Schrödinger Equation Revisited

Total Page:16

File Type:pdf, Size:1020Kb

Schrödinger Equation Revisited Schrödinger equation revisited Wolfgang P. Schleicha,b, Daniel M. Greenbergera,c, Donald H. Kobeb, and Marlan O. Scullyd,e,f,1 aInstitut für Quantenphysik and Center for Integrated Quantum Science and Technology (IQST), Universität Ulm, D-89069 Ulm, Germany; bDepartment of Physics, University of North Texas, Denton, TX 76203-1427; cCity College of the City University of New York, New York, NY 10031; dTexas A&M University, College Station, TX 77843; ePrinceton University, Princeton, NJ 08544; and fBaylor University, Waco, TX 97096 Contributed by Marlan O. Scully, February 8, 2013 (sent for review November 8, 2012) The time-dependent Schrödinger equation is a cornerstone of quan- i) Starting from the nonlinear wave equation (Eq. 2), we as- tum physics and governs all phenomena of the microscopic world. sume that we search for a wave equation for a scalar wave However, despite its importance, its origin is still not widely ap- containing only a first-order derivative in time and a second- preciated and properly understood. We obtain the Schrödinger order derivative in space, and we establish a mathematical equation from a mathematical identity by a slight generalization identity involving derivatives of a complex-valued field. of the formulation of classical statistical mechanics based on the ii) A description (16–20) of classical statistical mechanics in Hamilton–Jacobi equation. This approach brings out most clearly terms of a classical matter wave whose phase is given by the fact that the linearity of quantum mechanics is intimately con- the classical action and is governed by the Hamilton–Jacobi nected to the strong coupling between the amplitude and phase equation (21), and whose amplitude is defined by the square of a quantum wave. root of the Van Vleck determinant (22) and satisfies a con- tinuity equation (16–18, 22, 23), leads via our mathematical he birth of the time-dependent Schrödinger equation was identity to a nonlinear wave equation. iii perhaps not unlike the birth of a river. Often, it is difficult to ) However, a linear wave equation (i.e., the Schrödinger equa- T tion) emerges from our mathematical identity when we cou- locate uniquely its spring despite the fact that signs may officially ple amplitude and phase in a democratic way (i.e., the phase mark its beginning. Usually, many bubbling brooks and streams determines the dynamics of the amplitude, and vice versa). merge suddenly to form a mighty river. In the case of quantum mechanics, there are so many convincing experimental results that It is this mutual coupling between amplitude and phase that PHYSICS many of the major textbooks do not really motivate the subject. defines a quantum matter wave and ensures the linearity of the Instead, they often simply postulate the classical-to-quantum wave equation. Indeed, in the classical matter wave, this coupling rules as is broken; the phase still determines, via the continuity equation, the dynamics of the amplitude, but the equation of motion of the ∂ Z phase (i.e., the Hamilton–Jacobi equation) is independent of the E! Z p! V i ∂t and amplitude. It is for this reason that the wave equation is nonlinear. i Our article is organized as follows: we first establish the math- ematical identity and then turn to the nonlinear wave equation E p Z ’ for the energy and momentum ,where is Planck s con- corresponding to a classical matter wave; the next section is π stant divided by 2 and operators are understood as acting dedicated to the task of arriving at the linear Schrödinger equa- ψ = ψ r t on the wave function ( , ). The reason given is that tion; and we conclude by summarizing our results and providing “ ” it works. an outlook. For example, the Schrödinger equation is then obtained (1, 2) To focus on the essential ideas, we have moved detailed cal- H ≡ p2 m + V from the classical Hamiltonian /(2 ) for a particle of culations or introductory material to an appendix. In the first mass m in a potential V = V(r, t)as section (Appendix), we use standard relations of vector calculus to obtain the building blocks of our mathematical identity. In the ∂ψ Z2 second section (Appendix), we provide more insight into the Van iZ = − V2ψ + Vψ: [1] ∂t 2m Vleck determinant by considering a 1D description. This approach is unfortunate. Many of us recall feeling dis- Mathematical Identity satisfied with this recipe. In this section, we formulate the problem and spell out our as- It was the left-hand side of Eq. 1 that was the sticking point for sumptions about the wave equation. We then obtain the mathe- Schrödinger (3–7). Wave equations usually involved second time matical identity, which is at the heart of our approach toward the derivatives. It is thus somewhat ironic that classical mechanics à Schrödinger equation. la the Hamilton–Jacobi equation yield a nonlinear wave equation Our goal is to obtain a wave equation for matter. For this that is similar to Eq. 1, namely, purpose, we consider the most elementary case of a scalar particle described by a single complex-valued function ð Þ 2 h i ∂ψ cl Z θðr;tÞ iZ = − V2ψ ðclÞ + Vψ ðclÞ + Q ψ ðclÞ ψ ðclÞ: [2] Z = Zðr; tÞ ≡ Aðr; tÞei ; [3] ∂t 2m (cl) consisting of the real-valued and positive amplitude A = A(r, t) Here, Q is a nonlinear potential that depends on ψ (Eq. 14). and the real-valued phase θ = θ(r, t). Here, r combines the The basis for Eq. 2 is the fact that energy and momentum are – Cartesian coordinates of the particle in three space dimensions obtained from the Hamilton Jacobi theory by taking time and and t is the coordinate time. space derivatives of the action, as we discuss in the following. There are, of course, many ways (8–15) in which to obtain the time-dependent Schrödinger equation, with the most prominent Author contributions: W.P.S., D.M.G., D.H.K., and M.O.S. designed research, performed being the one developed by Feynman (14) based on the path research, and wrote the paper. integral. In this article, we obtain the Schrödinger equation The authors declare no conflict of interest. (Eq. 1) and discuss the connection with Eq. 2 in three steps: 1To whom correspondence should be addressed. E-mail: [email protected]. www.pnas.org/cgi/doi/10.1073/pnas.1302475110 PNAS Early Edition | 1of6 Downloaded by guest on September 28, 2021 cl At this point, the use of a complex, rather than a real, valued S(cl) ≡ S( )(r, α, t) denotes the classical action and the vector α wave is by no means obvious. However, this choice will become combines three constants of the motion. clear in the next section when we discuss classical matter waves. Indeed, the Hamilton–Jacobi equation (Eq. 7) is a partial dif- Indeed, our treatment will show that we use a complex function ferential equation of the first order in the three Cartesian coor- as a very efficient shorthand notation to combine two coupled dinates xk with k = 1, 2, and 3 and time. Hence, we expect its real-valued equations into a single equation. solution to depend on 3 + 1 = 4 independent constants αl of in- (cl) Wave equations contain derivatives with respect to the space tegration. Because only derivatives of S enter into the differ- α and time coordinates. For example, the familiar wave equation ential equation, we can always add a constant 0 to any solution (cl) for an electromagnetic wave involves second-order derivatives of S and obtain another solution. When we disregard this trivial with respect to space and time. However, we now consider the constant of integration, we arrive at only three, that is, one for N fi more elementary case of a wave equation with only a first-order each coordinate. Obviously, in the case of coordinates, we nd N α derivative with respect to time but second-order derivatives with constants l of integration. respect to space. Most relevant for the present problem of obtaining a wave 7 – In Appendix, we establish the identities equation is the fact that Eq. implies (16 18, 22, 23) the Van Vleck continuity equation ∂Z ∂ ∂θ i 2 i = A − Z [4] ∂ VSðclÞ ∂t 2 A2 ∂t ∂t D + V · D = ; [8] ∂t m 0 and where À Á V2A i 2 V2Z = V · A2Vθ − ðVθÞ + Z; [5] ∂2SðclÞ A2 A D ≡ [9] ∂xk∂αl which follow when we complete the differentiations on the right- hand sides of these equations, together with the representation denotes the Van Vleck determinant. (Eq. 3) of the complex-valued function Z in terms of the ampli- In Appendix, we motivate this conservation law by deriving it for tude A and the phase θ. a 1D motion. For the more complicated case of N coordinates and Because the first-order time derivative and the second-order N constants of integration, we refer to other sources (16–18, 22, 23). space derivative given by the Laplacian of Z have different − − dimensions, that is, [time] 1 vs. [space] 2, we need to introduce Nonlinear Wave Equation. Next, we note that the expression in the fi a constant β when we add the two derivatives. In this way, we rst square bracket on the right-hand side of the mathematical 6 arrive at the mathematical identity identity (Eq. ) is identical to the left-hand side of the Van Vleck continuity equation (Eq. 8), provided D ≡ A2 and 2βθ ≡ S(cl)/m. S(cl) ∂Z 1 ∂ À Á This feature, together with the fact that the classical action i + βV2Z = i A2 + 2βV · A2Vθ defines wave fronts, suggests consideration (16–18) of a wave ∂t 2 A2 ∂t [6] 2 ∂θ V A ðclÞ i + − − βðVθÞ2 + β Z: ψ ðclÞ ≡ AðclÞeiθ ≡ D1=2exp SðclÞ [10] ∂t A Z Because A and θ are real, the expressions in the two square whose amplitude A(cl) ≡ D1/2 is the square root of the Van Vleck brackets on the right-hand side of Eq.
Recommended publications
  • Quantum Theory Cannot Consistently Describe the Use of Itself
    ARTICLE DOI: 10.1038/s41467-018-05739-8 OPEN Quantum theory cannot consistently describe the use of itself Daniela Frauchiger1 & Renato Renner1 Quantum theory provides an extremely accurate description of fundamental processes in physics. It thus seems likely that the theory is applicable beyond the, mostly microscopic, domain in which it has been tested experimentally. Here, we propose a Gedankenexperiment 1234567890():,; to investigate the question whether quantum theory can, in principle, have universal validity. The idea is that, if the answer was yes, it must be possible to employ quantum theory to model complex systems that include agents who are themselves using quantum theory. Analysing the experiment under this presumption, we find that one agent, upon observing a particular measurement outcome, must conclude that another agent has predicted the opposite outcome with certainty. The agents’ conclusions, although all derived within quantum theory, are thus inconsistent. This indicates that quantum theory cannot be extrapolated to complex systems, at least not in a straightforward manner. 1 Institute for Theoretical Physics, ETH Zurich, 8093 Zurich, Switzerland. Correspondence and requests for materials should be addressed to R.R. (email: [email protected]) NATURE COMMUNICATIONS | (2018) 9:3711 | DOI: 10.1038/s41467-018-05739-8 | www.nature.com/naturecommunications 1 ARTICLE NATURE COMMUNICATIONS | DOI: 10.1038/s41467-018-05739-8 “ 1”〉 “ 1”〉 irect experimental tests of quantum theory are mostly Here, | z ¼À2 D and | z ¼þ2 D denote states of D depending restricted to microscopic domains. Nevertheless, quantum on the measurement outcome z shown by the devices within the D “ψ ”〉 “ψ ”〉 theory is commonly regarded as being (almost) uni- lab.
    [Show full text]
  • Appendix: the Interaction Picture
    Appendix: The Interaction Picture The technique of expressing operators and quantum states in the so-called interaction picture is of great importance in treating quantum-mechanical problems in a perturbative fashion. It plays an important role, for example, in the derivation of the Born–Markov master equation for decoherence detailed in Sect. 4.2.2. We shall review the basics of the interaction-picture approach in the following. We begin by considering a Hamiltonian of the form Hˆ = Hˆ0 + V.ˆ (A.1) Here Hˆ0 denotes the part of the Hamiltonian that describes the free (un- perturbed) evolution of a system S, whereas Vˆ is some added external per- turbation. In applications of the interaction-picture formalism, Vˆ is typically assumed to be weak in comparison with Hˆ0, and the idea is then to deter- mine the approximate dynamics of the system given this assumption. In the following, however, we shall proceed with exact calculations only and make no assumption about the relative strengths of the two components Hˆ0 and Vˆ . From standard quantum theory, we know that the expectation value of an operator observable Aˆ(t) is given by the trace rule [see (2.17)], & ' & ' ˆ ˆ Aˆ(t) =Tr Aˆ(t)ˆρ(t) =Tr Aˆ(t)e−iHtρˆ(0)eiHt . (A.2) For reasons that will immediately become obvious, let us rewrite this expres- sion as & ' ˆ ˆ ˆ ˆ ˆ ˆ Aˆ(t) =Tr eiH0tAˆ(t)e−iH0t eiH0te−iHtρˆ(0)eiHte−iH0t . (A.3) ˆ In inserting the time-evolution operators e±iH0t at the beginning and the end of the expression in square brackets, we have made use of the fact that the trace is cyclic under permutations of the arguments, i.e., that Tr AˆBˆCˆ ··· =Tr BˆCˆ ···Aˆ , etc.
    [Show full text]
  • Quantum Violation of Classical Physics in Macroscopic Systems
    Quantum VIOLATION OF CLASSICAL PHYSICS IN MACROSCOPIC SYSTEMS Lucas Clemente Ludwig Maximilian University OF Munich Max Planck INSTITUTE OF Quantum Optics Quantum VIOLATION OF CLASSICAL PHYSICS IN MACROSCOPIC SYSTEMS Lucas Clemente Dissertation AN DER Fakultät für Physik DER Ludwig-Maximilians-Universität München VORGELEGT VON Lucas Clemente AUS München München, IM NoVEMBER 2015 TAG DER mündlichen Prüfung: 26. Januar 2016 Erstgutachter: Prof. J. IGNACIO Cirac, PhD Zweitgutachter: Prof. Dr. Jan VON Delft WEITERE Prüfungskommissionsmitglieder: Prof. Dr. HarALD Weinfurter, Prof. Dr. Armin Scrinzi Reality is that which, when you stop believing in it, doesn’t go away. “ — Philip K. Dick How To Build A Universe That Doesn’t Fall Apart Two Days Later, a speech published in the collection I Hope I Shall Arrive Soon Contents Abstract xi Zusammenfassung xiii List of publications xv Acknowledgments xvii 0 Introduction 1 0.1 History and motivation . 3 0.2 Local realism and Bell’s theorem . 5 0.3 Contents of this thesis . 10 1 Conditions for macrorealism 11 1.1 Macroscopic realism . 13 1.2 Macrorealism per se following from strong non-invasive measurability 15 1.3 The Leggett-Garg inequality . 17 1.4 No-signaling in time . 19 1.5 Necessary and sufficient conditions for macrorealism . 21 1.6 No-signaling in time for quantum measurements . 25 1.6.1 Without time evolution . 26 1.6.2 With time evolution . 27 1.7 Conclusion and outlook . 28 Appendix 31 1.A Proof that NSIT0(1)2 is sufficient for NIC0(1)2 . 31 2 Macroscopic classical dynamics from microscopic quantum behavior 33 2.1 Quantifying violations of classicality .
    [Show full text]
  • Particle Or Wave: There Is No Evidence of Single Photon Delayed Choice
    Particle or wave: there is no evidence of single photon delayed choice. Michael Devereux* Los Alamos National Laboratory (Retired) Abstract Wheeler supposed that the way in which a single photon is measured in the present could determine how it had behaved in the past. He named such retrocausation delayed choice. Over the last forty years many experimentalists have claimed to have observed single-photon delayed choice. Recently, however, researchers have proven that the quantum wavefunction of a single photon assumes the identical mathematical form of the solution to Maxwell’s equations for that photon. This efficacious understanding allows for a trenchant analysis of delayed-choice experiments and denies their retrocausation conclusions. It is now usual for physicists to employ Bohr’s wave-particle complementarity theory to distinguish wave from particle aspects in delayed- choice observations. Nevertheless, single-photon, delayed-choice experiments, provide no evidence that the photon actually acts like a particle, or, instead, like a wave, as a function of a future measurement. And, a recent, careful, Stern-Gerlach analysis has shown that the supposition of concurrent wave and particle characteristics in the Bohm-DeBroglie theory is not tenable. PACS 03.65.Ta, 03.65.Ud 03.67.-a, 42.50.Ar, 42.50.Xa 1. Introduction. Almost forty years ago Wheeler suggested that there exists a type of retrocausation, which he called delayed choice, in certain physical phenomena [1]. Specifically, he said that the past behavior of some quantum systems could be determined by how they are observed in the present. “The past”, he wrote, “has no existence except as it is recorded in the present” [2].
    [Show full text]
  • New Journal of Physics the Open–Access Journal for Physics
    New Journal of Physics The open–access journal for physics The rise and fall of redundancy in decoherence and quantum Darwinism C Jess Riedel1,2,5, Wojciech H Zurek1,3 and Michael Zwolak1,4 1 Theoretical Division/CNLS, LANL, Los Alamos, NM 87545, USA 2 Department of Physics, University of California, Santa Barbara, CA 93106, USA 3 Santa Fe Institute, Santa Fe, NM 87501, USA 4 Department of Physics, Oregon State University, Corvallis, OR 97331, USA E-mail: [email protected] New Journal of Physics 14 (2012) 083010 (20pp) Received 9 March 2012 Published 10 August 2012 Online at http://www.njp.org/ doi:10.1088/1367-2630/14/8/083010 Abstract. A state selected at random from the Hilbert space of a many-body system is overwhelmingly likely to exhibit highly non-classical correlations. For these typical states, half of the environment must be measured by an observer to determine the state of a given subsystem. The objectivity of classical reality—the fact that multiple observers can agree on the state of a subsystem after measuring just a small fraction of its environment—implies that the correlations found in nature between macroscopic systems and their environments are exceptional. Building on previous studies of quantum Darwinism showing that highly redundant branching states are produced ubiquitously during pure decoherence, we examine the conditions needed for the creation of branching states and study their demise through many-body interactions. We show that even constrained dynamics can suppress redundancy to the values typical of random states on relaxation timescales, and prove that these results hold exactly in the thermodynamic limit.
    [Show full text]
  • Decoherence and Its Role in Interpretations of Quantum Physics
    Decoherence and its Role in Interpretations of Quantum Physics Simon Matthew Thomas Newey Submitted in Accordance with the Requirements for the Degree of Doctor of Philosophy University of Leeds School of Philosophy, Religion and History of Science February 2019 2 The candidate confirms that the work submitted is his/her/their own and that appropriate credit has been given where reference has been made to the work of others. This copy has been supplied on the understanding that it is copyright material and that no quotation from the thesis may be published without proper acknowledgement. The right of Simon Mathew Thomas Newey to be identified as Author of this work has been asserted by Simon Mathew Thomas Newey in accordance with the Copyright, Designs and Patents Act 1988 3 Acknowledgements I would like to thank my supervisors Juha Saatsi and Stephen French for their patience, support and guidance over the last four years. I am grateful to the Arts and Humanities Research Council for funding this project. I am also grateful for helpful and interesting conversations I have had over the last four years with Callum Duguid, Guido Bacciagaluppi, Karim Thébault, Richard Dawid, and Simon Saunders. 4 Abstract The purpose of this thesis is to examine different conceptions of decoherence and their significance within interpretations of quantum mechanics. I set out three different conceptions of decoherence found in the literature and examine the relations between them. I argue that only the weakest of these conceptions is empirically well supported, and that the other two rely on claims about the structure of the histories (robust patterns within the wavefunction) which we occupy which require justification.
    [Show full text]
  • Decoherence: an Explanation of Quantum Measurement
    Decoherence: An Explanation of Quantum Measurement Jason Gross\ast Massachusetts Institute of Technology, 77 Massachusetts Ave., Cambridge, MA 02139-4307 (Dated: May 5, 2012) The description of the world given by quantum mechanics is at odds with our classical experience. Most of this conflict resides in the concept of \measurement". After explaining the originsof the controversy, and introducing and explaining some of the relevant mathematics behind density matrices and partial trace, I will introduce decoherence as a way of describing classical measurements from an entirely quantum perspective. I will discuss basis ambiguity and the problem of information flow in a system + observer model, and explain how introducing the environment removes this ambiguity via environmentally-induced superselection. I will use a controlled not gate as a toy model of measurement; including a one-bit environment will provide an example of how interaction can pick out a preferred basis, and included an N-bit environment will give a toy model of decoherence. I. INTRODUCTION function over each independent observable. Moreover, the law of superposition, which states that any linear For any physicist who learns classical mechanics before combination of valid quantum states is also valid, gives quantum mechanics, the theory of quantum mechanics at rise to states that do not seem to correspond to any clas- first appears to be a strange and counter-intuitive wayto sical system anyone has experienced. The most famous describe the world. The correspondence between classical example of such a state is that of Schr\"odinger'shypo- experience and quantum theory is not obvious, and has thetical cat, which is in a superposition of being alive been at the core of debates about the interpretation of and being dead.
    [Show full text]
  • Quantum Theory of the Classical
    QUANTUM THEORY OF THE CLASSICAL Wojciech Hubert Zurek (to be continued by Mike Zwolak and Jess Ridel) “BEYOND DECOHERENCE” Quantum Jumps (discrete outcomes from unitary evolutions) Quantum Origins of Probability (from entanglement) Quantum Darwinism (the origin of “objective reality”) WHZ, Nature Physics March 2009 Quantum Theory of the Classical PROGRAM: Take the core “quantum” postulates of textbook * quantum theory and investigate whether they can account for the quantum-classical transition. 0. State of a composite system is a vector in the Q tensor product of constituent Hilbert spaces. U C 1. States correspond to vectors in Hilbert space. A R (“Quantum Superposition Principle”) N E 2. Evolutions are unitary (e.g. generated by T D Schroedinger equation). (“Unitarity”) U O 3. Immediate repetition of a measurement } M yields the same outcome. (“Repeatability”) 4. (a) Outcomes are restricted to orthonormal states {|sk>} (eigenstates of the measured observable). (b) One outcome is seen each time. 2 5. Probability of an outcome |sk> given state |ƒ> is pk=|<sk|ƒ>| . (“Born’s Rule”) *Postulates according to Dirac DECOHERENCE, POINTER BASIS, AND EINSELECTION* S E H , σ σ = 0 [ SE i i ] ⎛ ⎞ Interaction α σ ⊗ ε = Φ t EntanglementH i i SE ( ) ΦSE (0) = ψS ⊗ ε0 = ⎜ α i σ i ⎟ ⊗ ε0 SE ∑ i ∑ i ⎝ i ⎠ 2 REDUCED DENSITY MATRIX ρS (t) = TrE ΦSE (t) ΦSE (t) = ∑α i σ i σ i € i EINSELECTION* leads to POINTER STATES Stable states, tend to appear near diagonal€ of ρ t after decoherence time; € S ( ) Pointer states are effectively€ classical! They preserve correlations: they are left unperturbed€ by the “environmental monitoring”.
    [Show full text]
  • A Review of the Measurement Problem in Quantum Mechanics
    A Review of the Measurement Problem in Quantum Mechanics Ian Bennet Pittaway Thesis presented in fulfilment of the requirements for the degree of Master of Physics in the Faculty of Science at Stellenbosch University. Supervisors: Prof. F.G. Scholtz Dr. J.N. Kriel March 2021 Stellenbosch University https://scholar.sun.ac.za Declaration By submitting this thesis electronically, I declare that the entirety of the work contained therein is my own, original work, that I am the sole author thereof (save to the extent explic- itly otherwise stated), that reproduction and publication thereof by Stellenbosch University will not infringe any third party rights and that I have not previously in its entirety or in part submitted it for obtaining any qualification. Copyright c 2021 Stellenbosch University. All rights reserved i Stellenbosch University https://scholar.sun.ac.za A Review of the Measurement Problem in Quantum Mechanics Ian Bennet Pittaway Abstract Quantum Mechanics has been a massively successful theory, but for all its success it is at odds with our experiences at the macroscopic or classical level. This tension between the quantum and classical worlds and the transition between them has been dubbed the Measurement Problem. Here we review the Measurement Problem and describe it in the context of the double split experiment. We use this to define the problem and identify two major aspects, namely the Problem of Macro-objectification, the lack of superposition of macroscopic objects, and the Problem of Outcomes, the selection of a single outcome upon measurement of a superposition. Three more related, and more technical, problems are also identified.
    [Show full text]
  • Application of Quantum Darwinism to a Structured Environment
    View metadata, citation and similar papers at core.ac.uk brought to you by CORE provided by Sussex Research Online PHYSICAL REVIEW A 96, 062105 (2017) Application of quantum Darwinism to a structured environment Graeme Pleasance* and Barry M. Garraway Department of Physics and Astronomy, University of Sussex, Falmer, Brighton BN1 9QH, England, United Kingdom (Received 26 July 2017; published 5 December 2017) Quantum Darwinism extends the traditional formalism of decoherence to explain the emergence of classicality in a quantum universe. A classical description emerges when the environment tends to redundantly acquire information about the pointer states of an open system. In light of recent interest, we apply the theoretical tools of the framework to a qubit coupled with many bosonic subenvironments. We examine the degree to which the same classical information is encoded across collections of (i) complete subenvironments and (ii) residual “pseudomode” components of each subenvironment, the conception of which provides a dynamic representation of the reservoir memory. Overall, significant redundancy of information is found as a typical result of the decoherence process. However, by examining its decomposition in terms of classical and quantum correlations, we discover classical information to be nonredundant in both cases i and ii. Moreover, with the full collection of pseudomodes, certain dynamical regimes realize opposite effects, where either the total classical or quantum correlations predominantly decay over time. Finally, when the dynamics are non-Markovian, we find that redundant information is suppressed in line with information backflow to the qubit. By quantifying redundancy, we concretely show it to act as a witness to non-Markovianity in the same way as the trace distance does for nondivisible dynamical maps.
    [Show full text]
  • Quantum Mechanical Vistas on the Road to Quantum Gravity
    Quantum Mechanical Vistas on the Road to Quantum Gravity Thesis by Ashmeet Singh In Partial Fulfillment of the Requirements for the Degree of Doctor of Philosophy CALIFORNIA INSTITUTE OF TECHNOLOGY Pasadena, California 2020 Defended May 11, 2020 ii © 2020 Ashmeet Singh ORCID: 0000-0002-4404-1416 All rights reserved iii ACKNOWLEDGEMENTS My journey as a PhD student at Caltech over the last five years has been a rather unique one. It has been formative in ways more than one taking me through highs and lows spanning the spectrum, and I feel I am a more holistic person for it. I owe my gratitude to all those people who have made this journey, and this thesis, possible, and because of whom my experience of working toward a doctoral degree has been one that I will cherish. I am grateful to the Almighty (a concept I have now begun to more closely associate with the creative power in Nature) for the gift of good health and ascending spirits, which made working on this thesis enriching, both academically and otherwise. Let me begin with the academic facet of my PhD life. My most intellectually valu- able take-away from my research life at Caltech is the profound research direction I got to be a part of – an effort to understand quantum gravity from minimal elements in quantum mechanics. I am very thankful to our research group at Caltech for letting me be part of this bold and stimulating endeavor. First and foremost, my strongest gratitude to my advisor, Sean Carroll. Ever since I wandered into his office during my first month at Caltech, wanting to discuss ideas in foundational quantum mechanics, Sean has not just been a mentor to me, but rather an inspiration.
    [Show full text]
  • Whenever a Quantum Environment Emerges As a Classical System, It Behaves Like a Measuring Apparatus
    Whenever a quantum environment emerges as a classical system, it behaves like a measuring apparatus Caterina Foti1,2, Teiko Heinosaari3, Sabrina Maniscalco3, and Paola Verrucchi4,1,2 1Dipartimento di Fisica e Astronomia, Università di Firenze, I-50019, Sesto Fiorentino (FI), Italy 2INFN, Sezione di Firenze, I-50019, Sesto Fiorentino (FI), Italy 3QTF Centre of Excellence, Turku Centre for Quantum Physics, Department of Physics and Astronomy, University of Turku, FIN-20014, Turku, Finland 4ISC-CNR, at Dipartimento di Fisica e Astronomia, Università di Firenze, I-50019, Sesto Fiorentino (FI), Italy August 6, 2019 We study the dynamics of a quantum malizes the qualitative argument that the system Γ with an environment Ξ made of reason why we do not observe state su- N elementary quantum components. We perpositions is the continual measurement aim at answering the following questions: performed by the environment. can the evolution of Γ be characterized by some general features when N becomes very large, regardless of the specific form 1 Introduction of its interaction with each and every com- ponent of Ξ? In other terms: should we There exist two closely-related questions about expect all quantum systems with a macro- the quantum mechanical nature of our uni- scopic environment to undergo a somehow verse that keep being intriguing after decades of similar evolution? And if yes, of what thought processing: how is it that we do not ex- type? In order to answer these questions perience state superpositions, and why we cannot we use well established results from large- even see them when observing quantum systems.
    [Show full text]