A Thesis for the Decree of Ph.D., in the University of Edinburgh By

Total Page:16

File Type:pdf, Size:1020Kb

A Thesis for the Decree of Ph.D., in the University of Edinburgh By "MQLINOS AM) THE IMPLICATIONS OF THE SPIRIT OF QUIETISM. n A Thesis for the Decree of Ph.D., in the University of Edinburgh by. H. A. A^new, M.A. , BJL., Research Student in the Dejrt., of Ecclesiastical History (Faculty of Divinity) in the University. OCTOBER CONTENTS. CHAPTER. PAGE Int r o due t i on. 1 1. Hoots of Quietism: Neoplatonism, Dionysius. 3 2. Islamic Mysticism & Passivism in (a) the East; (b) Spain. Jewish influences. 21 3. Golden age of Mysticism (a) Spain; (b) The Netherlands. 43 4. The Alumbrados of Spain. 6? 5. The Illuminati of Italy. 88 6. Miguel Molinos: Valencia, Rome. 118 7. His Works. 137 8. The Growing Opposition. 163 9. The Trial. 179 10. Quietism in France. 200 11. Permanent worth of Quietism. 214 BIBLIOGRAPHY. INTRODUCTION: Beneath the anti-Reformation rigourism of the 17th century Spain and Italy, a school or thought was developing - and teaching men a doctrine of stillness and non-resistance. This is the school whose history and aims we now propose to investigate. The principal idea of this research is not only to judge the immediate influences which caused Molinos to expound his doctrine of Quietism, but to trace the close cultural contacts between the old and the new, and to draw attention to that particular mystical and semi-mystical atmosphere to which Spain was exposed by reason of its geographical and political position. As this thesis is only a chapter in the history of movements I have not attempted to do more than briefly outline the antique elements which might help to further our under­ standing of this growth of Quietism and the quietistic spirit in the 17th Century. Yet these elements must not be regarded as unimportant. Nor have I attempted to claim that Miguel de Molinos is an original mind, nor do I credit him with aiming to establish a synthesis between the hidden past and the present, between the Roman Church with its hard stone walls of ritual and formalism, and the Reformed Church with its freer atmosphere stimulating/ - 2 - stimulating to creative effort. Rather, we must look upon Molinos as the leader of a movement of men seeking a faith which exalts the individual above the Church; men who had a desire to find a direct road to God without the help of intermediaries. For them Molinos formulated the theory and practice of the Inner Life. It may "be of worth to trace some of the many streams from the Quietistic Spring. It might be suggested, though it may not be possible to prove, that Molinos is the source refreshing many spiritual movements of that age - Quakerism and various religious Reforms - but we must not be surprised that certain similarities prove a world wide exchange of ideas. A comparison of dates of different translations of "The Spiritual Guide" bears testimony to the influence of Molinos on the life of the age. It was a new emphasis, a seeking to bring the breath of life and the warmth of love to the religion of the 17th century. It was an attempt to liberate human thought, to break away from stereotyped formalism and dogma both of which were deadening the life of the Eoman and of the Reformed Churches in that sterile period. In short his work and his failure is one act in the drama of the soul f s struggle against external things. CHAPTER 1. ROOTS OF QUIETISM: EEOPIATONISM. DIONYSIUS We may briefly define Quietism as a variety of mysticism whose fundamental principles are: that it is necessary to annihilate oneself in order to be united to God; that the most perfect love of God consists in holding oneself in a state of passive contemplation, without reflection, or using any of the faculties of the soul; and being indifferent to anything that may happen to us in this state of quietude. In this state there is no need of prayer, or good works, or following any discipline. This mystic system culminates in MLguel de Molinos (1628-1697) a Spanish priest, who set the doctrine in order, gave it literary form, and became known from one of his key ideas as "Conquisi/tador de la Nada" the conqueror of the Nothing - as Unamuno names him. Our problem being to find a fuller answer to the questions "What is Quietism?" and "Who were the Quietists?" makes it necessary to answer another question, "Whence?" Most Spanish students up to a recent date regard Quietism as, in the main, having its foundations in the aberrations/ - 4 - aberrations of Teresan mysticism. Dean Inge supports this largely. But an increasing number in Spain hold that other and alien influences materially assisted and guided this development. If we trusted Molinos himself, he would have us believe that all of the thoughts of the Guia Espiritual came direct from the Holy Spirit. To that we might reply as Von Hiigel does to a similar claim made by George Fox: "Behind George Fox was all the gospel of St. John". For Quietism is a unity knit to a long past, and is therefore a very complex movement. Me cannot say that any one man was the sole author: we know it did not issue ready born from the brain of Molinos. Our task is to trace some of its sources, and tabulate some of the various movements and forces which were behind it, and which determined the nature of its development. "There are two types of piety," says Professor Heiler "which are at one in the pursuit of life, love and blessedness ... the religion which affirms, and that which negates personality; the experience of God which leans on history, and that which dispenses with history ... transformation of the world, and flight from the world."' 1 ' Though to most it was thought to be ever the part of Christian philosophy to live among the shadows, to order them/ (1) Paterson, "The Nature of Religion", p.55. - 5 - them, and to discipline them; there has ever "been in Christianity the conflict of two tendencies, corresponding to differences in human temperament; "one of attachment, a religious society which mingles with and moulds the non- religious association of human life. And a world fleeing religion, a school of solitude wherein single heroic souls learn to practise a maximum of detachment". ' The one relies upon organisation "to will, to plan, to work are wholly man's; man can, therefore must". ' ' Such a spirit must, of necessity, think more of the formal outward organism of the church. The other temperament finds its strength in the inward thought "the word is very nigh ... in thy heart ".^' Hence there is a tendency to rest rather than to do; to wait for that word of power: the only desire being for that unity in which God is visualized by St. John "I and the Father are one". Since the mere power to do comes from God, therefore "the true and essential preparation for any action ... in life, seems to be the repose of one's own powers; the absence of all efforts of self direction, of all strain and striving, the annihilation of all confidence in one's own capacities, the complete quiet of the 'creature'".' ' Von Hiigel, Essays on Philosophy & Religion, p.248 Martindale, St. Augustine, p.22. 8 Dt., JO. 14. II Harvard Review, Vol. 10. p. 3. - 6 - The two temperaments can coalesce and form a balanced type such as a St. Paul, who thirsts in his soul for God, passing over "the weak and beggarly elements" of external forms into the rapt moment when nl live,yet not. I,but Christ liveth in me n . Yet he does not contemn the framework of the Christian society as he gives directions about worship, rules about fasting, and ordinances. In Greek thought we have Aristotle and Plato, whose names have become symbols of like opposing principles. It is outside our purpose to study the real Aristotle with his dualism, his eternity of the world, his far-away God, his philosophy of reason. He had his influence, though Aquinfcs,A. who counted himself a disciple of the great Greek, chose only such parts of him as fitted into the Church's teaching.^ ' We are rather concentrating on the great service of Plato in maintaining and moulding the faith of the early Church in a time of extreme philosophic difficulty. Also we are acknowledging the debt of the mediaeval Church to the Platonic School in its struggle between religious perception, and meddling dialectic. Plato stood as the symbolic leader of all those who believed in the personal apprehension of the Divine by the human/ (1) D'Aygalliers, Ruysbroeck The Admirable, p. 243. - 7 - human conscience. All such had the Platonic desire to obtain a vision of Beauty and of Diety, not by he art-searching, but by loving: for they believed that God was meant to be enjoyed, and not analysed. This is mysticism: that rich and many sided type of religion; that effort of the mind to grasp the Infinite. Our task is not to detail a history of mysticism, but rather to show how easily and how everywhere it developed a quietistic tendency. The effort in mysticism has been to keep detachment and contemplation within reasonable limits - for these ideas which are central in mysticism contain in them a temptation to take a passive attitude, not only to God, but to life. Von Hulgel will have it that "there are two currents in mysticism itself. In one the decisive terms are Passivity, in which the soul is, and receives; Fixedness; and Oneness.
Recommended publications
  • Acquired Contemplation Full
    THE ART OF ACQUIRED CONTEMPLATION FOR EVERYONE (Into the Mystery of God) Deacon Dr. Bob McDonald ECCE HOMO Behold the Man Behold the Man-God Behold His holy face Creased with sadness and pain. His head shrouded and shredded with thorns The atrocious crown for the King of Kings Scourged and torn with forty lashes Humiliated and mockingly adored. Pleading with love rejected Impaled by my crucifying sins Yet persisting in his love for me I see all this in his tortured eyes. So, grant me the grace to love you As you have loved me That I may lay down my life in joy As you have joyfully laid down your life for me. In the stillness I seek you In the silence I find you In the quiet I listen For the music of God. THE ART OF ACQUIRED CONTEMPLATION Chapter 1 What is Acquired Contemplation? Chapter 2 The Christian Tradition Chapter 3 The Scriptural Foundation Chapter 4 The Method Chapter 5 Expectations Chapter 6 The Last Word CHAPTER 1 WHAT IS ACQUIRED CONTEMPLATION? It will no doubt come as a surprise For the reader to be told that acquired contemplation is indeed somethinG that can be “acquired” and that it is in Fact available to all Christians in all walKs oF liFe. It is not, as is commonly held, an esoteric practice reserved For men and women oF exceptional holiness. It is now Known to possess a universal potential which all oF us can enjoy and which has been larGely untapped by lay Christians For niGh on 2000 years.
    [Show full text]
  • Flagging Philosophical Minefields at the Synod of Dort (1618-1619) – Reformed Scholasticism Reconsidered1
    Flagging philosophical minefields at the Synod of Dort (1618-1619) – reformed Scholasticism reconsidered1 B.J. van der Walt School of Philosophy Potchefstroom Campus North-West University POTCHEFSTROOM E-mail: [email protected] Abstract Flagging philosophical minefields at the Synod of Dort (1618- 1619) – reformed Scholasticism reconsidered This article investigates the phenomenon of reformed Scholasticism (of about 1550-1700), as it occurred at the Synod of Dort (1618-1619) and its Canons. More specifically, it fo- cuses on the central problem at the Synod, viz. the relationship between God and human beings, as expressed in the ideas contained in the Canon regarding divine election and repro- bation. As illustration the positions of two leading figures in the clash between the Calvinists and the Remonstrants, namely that of Gomarus (1563-1641) and Arminius (1560-1609), are philosophically analysed. In spite of the fact that neither view- point was eventually accepted by the Synod, their theologies clearly reflect the dominant scholastic philosophy of the time. This analysis is carried out in the context of the problem- historical method of historiography developed by D.H. Th. Vollenhoven (1892-1978), one of the fathers of Christian philosophy. 1 This is a revised text from a paper delivered at the Vollenhoven Colloquium on 15 August 2011 at the Free University of Amsterdam, the Netherlands, prior to the International Symposium commemorating the 75th anniversary of the Association for Christian Philosophy. Koers 76(3) 2011:505-538 505 Flagging philosophical minefields … Synod of Dort … Scholasticism reconsidered This contribution provides (in a series of other research publi- cations, cf.
    [Show full text]
  • Introduction
    Introduction (1) In 1675 the Spanish priest Miguel de Molinos published at the age of forty-seven a concise and simple introduction to the art of interior prayer, or contemplation: the Spiritual Guide, “which disentangles the soul and leads it by the interior way to perfect contemplation and the rich treasure of interior peace.”1 On its first pages it carried the approbation of some of the most notable clerics of various orders, and was an immediate success, passing through several editions in the original Spanish, and being translated into Latin, French, Italian, and English. For ten years the Spiritual Guide was immensely popular, and Molinos himself enjoyed huge popular veneration as a spiritual director and teacher. Twelve years’ residence had made him a Roman citizen, and few would recall his arrival from Valencia at the age of thirty-five as a champion for the canonization of one Francisco Simón, whose case foundered. By this time Molinos had friends in high places, including Pope Innocent XI, who secured apartments for him in the papal palace. Spectacularly, however, ten years following publication of the Spiritual Guide, and after a protracted heresy trial, lasting two years, for his alleged illuminist views, he was found guilty on sixty-eight charges, and condemned to life in prison, where he SAMPLEdied nine years later. We do not have a great deal of information regarding Molinos’ beliefs, apart from the Spiritual Guide itself, and a second hitherto unpublished book titled the Defence of Contemplation, his rebuttal of the charges of heresy. Additionally, there is the Bull Coelestis Pastor, which sets out the so- called sixty-eight heretical “propositions”.
    [Show full text]
  • Recent Developments in the Study of Arabic Philosophy and Its Impact on the West
    Recent Developments in the Study of Arabic Philosophy and Its Impact on the West: with special reference to South Italy and Sicily from Alfanus to Frederick nn Charles Burnett In respect to Arabic/Islamic philosophy, the time seems to be ripe for making syntheses. As has often been observed before, there is a major problem as to whether the subject that one is dealing with should be called 'Arabic' or 'Islamic'. The choice of adjective reflects different attitudes to the subject matter, as is exemplified in two major works in preparation. In Turkey Alparslan Acikgenc is writing a history of Islamic philosophy, in the conviction that a philosophical attitude and the basics of philosophical terminology are established already in the Meccan surahs of the Qur'an, and was developed in the Medinan surahs. This native Islamic philosophy can be seen in the kalam (dialectical theology), and it was the preexistence of lively philosophical interest and discussion that made Arabic scholars inquisitive about Greek philosophy. Greek philosophy, which they referred to as (quot­ ing Acikgenc) 'falsafa' was merely an episode, a subsection, of Islamic philosophy: the word was 'reserved exclusively for the manner of Greek, more specifically, Aristotelian philosophizing' whereas 'within Islamic civilization kalam was used to refer to what we call today philosophy'. On the other hand Richard Taylor and Peter Adamson are preparing 'the Cambridge Companion to Arabic philosophy.' This is conspicuous for its lack of contributers from the Islamic world (the nearest
    [Show full text]
  • Maurinian Truths
    Tobias HanssonTobias Wahlberg | Robin Stenwall (Eds.) Johan Brännmark Darragh Byrne Einar Duenger Bohn Matti Eklund Tobias Hansson Wahlberg Rögnvaldur D. Ingthorsson Festschrift Ingvar Johansson Martin L. Jönsson This book is in honour of Professor Maurinian Truths Anna-Sofia Maurin on her 50th Johannes Persson birthday. It consists of eighteen essays Björn Petersson on metaphysical issues written by Swedish and international scholars. Nils-Eric Sahlin Peter Simons Ylwa Sjölin Wirling Alexander Skiles Jeroen Smid Robin Stenwall Fredrik Stjernberg Naomi Thompson Kelly Trogdon Maurinian Truths Lena Wahlberg Tobias Hansson Wahlberg | Robin Stenwall (Eds.) 9 789188 899538 Maurinian Truths – Essays in Honour of Anna-Sofia Maurin on her 50th Birthday Tobias Hansson Wahlberg | Robin Stenwall (Eds.) 3 Painting by Jean-Louis Maurin Photo by Jesper Heimerson © the Authors Department of Philosophy Lund University ISBN 978-91-88899-53-8 (print) ISBN 978-91-88899-54-5 (digital) Printed in Sweden by Media-Tryck, Lund University Lund 2019 4 Towards a Nominalist Understanding of Institutions Johan Brännmark A very common understanding of institutions is that they are rules of some kind. For instance, an institutional economist like North (1990: 3) suggests that ‘[i]nstitutions are the rules of the game in a society’ and a social ontologist such as Gilbert (2018: 30) character- izes an institution as ‘a system of rules that is a blueprint for human behavior.’ In political theory, Rawls (1999: 47-48) takes the stance that an institution is ‘a public system of rules which defines offices and positions with their right and duties, powers and immunities, and the like.’ What this means is that if I hold a particular status, such as the right to perform a specific action, the fact that I, as a concrete and particular individual, hold this status is explained in terms of a certain rule being established in my community or society.
    [Show full text]
  • Of Book Titles and Other Texts
    Index of Book Titles and Other Texts Aeneid, Virgil 902 Asrār al-ḥikma al-mashriqiyya (The Mysteries Āghāz wa-anjām (The Beginning and the End), of Illuministic Philosophy), Ibn Naṣīr al-Dīn al-Ṭūsī 662–63, 672 Sabʿīn 898 Aḥwāl-i qiyāma (The circumstances of Asrār-nāme (Book of secrets), ʿAṭṭār 281 resurrection) 1040, 1042–44 Asrār al-shahāda (The spiritual realities of in paradise 1055 fig.47.9 martyrdom), Sarbāz Burūjirdī 1056 records raining from the sky 1054 fig.47.8 Asrār al-tawḥīd (Secrets of oneness) 580 n. 9 ʿAjāʾib al-makhlūqāt, al-Qazwīnī 932–33, Auf rauhem Wege, Mark Lidzbarski 1132 936, 938–39 Awṣāf al-ashrāf (Attributes of the nobles), al-Ajwiba ʿan al-asʾila al-Ṣiqilliyya (The Naṣīr al-Dīn al-Ṭūsī 662 responses to the Sicilian questions), Ibn Sabʿīn 898 Bahjat al-nāẓirīn wa-āyāt al-mustadillīn (The Akhbār Makka, al-Azraqī 357 n. 80 delight of onlookers and the signs for Akhlāq-i Muḥtashamī (The Muḥtashamid investigators), Marʿī b. Yūsuf ethics), Naṣīr al-Dīn al-Ṭūsī 662 al-Karmī 25, 931–32, 935–36, 939–42 Akhlāq-i Nāṣirī (The Nasirean Ethics), Naṣīr Bāl-i Jibrīl (Gabriel’s Wing), Muḥammad al-Dīn al-Ṭūsī 662 Iqbāl 954 n. 7 ʿAlāmāt al-qiyāma, al-Barzanjī 1249 Baṣāʾir al-darajāt, al-Ṣaffār al-Qummī 608 Alf layla wa-layla (A Thousand and One Beiträge zur Eschatologie des Islam (1895), Nights) 25, 286, 435, 587, 923–27 Josef Bernhard Rüling 6 Almagest, Ptolemy 357, 1088, 1094 Between Heaven and Hell: Islam, Salvation, Alter und Heimat der mandäischen Religion, and the Fate of Others (2013), Mohammad Mark Lidzbarski 1134 Khalil 10 Anwār al-tanzīl wa-asrār al-ta ʾwīl (The lights Biḥār al-anwār (Seas of light), Muḥammad of revelation and the secrets of Bāqir al-Majlisī 614, 1253 interpretation), al-Bayḍāwī 223, 228, The Birds, Aristophanes 253 n.
    [Show full text]
  • Unattainability of the True World: Putnamian and Kripkensteinian Interpretation of Nietzsche’S E History of an Error
    Unattainability of the True World: Putnamian and Kripkensteinian Interpretation of Nietzsche’s e History of an Error Henrik Sova Department of Philosophy, University of Tartu In this article I am interpreting Friedrich Nietzsche’s piece of writing “How the “True World” nally became a fable—e History of an Error” in the context of óþth- century analytical philosophy of language. In particular, I am going to argue that the main theme in this text—the issue of abolishing “the true world”—can be in- terpreted as (Õ) Hilary Putnam’s model-theoretic arguments against external real- ism and (ó) Saul Kripke’s Wittgensteinian (or Kripkensteinian) arguments against truth-conditional meaning theories. Interpreting this Nietzsche’s text with the help of these arguments gives rise to two options determining Nietzsche’s own posi- tion. e perspective of Putnam’s argument seems to push Nietzsche to the quietist camp—the view that signicant metaphysical debate between external realism and its opposite is impossible or inexpressible. On the other hand, the Kripkensteinian perspective gives us reasons to interpret Nietzsche as an adherer of the pragmatic account of semantics, which explains meaning through the use of language. Keywords: Nietzsche, Putnam’s argument, Kripkenstein, reference indeterminacy, quietism Õ. Introduction Starting in the late ÕÉóþs, logical positivism launched a specic—and per- haps in some ways quite unique—attack against traditional metaphysics. Of course, the intrinsic feeling or yet unformed idea that might have triggered the initial thought—that there is something inherently wrong with the way philosophy has been done so far, that it has been far less than satisfying in answering the traditional “big” philosophical questions—that itself is a very Corresponding author’s address: Henrik Sova, Department of Philosophy, Institute of Phi- losophy and Semiotics, University of Tartu, Ülikooli Õ, ¢þþÉþ Tartu, Estonia.
    [Show full text]
  • Hidden Lives: Asceticism and Interiority in the Late Reformation, 1650-1745
    Hidden Lives: Asceticism and Interiority in the Late Reformation, 1650-1745 By Timothy Cotton Wright A dissertation submitted in partial satisfaction of the requirements for the degree of Doctor of Philosophy in History in the Graduate Division of the University of California, Berkeley Committee in charge: Professor Jonathan Sheehan, chair Professor Ethan Shagan Professor Niklaus Largier Summer 2018 Abstract Hidden Lives: Asceticism and Interiority in the Late Reformation, 1650-1745 By Timothy Cotton Wright Doctor of Philosophy in History University of California, Berkeley Professor Jonathan Sheehan, Chair This dissertation explores a unique religious awakening among early modern Protestants whose primary feature was a revival of ascetic, monastic practices a century after the early Reformers condemned such practices. By the early seventeenth-century, a widespread dissatisfaction can be discerned among many awakened Protestants at the suppression of the monastic life and a new interest in reintroducing ascetic practices like celibacy, poverty, and solitary withdrawal to Protestant devotion. The introduction and chapter one explain how the absence of monasticism as an institutionally sanctioned means to express intensified holiness posed a problem to many Protestants. Large numbers of dissenters fled the mainstream Protestant religions—along with what they viewed as an increasingly materialistic, urbanized world—to seek new ways to experience God through lives of seclusion and ascetic self-deprival. In the following chapters, I show how this ascetic impulse drove the formation of new religious communities, transatlantic migration, and gave birth to new attitudes and practices toward sexuality and gender among Protestants. The study consists of four case studies, each examining a different non-conformist community that experimented with ascetic ritual and monasticism.
    [Show full text]
  • Transcending the Limits of Finitude in St. Bonaventure's Itinerarium Mentis
    Transcending the Limits of Finitude In St. Bonaventure’s Itinerarium Mentis in Deum San Beda College Moses Aaron T. Angeles, Ph.D. he “Itinerarium Mentis in Deum” has been described as Finitude of Limits the Transcending an essentially Franciscan tract, guiding learned men in the spirit of St. Francis to his mode of contemplative life. Though intended by St. Bonaventure as a guide towards meditation and contemplation, it is our intention to emphasize and elaborate on a theme,T particularly on the question of transcendence and human finitude, within the Itinerarium rather than to controvert the prevailing scholarly judgments regarding the nature and utility of ... the work. St. Bonaventure’s description of how man comes to his self-realization or self-identity is simultaneously an inventory of man’s intellectual powers and operations with a collage of Scriptural injunctions regulating the course of intellectual introspection. The coalescence of these two dimensions is an entree to the Truth of God. After the reflection of the mind upon itself, man discovers that he is an imago Dei. The name imago was given by God to man in Genesis. But now, man re-enacts that part of Creation and appropriates the name to himself. The act of self-naming is a cry of attenuated triumph. The power to name is an activity of dominion, and the act of self-nomination is the consummate exhibition of human autonomy. First of all, the term “Transcendence” and “Person”1 is not very appropriate terms when it comes to St. Bonaventure and the Itinerarium. The term “Person” as we understood it now speaks about subjectivity, the self, uniqueness, autonomy, the Existential which is in stark contrast to the Boethian universal definition of person 1 St.
    [Show full text]
  • CONTEMPLATION and the FORMATION of the VIR SPIRITUALIS in BONAVENTURE's COLLATIONES in HEXAEMERON Jay M. Hammond in 1273, From
    CONTEMPLATION AND THE FORMATION OF THE VIR SPIRITUALIS IN BONAVENTURE’S COLLATIONES IN HEXAEMERON Jay M. Hammond In 1273, from Easter (April 9) to Pentecost (May 28),1 Bonaventure delivered his Collationes in Hexaemeron at the Franciscan Convent of Cordeliers at the University of Paris.2 They are third in a series of collationes3 he delivered at Paris between 1267–1273 and represent his final synthesis.4 Attacks against the mendicants and the domi- nance of Averroistic Aristotelianism within the faculty of arts, which was making steady inroads from philosophy into theology, were two controversies within the Parisian intelligentsia that prompted Bonaventure to deliver the conferences.5 The Hexaemeron records such tension: “For there have been attacks on the life of Christ by theo- logians in morals,6 and attacks on the doctrine of Christ by the false 1 Palémon Glorieux, “La date des Collationes de S. Bonaventure,” Archivum fran- ciscanum historicum 22 (1929), pp. 257–272, especially 270–272; Jacques Guy Bougerol, Introduction à Saint Bonaventure (Paris, 1988), pp. 237–238. 2 Unless noted, all citations of the Hexaemeron are from S. Bonaventurae opera omnia, vol. 5, ed. Collegii a S. Bonaventura (Quaracchi, 1889), pp. 327–454, hereafter Hex. 3 Olga Weijers, Terminologie des universités au XIIIe siècle, (Lessico Intellettuale Europeo) 39 (Rome, 1987), pp. 374–375, identifies the Hexaemeron as belonging to the genre of university sermon on a specific theme. Moreover, when a non-regent master delivered the sermons, as is the case with Bonaventure, the collatio resembles a con- ference rather than an official university act of the studia generalia.
    [Show full text]
  • Affect and Ascent in the Theology of Bonaventure
    The Force of Union: Affect and Ascent in the Theology of Bonaventure The Harvard community has made this article openly available. Please share how this access benefits you. Your story matters Citation Davis, Robert. 2012. The Force of Union: Affect and Ascent in the Theology of Bonaventure. Doctoral dissertation, Harvard University. Citable link http://nrs.harvard.edu/urn-3:HUL.InstRepos:9385627 Terms of Use This article was downloaded from Harvard University’s DASH repository, and is made available under the terms and conditions applicable to Other Posted Material, as set forth at http:// nrs.harvard.edu/urn-3:HUL.InstRepos:dash.current.terms-of- use#LAA © 2012 Robert Glenn Davis All rights reserved. iii Amy Hollywood Robert Glenn Davis The Force of Union: Affect and Ascent in the Theology of Bonaventure Abstract The image of love as a burning flame is so widespread in the history of Christian literature as to appear inevitable. But as this dissertation explores, the association of amor with fire played a precise and wide-ranging role in Bonaventure’s understanding of the soul’s motive power--its capacity to love and be united with God, especially as that capacity was demonstrated in an exemplary way through the spiritual ascent and death of St. Francis. In drawing out this association, Bonaventure develops a theory of the soul and its capacity for transformation in union with God that gives specificity to the Christian desire for self-abandonment in God and the annihilation of the soul in union with God. Though Bonaventure does not use the language of the soul coming to nothing, he describes a state of ecstasy or excessus mentis that is possible in this life, but which constitutes the death and transformation of the soul in union with God.
    [Show full text]
  • Sepielli Pragmatism
    PRAGMATISM AND METAETHICS Andrew Sepielli University of Toronto Among analytic philosophers, pragmatism tends to elicit two reactions that might seem to stand in tension with one other. The first reaction is confusion about what pragmatism is, exactly. The second is steadfast rejection of it. It's easier to reconcile these disparate responses when we consider that pragmatism tends to show up under two different guises. The first is as a woolly gestalt, expressed through support for experiment, democracy, fallibilism, and solidarity, and condemnation of authoritarianism, representationalism, Cartesianism, and dogmatic metaphysics. The second is as the simple doctrine that truth is what's good in any way whatsoever to believe. In its first guise, pragmatism tends to provoke confusion; in its second, rejection. As a result, pragmatism occupies at best a precarious position within the mainstream of analytic philosophy. Its influence on contemporary metaethics has been especially weak. My target reader for this article, then, is someone who is familiar with the basic problem- spaces in contemporary metaethics and the moves commonly made within those spaces, but who is not already sympathetic to pragmatism. I want to help such a reader to make sense of pragmatism in some of its many guises, to appreciate both its subtlety and its power as a philosophical stance, and to understand its bearing on some of the main debates within metaethics. !1 of !26 What Is Pragmatism? Let me begin by offering a characterization of pragmatism that will cover as many of those commonly called "pragmatists" as possible without being so capacious as to be useless.
    [Show full text]