POOLER, J., joined in part. POOLER, J., filed a dissenting opinion in which LEVAL and CARNEY, JJ., joined as to Parts I–IV.
    [Show full text]
  • Negligence and Two-Sided Causation
    Boston University School of Law Scholarly Commons at Boston University School of Law Faculty Scholarship 1-2015 Negligence and Two-Sided Causation Keith Hylton Boston University School of Law Haizhen Lin Indiana University - Kelley School of Business Hyo-Youn Chu College of International Studies, Kyung Hee University Follow this and additional works at: https://scholarship.law.bu.edu/faculty_scholarship Part of the Law and Economics Commons, and the Torts Commons Recommended Citation Keith Hylton, Haizhen Lin & Hyo-Youn Chu, Negligence and Two-Sided Causation, No. 13-50 Boston University School of Law, Law and Economics Research Paper (2015). Available at: https://scholarship.law.bu.edu/faculty_scholarship/193 This Article is brought to you for free and open access by Scholarly Commons at Boston University School of Law. It has been accepted for inclusion in Faculty Scholarship by an authorized administrator of Scholarly Commons at Boston University School of Law. For more information, please contact [email protected]. NEGLIGENCE AND TWO-SIDED CAUSATION Forthcoming in the European Journal of Law and Economics Boston University Schoolo of Law Law & Econommics Research Paper No. 13-50 (November 26, 2013, Revised January 2015) Keith N. Hylton Boston University School of Law Haizhen Lin Kelley School of Business, University of Indiana Hyo-Youn Chu Kyung Hee University This paper can be downloaded without charge at: http://www.bu.edu/law/faculty/scholarship/workingpapers/2013.html Negligence and Two-Sided Causation Keith N. Hylton Haizhen Lin** Hyo-Youn Chu*** forthcoming in European Journal of Law and Economics January 2015 Abstract: We extend the economic analysis of negligence and intervening causation to “two-sided causation” scenarios.
    [Show full text]