Categories of Relations As Models of Quantum Theory
Total Page:16
File Type:pdf, Size:1020Kb
Load more
Recommended publications
-
A Subtle Introduction to Category Theory
A Subtle Introduction to Category Theory W. J. Zeng Department of Computer Science, Oxford University \Static concepts proved to be very effective intellectual tranquilizers." L. L. Whyte \Our study has revealed Mathematics as an array of forms, codify- ing ideas extracted from human activates and scientific problems and deployed in a network of formal rules, formal definitions, formal axiom systems, explicit theorems with their careful proof and the manifold in- terconnections of these forms...[This view] might be called formal func- tionalism." Saunders Mac Lane Let's dive right in then, shall we? What can we say about the array of forms MacLane speaks of? Claim (Tentative). Category theory is about the formal aspects of this array of forms. Commentary: It might be tempting to put the brakes on right away and first grab hold of what we mean by formal aspects. Instead, rather than trying to present \the formal" as the object of study and category theory as our instrument, we would nudge the reader to consider another perspective. Category theory itself defines formal aspects in much the same way that physics defines physical concepts or laws define legal (and correspondingly illegal) aspects: it embodies them. When we speak of what is formal/physical/legal we inescapably speak of category/physical/legal theory, and vice versa. Thus we pass to the somewhat grammatically awkward revision of our initial claim: Claim (Tentative). Category theory is the formal aspects of this array of forms. Commentary: Let's unpack this a little bit. While individual forms are themselves tautologically formal, arrays of forms and everything else networked in a system lose this tautological formality. -
Regular Categories and Regular Logic Basic Research in Computer Science
BRICS Basic Research in Computer Science BRICS LS-98-2 C. Butz: Regular Categories and Regular Logic Regular Categories and Regular Logic Carsten Butz BRICS Lecture Series LS-98-2 ISSN 1395-2048 October 1998 Copyright c 1998, BRICS, Department of Computer Science University of Aarhus. All rights reserved. Reproduction of all or part of this work is permitted for educational or research use on condition that this copyright notice is included in any copy. See back inner page for a list of recent BRICS Lecture Series publica- tions. Copies may be obtained by contacting: BRICS Department of Computer Science University of Aarhus Ny Munkegade, building 540 DK–8000 Aarhus C Denmark Telephone: +45 8942 3360 Telefax: +45 8942 3255 Internet: [email protected] BRICS publications are in general accessible through the World Wide Web and anonymous FTP through these URLs: http://www.brics.dk ftp://ftp.brics.dk This document in subdirectory LS/98/2/ Regular Categories and Regular Logic Carsten Butz Carsten Butz [email protected] BRICS1 Department of Computer Science University of Aarhus Ny Munkegade DK-8000 Aarhus C, Denmark October 1998 1Basic Research In Computer Science, Centre of the Danish National Research Foundation. Preface Notes handed out to students attending the course on Category Theory at the Department of Computer Science in Aarhus, Spring 1998. These notes were supposed to give more detailed information about the relationship between regular categories and regular logic than is contained in Jaap van Oosten’s script on category theory (BRICS Lectures Series LS-95-1). Regular logic is there called coherent logic. -
Basic Category Theory and Topos Theory
Basic Category Theory and Topos Theory Jaap van Oosten Jaap van Oosten Department of Mathematics Utrecht University The Netherlands Revised, February 2016 Contents 1 Categories and Functors 1 1.1 Definitions and examples . 1 1.2 Some special objects and arrows . 5 2 Natural transformations 8 2.1 The Yoneda lemma . 8 2.2 Examples of natural transformations . 11 2.3 Equivalence of categories; an example . 13 3 (Co)cones and (Co)limits 16 3.1 Limits . 16 3.2 Limits by products and equalizers . 23 3.3 Complete Categories . 24 3.4 Colimits . 25 4 A little piece of categorical logic 28 4.1 Regular categories and subobjects . 28 4.2 The logic of regular categories . 34 4.3 The language L(C) and theory T (C) associated to a regular cat- egory C ................................ 39 4.4 The category C(T ) associated to a theory T : Completeness Theorem 41 4.5 Example of a regular category . 44 5 Adjunctions 47 5.1 Adjoint functors . 47 5.2 Expressing (co)completeness by existence of adjoints; preserva- tion of (co)limits by adjoint functors . 52 6 Monads and Algebras 56 6.1 Algebras for a monad . 57 6.2 T -Algebras at least as complete as D . 61 6.3 The Kleisli category of a monad . 62 7 Cartesian closed categories and the λ-calculus 64 7.1 Cartesian closed categories (ccc's); examples and basic facts . 64 7.2 Typed λ-calculus and cartesian closed categories . 68 7.3 Representation of primitive recursive functions in ccc's with nat- ural numbers object . -
The Morita Theory of Quantum Graph Isomorphisms
Commun. Math. Phys. Communications in Digital Object Identifier (DOI) https://doi.org/10.1007/s00220-018-3225-6 Mathematical Physics The Morita Theory of Quantum Graph Isomorphisms Benjamin Musto, David Reutter, Dominic Verdon Department of Computer Science, University of Oxford, Oxford, UK. E-mail: [email protected]; [email protected]; [email protected] Received: 31 January 2018 / Accepted: 11 June 2018 © The Author(s) 2018 Abstract: We classify instances of quantum pseudo-telepathy in the graph isomorphism game, exploiting the recently discovered connection between quantum information and the theory of quantum automorphism groups. Specifically, we show that graphs quantum isomorphic to a given graph are in bijective correspondence with Morita equivalence classes of certain Frobenius algebras in the category of finite-dimensional representations of the quantum automorphism algebra of that graph. We show that such a Frobenius algebra may be constructed from a central type subgroup of the classical automorphism group, whose action on the graph has coisotropic vertex stabilisers. In particular, if the original graph has no quantum symmetries, quantum isomorphic graphs are classified by such subgroups. We show that all quantum isomorphic graph pairs corresponding to a well-known family of binary constraint systems arise from this group-theoretical construction. We use our classification to show that, of the small order vertex-transitive graphs with no quantum symmetry, none is quantum isomorphic to a non-isomorphic graph. We show that this is in fact asymptotically almost surely true of all graphs. Contents 1. Introduction ................................. 2. Background ................................. 2.1 String diagrams, Frobenius monoids and Gelfand duality ...... -
Categories of Quantum and Classical Channels (Extended Abstract)
Categories of Quantum and Classical Channels (extended abstract) Bob Coecke∗ Chris Heunen† Aleks Kissinger∗ University of Oxford, Department of Computer Science fcoecke,heunen,[email protected] We introduce the CP*–construction on a dagger compact closed category as a generalisation of Selinger’s CPM–construction. While the latter takes a dagger compact closed category and forms its category of “abstract matrix algebras” and completely positive maps, the CP*–construction forms its category of “abstract C*-algebras” and completely positive maps. This analogy is justified by the case of finite-dimensional Hilbert spaces, where the CP*–construction yields the category of finite-dimensional C*-algebras and completely positive maps. The CP*–construction fully embeds Selinger’s CPM–construction in such a way that the objects in the image of the embedding can be thought of as “purely quantum” state spaces. It also embeds the category of classical stochastic maps, whose image consists of “purely classical” state spaces. By allowing classical and quantum data to coexist, this provides elegant abstract notions of preparation, measurement, and more general quantum channels. 1 Introduction One of the motivations driving categorical treatments of quantum mechanics is to place classical and quantum systems on an equal footing in a single category, so that one can study their interactions. The main idea of categorical quantum mechanics [1] is to fix a category (usually dagger compact) whose ob- jects are thought of as state spaces and whose morphisms are evolutions. There are two main variations. • “Dirac style”: Objects form pure state spaces, and isometric morphisms form pure state evolutions. -
Compact Inverse Categories 11
COMPACT INVERSE CATEGORIES ROBIN COCKETT AND CHRIS HEUNEN Abstract. The Ehresmann-Schein-Nambooripad theorem gives a structure theorem for inverse monoids: they are inductive groupoids. A particularly nice case due to Jarek is that commutative inverse monoids become semilattices of abelian groups. It has also been categorified by DeWolf-Pronk to a structure theorem for inverse categories as locally complete inductive groupoids. We show that in the case of compact inverse categories, this takes the particularly nice form of a semilattice of compact groupoids. Moreover, one-object com- pact inverse categories are exactly commutative inverse monoids. Compact groupoids, in turn, are determined in particularly simple terms of 3-cocycles by Baez-Lauda. 1. Introduction Inverse monoids model partial symmetry [24], and arise naturally in many com- binatorial constructions [8]. The easiest example of an inverse monoid is perhaps a group. There is a structure theorem for inverse monoids, due to Ehresmann-Schein- Nambooripad [9, 10, 27, 26], that exhibits them as inductive groupoids. The latter are groupoids internal to the category of partially ordered sets with certain ex- tra requirements. By a result of Jarek [19], the inductive groupoids corresponding to commutative inverse monoids can equivalently be described as semilattices of abelian groups. A natural typed version of an inverse monoid is an inverse category [22, 6]. This notion can for example model partial reversible functional programs [12]. The eas- iest example of an inverse category is perhaps a groupoid. DeWolf-Pronk have generalised the ESN theorem to inverse categories, exhibiting them as locally com- plete inductive groupoids. This paper investigates `the commutative case', thus fitting in the bottom right cell of Figure 1. -
Most Human Things Go in Pairs. Alcmaeon, ∼ 450 BC
Most human things go in pairs. Alcmaeon, 450 BC ∼ true false good bad right left up down front back future past light dark hot cold matter antimatter boson fermion How can we formalize a general concept of duality? The Chinese tried yin-yang theory, which inspired Leibniz to develop binary notation, which in turn underlies digital computation! But what's the state of the art now? In category theory the fundamental duality is the act of reversing an arrow: • ! • • • We use this to model switching past and future, false and true, small and big... Every category has an opposite op, where the arrows are C C reversed. This is a symmetry of the category of categories: op : Cat Cat ! and indeed the only nontrivial one: Aut(Cat) = Z=2 In logic, the simplest duality is negation. It's order-reversing: if P implies Q then Q implies P : : and|ignoring intuitionism!|it's an involution: P = P :: Thus if is a category of propositions and proofs, we C expect a functor: : op : C ! C with a natural isomorphism: 2 = 1 : ∼ C This has two analogues in quantum theory. One shows up already in the category of finite-dimensional vector spaces, FinVect. Every vector space V has a dual V ∗. Taking the dual is contravariant: if f : V W then f : W V ! ∗ ∗ ! ∗ and|ignoring infinite-dimensional spaces!|it's an involution: V ∗∗ ∼= V This kind of duality is captured by the idea of a -autonomous ∗ category. Recall that a symmetric monoidal category is roughly a category with a unit object I and a tensor product C 2 C : ⊗ C × C ! C that is unital, associative and commutative up to coherent natural isomorphisms. -
The Way of the Dagger
The Way of the Dagger Martti Karvonen I V N E R U S E I T H Y T O H F G E R D I N B U Doctor of Philosophy Laboratory for Foundations of Computer Science School of Informatics University of Edinburgh 2018 (Graduation date: July 2019) Abstract A dagger category is a category equipped with a functorial way of reversing morph- isms, i.e. a contravariant involutive identity-on-objects endofunctor. Dagger categor- ies with additional structure have been studied under different names in categorical quantum mechanics, algebraic field theory and homological algebra, amongst others. In this thesis we study the dagger in its own right and show how basic category theory adapts to dagger categories. We develop a notion of a dagger limit that we show is suitable in the following ways: it subsumes special cases known from the literature; dagger limits are unique up to unitary isomorphism; a wide class of dagger limits can be built from a small selection of them; dagger limits of a fixed shape can be phrased as dagger adjoints to a diagonal functor; dagger limits can be built from ordinary limits in the presence of polar decomposition; dagger limits commute with dagger colimits in many cases. Using cofree dagger categories, the theory of dagger limits can be leveraged to provide an enrichment-free understanding of limit-colimit coincidences in ordinary category theory. We formalize the concept of an ambilimit, and show that it captures known cases. As a special case, we show how to define biproducts up to isomorphism in an arbitrary category without assuming any enrichment. -
A Survey of Graphical Languages for Monoidal Categories
5 Traced categories 32 5.1 Righttracedcategories . 33 5.2 Planartracedcategories. 34 5.3 Sphericaltracedcategories . 35 A survey of graphical languages for monoidal 5.4 Spacialtracedcategories . 36 categories 5.5 Braidedtracedcategories . 36 5.6 Balancedtracedcategories . 39 5.7 Symmetrictracedcategories . 40 Peter Selinger 6 Products, coproducts, and biproducts 41 Dalhousie University 6.1 Products................................. 41 6.2 Coproducts ............................... 43 6.3 Biproducts................................ 44 Abstract 6.4 Traced product, coproduct, and biproduct categories . ........ 45 This article is intended as a reference guide to various notions of monoidal cat- 6.5 Uniformityandregulartrees . 47 egories and their associated string diagrams. It is hoped that this will be useful not 6.6 Cartesiancenter............................. 48 just to mathematicians, but also to physicists, computer scientists, and others who use diagrammatic reasoning. We have opted for a somewhat informal treatment of 7 Dagger categories 48 topological notions, and have omitted most proofs. Nevertheless, the exposition 7.1 Daggermonoidalcategories . 50 is sufficiently detailed to make it clear what is presently known, and to serve as 7.2 Otherprogressivedaggermonoidalnotions . ... 50 a starting place for more in-depth study. Where possible, we provide pointers to 7.3 Daggerpivotalcategories. 51 more rigorous treatments in the literature. Where we include results that have only 7.4 Otherdaggerpivotalnotions . 54 been proved in special cases, we indicate this in the form of caveats. 7.5 Daggertracedcategories . 55 7.6 Daggerbiproducts............................ 56 Contents 8 Bicategories 57 1 Introduction 2 9 Beyond a single tensor product 58 2 Categories 5 10 Summary 59 3 Monoidal categories 8 3.1 (Planar)monoidalcategories . 9 1 Introduction 3.2 Spacialmonoidalcategories . -
Some Glances at Topos Theory
Some glances at topos theory Francis Borceux Como, 2018 2 Francis Borceux [email protected] Contents 1 Localic toposes 7 1.1 Sheaves on a topological space . 7 1.2 Sheaves on a locale . 10 1.3 Localic toposes . 12 1.4 An application to ring theory . 13 2 Grothendieck toposes 17 2.1 Sheaves on a site . 17 2.2 The associated sheaf functor . 19 2.3 Limits and colimits in Grothendieck toposes . 21 2.4 Closure operator and subobject classifier . 22 3 Elementary toposes 25 3.1 The axioms for a topos . 25 3.2 Some set theoretical notions in a topos . 26 3.3 The slice toposes . 28 3.4 Exactness properties . 29 3.5 Heyting algebras in a topos . 30 4 Internal logic of a topos 33 4.1 The language of a topos . 33 4.2 Interpretation of terms and formulæ . 35 4.3 Propositional calculus in a topos . 37 4.4 Predicate calculus in a topos . 38 4.5 Structure of a topos in its internal language . 40 4.6 Boolean toposes . 41 4.7 The axiom of choice . 42 4.8 The axiom of infinity . 43 5 Morphisms of toposes 45 5.1 Logical morphisms . 45 5.2 Geometric morphisms . 46 5.3 Coherent and geometric formulæ . 48 5.4 Grothendieck topologies revisited . 49 5.5 Internal topologies and sheaves . 50 5.6 Back to Boolean toposes . 52 3 4 CONTENTS 6 Classifying toposes 53 6.1 What is a classifying topos? . 53 6.2 The theory classified by a topos . 54 6.3 Coherent and geometric theories . -
Categories with Fuzzy Sets and Relations
Categories with Fuzzy Sets and Relations John Harding, Carol Walker, Elbert Walker Department of Mathematical Sciences New Mexico State University Las Cruces, NM 88003, USA jhardingfhardy,[email protected] Abstract We define a 2-category whose objects are fuzzy sets and whose maps are relations subject to certain natural conditions. We enrich this category with additional monoidal and involutive structure coming from t-norms and negations on the unit interval. We develop the basic properties of this category and consider its relation to other familiar categories. A discussion is made of extending these results to the setting of type-2 fuzzy sets. 1 Introduction A fuzzy set is a map A : X ! I from a set X to the unit interval I. Several authors [2, 6, 7, 20, 22] have considered fuzzy sets as a category, which we will call FSet, where a morphism from A : X ! I to B : Y ! I is a function f : X ! Y that satisfies A(x) ≤ (B◦f)(x) for each x 2 X. Here we continue this path of investigation. The underlying idea is to lift additional structure from the unit interval, such as t-norms, t-conorms, and negations, to provide additional structure on the category. Our eventual aim is to provide a setting where processes used in fuzzy control can be abstractly studied, much in the spirit of recent categorical approaches to processes used in quantum computation [1]. Order preserving structure on I, such as t-norms and conorms, lifts to provide additional covariant structure on FSet. In fact, each t-norm T lifts to provide a symmetric monoidal tensor ⊗T on FSet. -
Dagger Symmetric Monoidal Category
Tutorial on dagger categories Peter Selinger Dalhousie University Halifax, Canada FMCS 2018 1 Part I: Quantum Computing 2 Quantum computing: States α state of one qubit: = 0. • β ! 6 α β state of two qubits: . • γ δ ac a c ad separable: = . • b ! ⊗ d ! bc bd otherwise entangled. • 3 Notation 1 0 |0 = , |1 = . • i 0 ! i 1 ! |ij = |i |j etc. • i i⊗ i 4 Quantum computing: Operations unitary transformation • measurement • 5 Some standard unitary gates 0 1 0 −i 1 0 X = , Y = , Z = , 1 0 ! i 0 ! 0 −1 ! 1 1 1 1 0 1 0 H = , S = , T = , √2 1 −1 ! 0 i ! 0 √i ! 1 0 0 0 I 0 0 1 0 0 CNOT = = 0 X ! 0 0 0 1 0 0 1 0 6 Measurement α|0 + β|1 i i 0 1 |α|2 |β|2 α|0 β|1 i i 7 Mixed states A mixed state is a (classical) probability distribution on quantum states. Ad hoc notation: 1 α 1 α + ′ 2 β ! 2 β′ ! Note: A mixed state is a description of our knowledge of a state. An actual closed quantum system is always in a (possibly unknown) “pure” (= non-mixed) state. 8 Density matrices (von Neumann) α Represent the pure state v = C2 by the matrix β ! ∈ αα¯ αβ¯ 2 2 vv† = C × . βα¯ ββ¯ ! ∈ Represent the mixed state λ1 {v1} + ... + λn {vn} by λ1v1v1† + ... + λnvnvn† . This representation is not one-to-one, e.g. 1 1 1 0 1 1 0 1 0 0 .5 0 + = + = 2 0 ! 2 1 ! 2 0 0 ! 2 0 1 ! 0 .5 ! 1 1 1 1 1 1 1 .5 .5 1 .5 −.5 .5 0 + = + = 2 √2 1 ! 2 √2 −1 ! 2 .5 .5 ! 2 −.5 .5 ! 0 .5 ! But these two mixed states are indistinguishable.