Justice: the Most Terrible of the Virtues Be the Normal Accomplishments of Human Moral Growth Acquired for Their Own Sakes

Total Page:16

File Type:pdf, Size:1020Kb

Justice: the Most Terrible of the Virtues Be the Normal Accomplishments of Human Moral Growth Acquired for Their Own Sakes Journal of Markets & Morality Volume 7, Number 2 (Fall 2004): 409–421 Copyright © 2004 Justice: The Most Terrible of the James V. Schall, S.J. Professor of Government Virtues Georgetown University The place of justice among the virtues, both moral and theological, has always been a delicate issue. Machiavellians tend to underestimate or deny its central significance. Contemporary religious rhetoric often tends to exaggerate it. Classi- cal philosophy was ever aware of the ambiguity of justice—its impersonality and rigidity. Unless placed within a higher order of “good,” as Plato saw, or of “charity,” as Aquinas understood, justice introduces an unsettling utopianism into any existing polity. “Mercy and truth are met together; righteousness and peace have kissed each other. Truth shall spring out of the earth; and righteousness shall look down from heaven.” —Psalm 85:10–11 “Summum jus, summa injustitia.” —Cicero, De officiis “Deus misericorditer agit, non quidem contra justitiam suam faciendo, sed aliquid supra justitiam operando.…” —Thomas Aquinas, Summa Theologiae, I, 21, 3, ad 2 In ethical and political affairs, no more frequent or more agonizing word is found than that of justice or its related words fair, equitable, right, or rights. In its own way, of course, justice is also a noble word standing at the height of the practical, not theoretical or theological, virtues. It is also one of the attrib- utes applied to the divinity—God is just. Justice, following Plato, can have a 409 James V. Schall, S.J. very broad scope. It means that everything is voluntarily doing what it ought to do so that the whole may do what it is ordered (that is, designed) to do. Such is the fifth definition of justice in the fourth book of Plato’s Republic. The standard subtitle of this famous dialogue is precisely “On Justice.” Justice is classically treated in the fifth book of Aristotle’s Ethics, wherein he distinguishes between legal or general justice and special justice. In earlier books, he offered an overall description or analysis of virtue and responsibil- ity, together with the vices opposite to each of the virtues.1 Aristotle explained how virtues applied to human action and passion in which they exist as habit- ual guides or moderators. Justice is a virtue, which, unlike courage or temper- ance, does not look inward. Rather, it looks ad alium, to how we stand to another or others besides ourselves when we chance to come into various rela- tionships with them. It implies that our perfection is not something totally dependent on or related to ourselves alone. If we speak of “justice to our- selves,” we mean that we compare or relate what we ought to be with what we in fact are and do. Justice is usually the first virtue that children and youth become aware of, the one that causes most of the loudest controversies existing within families or society. “He took my toy” or “she won’t give me my cake” are protestations frequently heard by parents throughout the world and in all times. Whether the toy is his or the cake hers is itself a controversy about justice. Justice has some- thing strangely incomplete about it, even when it is complete. Shakespeare’s Merchant of Venice was addressed to the potential conflict between justice and charity, to the reasons why the famous “pound of flesh,” even though due in “justice,” was not just in its carrying out.2 Justice seems to overlook excep- tions, something Aristotle discussed under the heading of epichia or equity in the same fifth book of his Ethics. This problem with exceptions also explains, in part, the length and nature of Plato’s dialogue on the Laws, why each law needed a preamble to explain what it was intended to accomplish whatever the words used to describe it. Actually, Aristotle tells us, every virtue or vice, not merely justice and injus- tice, can have an effect on others so that it thereby acquires a justice compo- nent. Thus, it can fall under the law. Our excessive anger or intemperance, for example, can require legal standards and restrictive coercion or penalty. This need is what drunken driving laws, after all, are all about, the combination of temperance and justice. When a virtue is looked upon under the aspect of how it relates to others, it is what Aristotle meant by general or legal justice, an action that could or should be subject to legislation but only under the aspect of justice, not of itself. Actually acquiring and practicing the virtues ought to 410 Justice: The Most Terrible of the Virtues be the normal accomplishments of human moral growth acquired for their own sakes. That is, we should control our eating or drinking even if it had no effect on others. Justice was also its own particular virtue not just an element in the other virtues. It had its own specific realm or object, something that was not merely subjective. It concerned itself with how we stand to others either voluntarily or involuntarily in relationships that, broadly speaking, had to do with exchanges in which something could be measured or at least reasonably estimated. Liberality or generosity was treated in book four of the Ethics. This particular virtue also dealt with something outside of ourselves—with how we handle our wealth or property. This is one of the origins of the term liberal, which meant, in such writers as Locke, that the state was designed to protect our wealth so that we can freely use it. In Aristotle, it meant our being free of our wealth so that we could use it in a reasonable manner when occasion arose. Clearly, property or wealth is something related to justice, at least indi- rectly. In fact, though, liberality is related to wealth as a means to meet the bodily and human needs of finite, corporeal beings, particularly the family. Indeed, liberality, strictly speaking, means that we show in our actions that we sue our wealth for proper or beneficent ends. Chesterton, in a famous essay explaining why he was not a socialist, remarked that he did not want to live in a world in which everything was shared because sharing had attached to it the notion of justice rather than of something beyond justice. He wanted to live in a world in which he could actually give what was really his freely to someone else.3 He also wanted to be able to receive something that was really given to him, not just shared, as if it were a matter of justice. Strictly speaking, justice does not require thanks. Without this economic foundation of freedom, with- out some basic abundance or superfluity, it is impossible to have the virtue of generosity, of liberality. This notion does not mean, however, that the poor cannot be generous or liberal. Often they are more generous proportionately than the rich, a reminder of the story of the widow’s mite in the New Testament (Luke 21:1–4). Liberality, nevertheless, was, like fear and pleasure, still concerned with something more directly related to ourselves, even to our bodies. It noted, too, that there is nothing pejorative or wrong about things naturally related to our- selves. It is good that we exist, as Genesis teaches. Nature also looks to our- selves and to the things needed to be what we are in our flourishing. “No ethi- cally unfavorable connotation attaches to the notion of a need centered about the self…,” Yves Simon has written: “Needs relative to such goods as food and shelter are self-centered by nature.…”4 We have a proper good that needs 411 James V. Schall, S.J. reasonable attention. The common good in principle is not opposed to our pri- vate good. Indeed, one of the purposes of the common good is that private goods, in their proper manner, be achieved by us. One of the basic purposes of authority, as Yves Simon also wrote in his great book, is that it fosters and pro- tects the autonomy of families and smaller institutions.5 Aristotle considered justice itself under two headings. The first was distrib- utive justice; namely, how the general or common goods and burdens were to be equitably divided among the various people within a polity or organization. In this sense, justice, like all virtues, always involved an element of prudence, namely, the discovery of a proper judgment about what this proportion was, more or less. We should not expect, as Aristotle warned us, more certitude of a science than its subject matter will allow (1094b13-15; 1103b28; 1104a3-5). Thus, it was recognized that it was impossible, usually, to have an exact math- ematical relationship, even though Aristotle spoke of distributive justice in terms of geometric proportion and commutative justice, the second form of justice, in terms of mathematical proportion. Aristotle thought that these goods and burdens should be decided in accordance with their relative contributions to a common good. Thus, those who contributed or suffered more deserved more rewards, either spiritual or temporal. Burdens, be it noted, were likewise to be distributed according to some standard of equitable bearing of what commonly needed to be done, in wars, for instance, or in taxation, or in honors. The second form of justice, that is the one with which we are most instinc- tively familiar, the one we learn, or fail to learn, as children, is generally called commutative or rectificatory or rectifying justice. Its classical definition, itself a kind of self-evident principle, is “reddere cuique quod suum est,” to “render to another what is due.” Thus, if I borrow a hundred dollars from you and promise to repay it in a month, then I make right what is unbalanced in our relationship when I pay back the hundred dollars.
Recommended publications
  • SGR VERY Final Version
    PLATO’S EXPLANATORY PREDICATION A Dissertation Presented to the Faculty of the Graduate School of Cornell University in Partial Fulfillment of the Requirements for the Degree of Doctor of Philosophy by Saul Gordon Rosenthal January 2011 © 2011 Saul Gordon Rosenthal All rights reserved PLATO’S EXPLANATORY PREDICATION Saul Gordon Rosenthal, Ph. D. Cornell University 2011 One of the most classic puzzles in Plato’s metaphysics is how to interpret his apparently self-predicational language. Plato seems committed, at least in his middle dialogues, to the view that for all forms, the form of F “is F”. For instance, he seems to say that the form of largeness itself “is large”, and to generalize this claim to all forms. Commentators have struggled to find an interpretation of such claims that is consistent with Plato’s text and that attributes to Plato a view with some plausibility. One aim of this dissertation is to show that we have good reason to doubt all of the most influential interpretations offered by commentators. The views discussed include Narrow Self-Predication, the Tautologous Identity view, two Non- Tautologous Identity views, the Pauline Predication view, Broad Self-Predication, and a view distinguishing different kinds of predication. It is doubtful whether any of these interpretations correctly captures Plato’s self-predicational commitments. Another aim of the dissertation is to argue that the textual evidence most often thought to commit Plato to the Self-Predication Assumption (SP), that for all forms, the form of F is itself an F thing, is insufficient to establish such a commitment. One chapter focuses on Plato’s repeated discussion of the resemblance between form and participant.
    [Show full text]
  • On the Arrangement of the Platonic Dialogues
    Ryan C. Fowler 25th Hour On the Arrangement of the Platonic Dialogues I. Thrasyllus a. Diogenes Laertius (D.L.), Lives and Opinions of Eminent Philosophers 3.56: “But, just as long ago in tragedy the chorus was the only actor, and afterwards, in order to give the chorus breathing space, Thespis devised a single actor, Aeschylus a second, Sophocles a third, and thus tragedy was completed, so too with philosophy: in early times it discoursed on one subject only, namely physics, then Socrates added the second subject, ethics, and Plato the third, dialectics, and so brought philosophy to perfection. Thrasyllus says that he [Plato] published his dialogues in tetralogies, like those of the tragic poets. Thus they contended with four plays at the Dionysia, the Lenaea, the Panathenaea and the festival of Chytri. Of the four plays the last was a satiric drama; and the four together were called a tetralogy.” b. Characters or types of dialogues (D.L. 3.49): 1. instructive (ὑφηγητικός) A. theoretical (θεωρηµατικόν) a. physical (φυσικόν) b. logical (λογικόν) B. practical (πρακτικόν) a. ethical (ἠθικόν) b. political (πολιτικόν) 2. investigative (ζητητικός) A. training the mind (γυµναστικός) a. obstetrical (µαιευτικός) b. tentative (πειραστικός) B. victory in controversy (ἀγωνιστικός) a. critical (ἐνδεικτικός) b. subversive (ἀνατρεπτικός) c. Thrasyllan categories of the dialogues (D.L. 3.50-1): Physics: Timaeus Logic: Statesman, Cratylus, Parmenides, and Sophist Ethics: Apology, Crito, Phaedo, Phaedrus, Symposium, Menexenus, Clitophon, the Letters, Philebus, Hipparchus, Rivals Politics: Republic, the Laws, Minos, Epinomis, Atlantis Obstetrics: Alcibiades 1 and 2, Theages, Lysis, Laches Tentative: Euthyphro, Meno, Io, Charmides and Theaetetus Critical: Protagoras Subversive: Euthydemus, Gorgias, and Hippias 1 and 2 :1 d.
    [Show full text]
  • Gregory Vlastos
    Gregory Vlastos: A Preliminary Inventory of His Papers at the Harry Ransom Center Descriptive Summary Creator: Vlastos, Gregory, 1907-1991 Title: Gregory Vlastos Papers Dates: circa 1930s-1991 Extent: 100 document boxes (42.00 linear feet) Abstract: The papers of philosopher Gregory Vlastos, a scholar of ancient Greek philosophy who spent most of his career studying the thought of Plato and Socrates, document his studies, his writings, and his career as an educator at several American universities. Call Number: Manuscript Collection MS-4361 Language: English, with Ancient Greek, French, German, Italian, Latin, Modern Greek, and Spanish Access: Open for research Administrative Information Acquisition: Gifts, 1993-2010 (G9070, G9134, G9163, G9225, G9252, G9628, G9979, G9982, G10214, G10288, G11877, 10-03-014-G) Processed by: Hope Rider, 2006; updated by Joan Sibley, 2016 Repository: The University of Texas at Austin, Harry Ransom Center Vlastos, Gregory, 1907-1991 Manuscript Collection MS-4361 Scope and Contents The papers of philosopher Gregory Vlastos (1907-1991), a scholar of ancient Greek philosophy who spent most of his career studying the thought of Plato and Socrates, document his studies, his writings, and his career as an educator at several American universities, especially Cornell, Princeton, and The University of California at Berkeley. The papers are arranged in six series: I. Correspondence and Offprint Files, II. Study, Lecture, and Teaching Files, III. Works, IV. Works by Others, V. Miscellaneous, and VI. Offprints Removed from Manuscripts. The Correspondence and Offprint Files (35 boxes) in Series I. represent Vlastos' extensive correspondence with other philosophers, classicists, former students, academics, and others. The files are arranged alphabetically by correspondent name, and generally include not only letters received, but copies of Vlastos' responses.
    [Show full text]
  • Plato's Critique of Injustice in the Gorgias and the Republic
    Plato's critique of injustice in the Gorgias and the Republic Author: Jonathan Frederick Culp Persistent link: http://hdl.handle.net/2345/972 This work is posted on eScholarship@BC, Boston College University Libraries. Boston College Electronic Thesis or Dissertation, 2008 Copyright is held by the author, with all rights reserved, unless otherwise noted. Boston College The Graduate School of Arts and Sciences Department of Political Science PLATO’S CRITIQUE OF INJUSTICE IN THE GORGIAS AND THE REPUBLIC a dissertation by JONATHAN FREDERICK CULP submitted in partial fulfillment of the requirements for the degree of Doctor of Philosophy August 2008 © Copyright by JONATHAN FREDERICK CULP 2008 Plato’s Critique of Injustice in the Gorgias and the Republic Jonathan Frederick Culp Advisor: Professor Christopher Bruell No rational decision can be made concerning how to live without confronting the problem of justice—both what it is and whether it is good to be just. In this essay I examine Plato’s articulation of these problems in the Gorgias and the Republic. Through detailed analyses of Socrates’ exchanges with several interlocutors, I establish, first, that despite some real and apparent differences, all the interlocutors share the same fundamental conception of justice, which could be called justice as fairness or reciprocal equality (to ison). The core of justice lies in refraining from pleonexia (seeking to benefit oneself at the expense of another). Second, according to this view, the practice of justice is not intrinsically profitable; it is valuable only as a means to the acquisition or enjoyment of other, material goods. This conception thus implies that committing successful injustice is often more profitable than being just.
    [Show full text]
  • Justice for Juveniles
    If you have issues viewing or accessing this file contact us at NCJRS.gov. )OS!, 7 JUSTICE FOR JUVENILES Charles E. Springer Vice-Chief Justice Supreme Court of Nevada ~ " :tment of Justice lvenile Justice and Delinquency Prevention OJJDP Ie * JUSTICE FOR JUVENILES Charles E. Springer Vice-Chief Justice Supreme Court of Nevada U.S. Department of Justice Office of Juvenile Justice and Delinquency Prevention OJJDP II ,I;' - c :;;w '&-••1\'£:-.' ¥W, Charles E. Springer is Vice-Chief Justice of the Supreme Court of the State of Nevada. Prior to being commissioned to the Supreme Court, he was Juvenile Court Master for the Second Judicial District Court for the State of Nevada from 1973 to 1980. He has also served the State of Nevada as Attorney General. He received the Outstanding Service Award from the National Council of Juvenile and Family Court Judges in 1980 and has served on the Boards and Commissions of numerous civic and State organizations in an effort to improve the quality of justice for adults and juveniles . ........ * & & !MI',. u. S. ~partment of Justice Office of Juvenile Justice and Delinquency Prevention NmionallnslituJejiJr Juvenile Justice and Delinquency Prevention Juvenile Ju.rl;" Cfrorin8/w"''' NCJRS Box6000. Rochill<. MD 20lJjO Dear Colleague: "Justice for Juveniles" is a serious and deliberative look at the juvenile justice systeln, its philosophical and historical underpinnings, the strengths and weaknesses of today's system, and the implications for its future. Last year over 35,000 juveniles were arrested in this country for violent crimes, including murder, rape, and aggravated assault. The success of this office's e~forts to reduce juvenile crime and create a nlore secure society depends on the ready exchange of information and ideas among professionals in the field.
    [Show full text]
  • Ethics and Moral Choices Ethics, Morality and Religion, Socrates Versus Abrahamic Religions
    ETHICS AND MORAL CHOICES ETHICS, MORALITY AND RELIGION, SOCRATES VERSUS ABRAHAMIC RELIGIONS BY PARVIZ DEHGHANI The dialogue between Euthyphro and Socrates has captured the imagination of many Western philosophers since Plato wrote it more than two thousand years ago. Socrates meets young Euthyphro on the steps of the same court where he would be sentenced to death. The false allegations were he had been involved in corrupting the youth, turning his back to the gods of Athens and secretly admiring the Persian monarchical system as opposed to the democracy of his day and Spartans' firm belief in their gods and causes. After all, Athens had been invaded by both armies in the past and were considered the enemies by the Athenians. Apparently Socrates wanted to keep his friends close and his enemies closer. Because for him the truth was more important than patriotism. He never desired to be politically correct. He asked Euthyphro as to why he was sitting on the steps? Euthyphro answered Socrates by saying that he was about to go to the court and indict his father. Why, Socrates asked? Because my father captured a murderer and left him in a ditch with his hands tied up behind him and ran to bring in authorities. But by the time he was back, the murderer was dead due to excessive heat and hunger. Socrates being a man of discernment could not let such an opportunity slip. So he began engaging Euthyphro in a dialogue in order to let the truth emerge. Do you realize what you're doing, Socrates asked? After all he is your father.
    [Show full text]
  • This Course on Plato Provides an In-Depth Account of This Seminal Thinker’S Philosophy
    PLATO PHILO 380(W) Dr. V. Adluri Sec. 001 [4921] Office: Hunter West, 12th floor, Room 1242 Spring 2009 Telephone: 973 216 7874 Prof. Adluri Email: [email protected] Monday/Wednesday, 4:10-5:25pm Office hours: Wednesdays, 6:00 – 7:00 P.M and by appointment DESCRIPTION: This course on Plato provides an in-depth account of this seminal thinker’s philosophy. Major themes such as the nature of knowledge, soul, universe, city, God, language, love, and art will be discussed based on selections from all of his dialogues. Plato’s relationship to Pre- Socratic philosophy, especially Parmenides and Heraclitus will be discussed. We will pay special attention to Plato’s use of the dialogic form and its main protagonist: Socrates. In the second half of the course, we will read the Republic in detail, with special attention to the legacy of Plato’s thought in the history of Western Philosophy. Required Text: Plato. Complete Works. Edited by John Cooper. Indianapolis: Hackett Publishing Company, 1997. $54. All textbooks are on order at Shakespeare & Co. Booksellers (939 Lexington Avenue between 68th and 69th streets; 212 570 0201). Shakespeare & Co. also has a limited number of used copies available at lower prices. COURSE OBJECTIVES: This course is intended to give students a basic familiarity with the Platonic corpus and an in-depth knowledge of the Republic. In the first half of the course, students will gain a basic familiarity with Platonic philosophy, including its method of argumentation, its ultimate aims, and its wider political and literary context. We will then apply these insights to a close- reading of the Republic.
    [Show full text]
  • Plato's Meno (2005)
    PLATO’S MENO Given its brevity, Plato’s Meno covers an astonishingly wide array of topics: politics, education, virtue, definition, philosophical method, mathematics, the nature and acquisition of knowledge, and immor- tality. Its treatment of these, though profound, is tantalizingly short, leaving the reader with many unresolved questions. This book con- fronts the dialogue’s many enigmas and attempts to solve them in a way that is both lucid and sympathetic to Plato’s philosophy. Reading the dialogue as a whole, it explains how different arguments are related to one another, and how the interplay between characters is connected to the philosophical content of the work. In a new departure, this book’s exploration focuses primarily on the content and coherence of the dialogue in its own right, and not merely in the context of other dialogues, making it required reading for all students of Plato, be they from the world of classics or philosophy. dominic scott is Senior Lecturer in Philosophy at the University of Cambridge and a Fellow of Clare College. His previous publications include Recollection and Experience: Plato’s Theory of Learning and its Successors (Cambridge, 1995). cambridge studies in the dialogues of plato Series editor: Mary Margaret McCabe Plato’s dialogues are rich mixtures of subtle argument, sublime theorising and superb literature. It is tempting to read them piecemeal – by analysing the argu- ments, by espousing or rejecting the theories or by praising Plato’s literary expertise. It is equally tempting to search for Platonic views across dialogues, selecting pas- sages from throughout the Platonic corpus.
    [Show full text]
  • Handbook on Justice for Victims Was Developed in Response to That Resolution
    This Handbook was prepared by a group of experts from more than 40 countries at a series of meetings supported by the Office for Victims of Crime in the United States Department of Justice and the Ministry of Justice in the Netherlands. The document was developed in cooperation with the United Nations Office at Vienna, Centre for International Crime Prevention, Office for Drug Control and Crime Prevention, and its publication was generously funded by the Office for Victims of Crime, United States Department of Justice. Foreword Crime takes an enormous physical, financial and emotional toll on its victims. On 29 November 1985, the General Assembly of the United Nations adopted the Declaration of Basic Principles of Justice for Victims of Crime and Abuse of Power (General Assembly resolution 40/34, annex) based on the conviction that victims should be treated with compassion and respect for their dignity and that they are entitled to prompt redress for the harm that they have suffered, through access to the criminal justice system, reparation and services to assist their recovery. The Declaration recommends measures to be taken on behalf of victims of crime at the international, regional and national levels to improve access to justice and fair treatment, restitution, compensation and assistance. It also outlines the main steps to be taken to prevent victimization linked to abuse of power and to provide remedies for the victims. In May 1996, the United Nations Commission on Crime Prevention and Criminal Justice, at its fifth session, adopted a resolution to develop a manual or manuals on the use and application of the Declaration (Economic and Social Council resolution 1996/14).
    [Show full text]
  • The Republic of Plato
    THE REPUBLIC OF PLATO 'I'IlANSLATBD WInI INTJtODUCTlON AND NOTES BY FRANCIS MACDONALD CORNFORD LrrrD., F.B.A. Fellow of Trinity CoI1ege, Cambric:Igc OXFORD UNIVERSITY PRESS LONDON OXFORD NEW YORK OXFORD UN IVERSITY PRESS Oxford london New York Glasgow Toronto Melbourne Wellington Cape Town Salisbury Ibadan Nairobi lusaka Addis Ababa Bombay Calcutta Madras Karachi lahore Dacca Kuala lumpur Hong Kong Tokyo First published by Oxford University Press, london, 1941 First issued as an Oxford University Press paperback, 1945 This reprint, 1970-3 Printed in the United States of America CONTENTS Page xv PART I (Book I). SOME CURRENT VIEWS OF JUSTICE CHAP. I (i. 32?-33I D). Cephalus. Justice as Honesty in word and darl 2 II (331 E-336 A). Polemarchus. Justice as Helping Friends and Harming Enemies • 7 III (336 B-347 E). Thrasymachus. Justice as the Interest of the Stronger 14 IV (347 E-354 c). Thrasymachus. Is Injustice more profitable than Justice? 30 PART II (Books II-IV, 445 B). JUSTICE IN THE STATE AND IN THE INDIVIDUAL V (ii. 357 A-367 E). The Problem stated 41 VI (367 E-372 A). The Rudiments of Social Organization 53 VII (372 A-374 E). The Luxurious State 59 VIII (375 A-376 E). The Guardian's Temperament 63 IX (376 E-iii. 412 B). Primary Education of the Guardians 66 § 1 (376 E-iii. 392 c). Censorship of Literature for School Use 67 § 2 (392 c-398 B). The Influence of Dramatic Recitation 80 § 3 (398 c-4°O c). Musical Accompaniment and Metre 85 § 4 ("00 c-403 c).
    [Show full text]
  • The Wisdom of Noble Simplicity
    The Εὐηθέστεροι Myth: the Wisdom of Noble Simplicity L. M. J. Coulson A Thesis Submitted in Fulfilment of the Requirements for the Degree of Doctor of Philosophy Department of Classics and Ancient History School of Philosophical and Historical Inquiry Faculty of Arts and Social Sciences The University of Sydney November 2016 Statement of Originality This is to certify that to the best of my knowledge, the content of this thesis is my own work. This thesis has not been submitted for any degree or other purposes. I certify that the intellectual content of this thesis is the product of my own work and that all the assistance received in preparing this thesis and sources have been acknowledged. L. M. J. Coulson November 2016 i Acknowledgements Throughout this undertaking it has been my great good fortune and privilege to have the gracious and generous support of my family, supervisors and colleagues. On November 5, 2012 Professor Eric Csapo and I met for the first time. At that meeting Eric suggested the apparently paradoxical use of εὐήθεια in Ancient Greece as a postgraduate research topic. This thesis is a direct consequence of his suggestion, encouragement and forbearance. Eric’s erudition in the Classics’ disciplines is extraordinary and gives constant cause for admiration. Professor Rick Benitez is officially designated as my auxiliary supervisor. However, he has been far more that that, especially in the last year of this project when the depth of his Platonic scholarship and generous support made an invaluable contribution to the completion of this thesis. I am grateful for the opportunity to have worked closely with these exceptional scholars.
    [Show full text]
  • The Meno, Recollection, and the Role of Hypothesis Joseph A
    Binghamton University The Open Repository @ Binghamton (The ORB) The ocS iety for Ancient Greek Philosophy Newsletter 4-29-2005 The eM no, Recollection, and the Role of Hypothesis Joseph A. Novak University of Waterloo, [email protected] Follow this and additional works at: https://orb.binghamton.edu/sagp Part of the Ancient History, Greek and Roman through Late Antiquity Commons, Ancient Philosophy Commons, and the History of Philosophy Commons Recommended Citation Novak, Joseph A., "The eM no, Recollection, and the Role of Hypothesis" (2005). The Society for Ancient Greek Philosophy Newsletter. 346. https://orb.binghamton.edu/sagp/346 This Article is brought to you for free and open access by The Open Repository @ Binghamton (The ORB). It has been accepted for inclusion in The Society for Ancient Greek Philosophy Newsletter by an authorized administrator of The Open Repository @ Binghamton (The ORB). For more information, please contact [email protected]. The Meno, Recollection, and the Role of Hypothesis Joseph A. Novak, University of Waterloo (CANADA) Presented to the SAGP at its April 2005 meeting with the Central Division of the APA, Chicago, IL. Although memory and recollection are topics discussed by some of the chief figures in Western Philosophy, there are few treatises devoted to a thorough examination of these two. Aristotle's treatise is one exception in that it captures these two topics in its very title: De Memoria et Reminiscentia. However, this is a relatively short work and other treatments and references to these two notions within the Aristotelian corpus are not that extensive. One should not infer from this that memory does not play an important role in Aristotle's philosophy nor that memory is considered an insignificant cognitive ability.
    [Show full text]