Causation: Philosophy of Science •

Total Page:16

File Type:pdf, Size:1020Kb

Causation: Philosophy of Science • CAUSATION: PHILOSOPHY OF SCIENCE Reinhardt. Cambridge, U.K.: Cambridge University Press, causation was one of the fundamental concepts that ren­ 1993. dered the empirical world comprehensible to humans. By McDermott, Michael. "Redundant Causation." British Journal the beginning of the twenty-first century, psychology was for the Philosophy of Science 40 (1995): 523-544. Mellor, D. H. The Facts of Causation. London: Routledge, 1995. beginning to show just how pervasive human reasoning Mellor, D. H. "Fixed Past, Unfixed Future." In Contributions to concerning cause and effect is. Even young children seem Philosophy: Michael Dummett, edited by Barry Taylor, to naturally organize their knowledge of the world 166-186. The Hague: Nijhoff, 1986. according to relations of cause and effect. Menzies, Peter. "Probabilistic Causation and Causal Processes: A Critique of Lewis." Philosophy of Science 56 (1989): It is hardly surprising, then, that causation has been 642-663. a topic of great interest in philosophy, and that many Ramachandran, Murali. "A Counterfactual Analysis of philosophers have attempted to analyze the relationship Causation." Mind 106 (1997): 263-277. between cause and effect. Among the more prominent Reichenbach, Hans. The Direction of Time. Berkeley and Los proposals are the following: Causation consists in the Angeles: University of California Press, 1956. instantiation of exceptionless regularities (Hume 1975, Salmon, Wesley C. "Probabilistic Causality." Pacific Philosophical Quarterly 61 (1980): 50-74. 1999; Mill1856; Hempel1965; Mackie 1974); causation is Salmon, Wesley C. Scientific Explanation and the Causal to be understood in terms of relations of probabilistic Structure of the World. Princeton, NT: Princeton University dependence (Reichenbach 1956, Suppes 1970, Cartwright Press, 1984. 1983, Eells 1991); causation is the relation that holds Schaffer, Jonathan. "Trumping Preemption." Journal of between means and ends (Gasking 1955, von Wright Philosophy 97 (4) (2000): 165-181. Sosa, Ernest, and Michael Tooley, eds. Causation. Oxford: 1975, Woodward 2003); causes are events but for which Oxford University Press, 1993. their effects would not have happened (Lewis 1986); Stalnaker, Robert C. "A Theory of Conditionals." In Studies in causes and effects are connected by physical processes Logical Theory, American Philosophical Quarterly, that are capable of transmitting certain types of proper­ Monograph 2, edited by Nicholas Rescher, 98-112. Oxford: ties (Salmon 1984, Dowe 2000). Blackwell, 1968. Strawson, Galen. The Secret Connexion: Causation, Realism, It often happens, however, that advances in science and David Hume. Oxford: Oxford University Press, 1989. force people to abandon aspects of their common sense Suppes, Patrick. A Probabilistic Theory of Causality. picture of the world. For example, Einstein's theories of Amsterdam: North-Holland, 1970. relativity have forced people to rethink their conceptions Tooley, Michael. Causation: A Realist Approach. Oxford: Oxford University Press, 1987. of time, space, matter, and energy. What lessons does sci­ Tooley, Michael. "The Nature of Causation: A Singularist ence teach about the concept of causation? Account:' Canadian Philosophers, Canadian Journal of Philosophy Suppl. 16 (1990): 271-322. RUSSELL'S CHALLENGE Tooley, Michael. "Probability and Causation." In Cause and Chance, edited by Phil Dowe and Paul Noordhof. London In 1912, the eminent British philosopher Bertrand Rus­ and New York: Routledge, 2004. sell delivered his paper "On the Notion of Cause" before Tooley, Michael. "The Stalnaker-Lewis Approach to the Aristotelian Society. In this paper, he claimed that the Counterfactuals:' Journal of Philosophy 100 (7) (2003): notion of cause had no place in a scientific worldview: 321-327. Tooley, Michael. Time, Tense, and Causation. Oxford: Oxford All philosophers, of every school, imagine that University Press, 1997. causation is one of the fundamental axioms or Von Bretzel, Philip. "Concerning a Probabilistic Theory of postulates of science, yet, oddly enough, in Causation Adequate for the Causal Theory of Time." advanced sciences such as gravitational astron­ Synthese 35 (1977): 173-190. omy, the word "cause" never appears ... To me, Von Wright, Georg Henrik. Explanation and Understanding. Ithaca, NY: Cornell University Press, 1971. it seems that . the reason why physics has ceased to look for causes is that, in fact, there are Michael Tooley (1996, 2005) no such things. The law of causality, I believe, like much that passes muster among philoso­ phers, is a relic of a bygone age, surviving, like CAUSATION: PHILOSOPHY the monarchy, only because it is erroneously supposed to do no harm. (p. 1) OF SCIENCE Russell was not alone in this view. Other writers of In The Critique of Pure Reason (first published in 1781), the period, such as Ernst Mach (the German physicist and the German philosopher Immanuel Kant maintained that philosopher of science), Karl Pearson (the father of mod- ENCYCLOPEDIA OF PHILOSOPHY 2nd edition • 103 CAUSATION; PHILOSOPHY OF SCIENCE ern statistics), and Pierre Duhem (French physicist, as electric and magnetic fields, Schrodinger's equation gov­ well as historian and philosopher of science), also argued erning the evolution of quantum systems, and Einstein's that causation did not belong in the world of science. field equations relating the distribution of mass-energy in This view was shared by the logical positivists, a group of the universe with the structure of space and time-make philosophers working primarily in Austria and Germany no mention of causation. All of these principles take the between the World Wars whose ideas shaped much of form of mathematical equations and act as constraints on philosophy of science in the twentieth century. A general possible states of physical systems (under suitable mathe­ suspicion of causal notions also pervaded a number of matical characterizations). A given sequence of states may fields outside of philosophy, such as statistics and psy­ be compatible with, for example, Newton's laws of chology. motion, but nothing in those laws explicitly says that cer­ tain states (or aspects of those states) cause others. This CAUSATION IN SCIENCE suggests that the causal relation is not part of the consti­ tution of the world at the deepest metaphysical level, a Despite Russell's remark, it is simply false that the word view that the historian and philosopher of science John "cause" (and its cognates) does not appear in the Norton labels "anti-fundamentalism" (Norton 2003). advanced sciences. Russell's claim can be readily refuted Indeed, the world described by fundamental physics is in by perusing any leading science journal. Admittedly, many ways at odds with the ordinary picture of a world some uses of the word "cause" and its cognates have spe­ regimented by cause and effect relationships. cific technical meanings-such as talk of "causal struc­ ture" in connection with the general theory of relativity-but frequently enough these words are used in ASYMMETRY their ordinary English sense. To cite just one example, an People normally think of causation as both asymmetric issue of Physical Review Letters from 2003 contains an and temporally biased. It is asymmetric in the sense that if article titled "Specific-Heat Anomaly Caused by Cis a cause of E, then (always? typically?) E is not a cause Ferroelectric Nanoregions in Pb(Mg[sub 1/3]Nb[sub of C. This claim must be stated with some care. It may be, 2/3])0[sub 3] and Pb(Mg[sub 1/3]Ta[sub 2/3])0[sub 3] for instance, that anxiety is a cause of insomnia, which is Relaxors." Moreover, it has become common in physics to in turn a cause of anxiety. But it is one's anxiety on Mon­ classify a variety of phenomena as "effects": there is the day evening that causes insomnia on Monday night, "Hall effect;' the "Kondo effect;' the "Lamb-shift effect;' which in turn causes anxiety on Tuesday morning. Mon­ the "Zeeman effect," and so on. But surely "cause and day night's insomnia is not both the cause and the effect effect" are an inseparable pair: where there are causes, of one and the same episode of anxiety. Causation is tem­ there are effects that are caused by them, and where there porally biased in the sense that causes (always? typically?) are effects, there are causes that cause them. occur before their effects in time. The person on the street is more likely to encounter By contrast, the fundamental laws of physics men­ causal claims from the medical sciences, such as: "Choles­ tioned above are all time-reversal invariant. That is, if a terol in the bloodstream causes hardened arteries, which particular sequence of states of a physical system is con­ in turn causes heart attacks." While the medical sciences sistent with the laws of physics, then the temporally may not be as advanced as Russell's example of gravita­ reversed sequence is also consistent with those laws. The tional astronomy, it· is implausible to think that these laws of physics do not discriminate between the past and causal claims are the result of conceptual confusion, or the future in the way that causation does;with two possi­ are otherwise scientifically disreputable. ble exceptions. The first exception involves the statistical Despite the falsehood of its most provocative claim, laws governing the decay of certain mesons. While these however, Russell's paper does succeed in highlighting a laws exhibit a slight temporal asymmetry, the phenomena number of important and interesting problems about the in question seem too esoteric to be of much help in role of causation in science. understanding the asymmetry of causation. The second exception is the second law of thermody­ ANTI-FUNDAMENTALISM namics, which states that the entropy of a closed system Although the advanced sciences have hardly eschewed can increase but never decrease. Thus a closed system talk of causation, it is true that the deepest physical prin­ whose entropy is increasing is consistent with the second ciples-such as Newton's three laws of motion, his law of law, while the temporal reverse of this system is not.
Recommended publications
  • Haecceitism, Chance
    HAECCEITISM, CHANCE, AND COUNTERFACTUALS Boris Kment Abstract. Anti-haecceitists believe that all facts about specific individuals—such as the fact that Fred exists, or that Katie is tall—globally supervene on purely qualitative facts. Haecceitists deny that. The issue is not only of interest in itself, but receives additional importance from its intimate connection to the question of whether all fundamental facts are qualitative or whether they include facts about which specific individuals there are and how qualitative properties and relations are distributed over them. Those who think that all fundamental facts are qualitative are arguably committed to anti-haecceitism. The goal of this paper is to point out some problems for anti-haecceitism (and therefore for the thesis that all fundamental facts are qualitative). The article focuses on two common assumptions about possible worlds: (i) Sets of possible worlds are the bearers of objective physical chance. (ii) Counterfactual conditionals can be defined by appeal to a relation of closeness between possible worlds. The essay tries to show that absurd consequences ensue if either of these assumptions is combined with anti-haecceitism. Then it considers a natural response by the anti-haecceitist, which is to deny that worlds play the role described in (i) and (ii). Instead, the reply continues, we can introduce a new set of entities that are defined in terms of worlds and that behave the way worlds do on the haecceitist position. That allows the anti-haecceitist to formulate anti-haecceitist friendly versions of (i) and (ii) by replacing the appeal to possible worlds with reference to the newly introduced entities.
    [Show full text]
  • Curriculum Vitae
    BAS C. VAN FRAASSEN Curriculum Vitae Last updated 3/6/2019 I. Personal and Academic History .................................................................................................................... 1 List of Degrees Earned ........................................................................................................................................................ 1 Title of Ph.D. Thesis ........................................................................................................................................................... 1 Positions held ..................................................................................................................................................................... 1 Invited lectures and lecture series ........................................................................................................................................ 1 List of Honors, Prizes ......................................................................................................................................................... 4 Research Grants .................................................................................................................................................................. 4 Non-Academic Publications ................................................................................................................................................ 5 II. Professional Activities .................................................................................................................................
    [Show full text]
  • Metaphysical Perspectives by Nicholas Rescher (Review) J
    Metaphysical Perspectives by Nicholas Rescher (review) J. P. Moreland The Review of Metaphysics, Volume 72, Number 1 (Issue No. 285), September 2018, pp. 151-153 (Review) Published by The Philosophy Education Society, Inc. For additional information about this article https://muse.jhu.edu/article/736129 [ This content has been declared free to read by the pubisher during the COVID-19 pandemic. ] SUMMARIES AND COMMENTS 151 easy to spot a wolf in sheep’s clothing.” Rescher cites as examples the cases involving Alger Hiss, Claus Fuchs, and Anthony Blunt. Rescher concludes with the acknowledgment that evaluating reports prepared for state purposes is a complex business. There is an inevitable gap between the supporting evidence provided and the objective factual claims often based upon it. The information actually at our disposal in many matters confirms our claims but does not always demonstrate them. One is reminded of Plato’s discussion in the Meno where, in introducing the notion of “true opinion,” Plato has Socrates speak of the value of such knowledge. True opinion, although supported by fact, falls short of demonstrative knowledge but is nevertheless required by those who would govern. “Men,” says Socrates, “become good and useful to states not only because they have knowledge, but because they have right opinion.” Given the practical wisdom offered in this volume, it could well be required reading for any high school or college journalism class, and promoted for principled guidance to others, especially those who report on matters of state.—Jude P. Dougherty, The Catholic University of America RESCHER, Nicholas. Metaphysical Perspectives. Notre Dame, Ind.: University of Notre Dame Press, 2017.
    [Show full text]
  • Concrete Possible Worlds (Final)
    CONCRETE POSSIBLE WORLDS Phillip Bricker 1. INTRODUCTION. Open a book or article of contemporary analytic philosophy, and you are likely to find talk of possible worlds therein. This applies not only to analytic metaphysics, but to areas as diverse as philosophy of language, philosophy of science, epistemology, and ethics. Philosophers agree, for the most part, that possible worlds talk is extremely useful for explicating concepts and formulating theories. They disagree, however, over its proper interpretation. In this chapter, I discuss the view, championed by David Lewis, that philosophers’ talk of possible worlds is the literal truth.1 There exists a plurality of worlds. One of these is our world, the actual world, the physical universe that contains us and all our surroundings. The others are merely possible worlds containing merely possible beings, such as flying pigs and talking donkeys. But the other worlds are no less real or concrete for being merely possible. Fantastic? Yes! What could motivate a philosopher to believe such a tale? I start, as is customary, with modality.2 Truths about the world divide into two sorts: categorical and modal. Categorical truths describe how things are, what is actually the case. Modal truths describe how things could or must be, what is possibly or 1 The fullest statement of Lewis’s theory of possible worlds is contained in his magnum opus, Lewis (1986), On the Plurality of Worlds. Lewis’s view is sometimes called “modal realism.” 2 Historically, it was the attempt to provide semantics for modal logic that catapulted possible worlds to the forefront of analytic philosophy.
    [Show full text]
  • What Is Radical About Radical Constructivism?
    What is Radical about Radical Constructivism? Karl H. Müller This article will become an exercise in cognitive mapping of constructivist territories or landscapes. In this sense, the proposed map on different domains of constructivism is, by necessity, the territory. The subsequent explorations will start with Ernst von Glasersfeld’s account of what constitutes Radical Constructivism (RC). The aim is to assemble a set of building blocks and fields of discourse which, in conjunction, form the core of RC Glasersfeld-style. Subsequently, a quick overview will be given on the structure and organization of Second-Order Cybernetics (SOC) as developed and proposed in the late 1960s and throughout the 1970s by Heinz von Foerster, who, together with Humberto R. Maturana, Francisco L. Varela and Ernst von Glasersfeld, formed the core-group of RC.1 Mapping RC and SOC across different arenas, an interesting trade-off can be constructed between the radical building blocks of RC or SOC and their degree of diffusion. Towards the end, a few strategies will be outlined how RC and SOC, in conjunction, could be utilized as a radically new framework which so far has only been occasionally utilized or explored. 1 Radical Constructivism à la Glasersfeld Ernst von Glasersfeld, in combination with Siegfried J. Schmidt (1987, 1987a), was largely responsible for the label of Radical Constructivism (RC). In 1974 von Glasersfeld wrote an article about Jean Piaget and the radical constructivist epistemology (Glasersfeld 1974). In 1981 Ernst von Glasersfeld produced the most influential article for the promotion and the diffusion of RC, namely his “Introduction to Radical Constructivism” in Paul Watzlawick’s widely distributed reader “Die erfundene Wirklichkeit” or, in English, “The Invented Reality” (1984).
    [Show full text]
  • ROBERT ALMEDER 1 on Possibilities and Thought Experiments
    CONTENTS Preface: ROBERT ALMEDER The Limits of Science, Realism, and Idealism: ROBERT ALMEDER 1 On Possibilities and Thought Experiments: DIDERIK BATENS 29 Coherentism and Coherence Truth in the Philosophy of Nicholas Rescher: BRYSON BROWN 59 Philosophical Anthropology: JAMES W. FELT 89 Pluralism and Consensus: LENN E. GOODMAN 105 Mediations, Wagers, and Existential Issues: Nicholas Rescher on Religion and Philosophy: JOHN HALDANE 121 Rescher’s Metaphysics: WILLIAM JAWORSKI 141 The Limits of Science Reconsidered: ULRICH MAJER 151 Conceivability: DIEGO MARCONI 169 Weird Worlds: ROBERT K. MEYER 197 Nicholas Rescher on Greek Philosophy and the Syllogism: JÜRGEN MITTELSTRASS and PETER SCHROEDER-HEISTER 211 Rescher’s Evolutionary Epistemology: JESÚS MOSTERÍN 241 Common Sense: JOSEPH PITT 253 Systematic Philosophy and Theoretical Framework on Nicholas Rescher’s A System of Pragmatic Idealism: LORENZ B. PUNTEL 261 Nicholas Rescher • Project Name On Rescher’s View of Idealism (and Pragmatism): TOM ROCKMORE 287 Rescher on Arabic Logic: TONY STREET 309 Philosophy in the Future: AVRUM STROLL 325 Rescher on Explanation and Prediction: BAS C. VAN FRAASSEN 339 Nicholas Rescher on Scientific Progress: Science in the Face of Limited Cognitive and Technological Resources: THEODOR LEIBER and ROLAND WAGNER-DÖBLER 363 Rescher on Dialog Systems, Argumentation, and Burden of Proof: DOUGLAS WALTON and DAVID M. GODDEN 401 Rescher on Process Thought: MICHEL WEBER 429 How is Scientific Knowledge Economically Possible?: Nicholas Rescher’s Contributions to an Economic Understanding of Science: JAMES R. WIBLE 445 Possibility, Plenitude, and the Optimal World: Rescher on Leibniz’s Cosmology: CATHERINE WILSON 475 Rescher on Aporetics and Consistency: JOHN WOODS 493 Responses to the Contributed Essays: NICHOLAS RESCHER 513 Work by and about Nicholas Rescher 553 List of Contributors 573 .
    [Show full text]
  • The Berlin Group and the Philosophy of Logical Empiricism BOSTON STUDIES in the PHILOSOPHY and HISTORY of SCIENCE
    The Berlin Group and the Philosophy of Logical Empiricism BOSTON STUDIES IN THE PHILOSOPHY AND HISTORY OF SCIENCE Editors ROBERT S. COHEN, Boston University JURGEN¨ RENN, Max Planck Institute for the History of Science KOSTAS GAVROGLU, University of Athens Managing Editor LINDY DIVARCI, Max Planck Institute for the History of Science Editorial Board THEODORE ARABATZIS, University of Athens ALISA BOKULICH, Boston University HEATHER E. DOUGLAS, University of Pittsburgh JEAN GAYON, Universit´eParis1 THOMAS F. GLICK, Boston University HUBERT GOENNER, University of Goettingen JOHN HEILBRON, University of California, Berkeley DIANA KORMOS-BUCHWALD, California Institute of Technology CHRISTOPH LEHNER, Max Planck Institute for the History of Science PETER MCLAUGHLIN, Universit¨at Heidelberg AGUSTI´ NIETO-GALAN, Universitat Aut`onoma de Barcelona NUCCIO ORDINE, Universit´a della Calabria ANA SIMOES,˜ Universidade de Lisboa JOHN J. STACHEL, Boston University SYLVAN S. SCHWEBER, Harvard University BAICHUN ZHANG, Chinese Academy of Science VOLUME 273 For further volumes: http://www.springer.com/series/5710 Nikolay Milkov • Volker Peckhaus Editors The Berlin Group and the Philosophy of Logical Empiricism 123 Editors Nikolay Milkov Volker Peckhaus Department of Philosophy Department of Philosophy University of Paderborn University of Paderborn 33098 Paderborn 33098 Paderborn Germany Germany ISSN 0068-0346 ISBN 978-94-007-5484-3 ISBN 978-94-007-5485-0 (eBook) DOI 10.1007/978-94-007-5485-0 Springer Dordrecht Heidelberg New York London Library of Congress
    [Show full text]
  • Private Vices, Scientific Virtues: Using Economics to Think About Science
    Private Vices, Scientific Virtues: Using Economics to Think about Science THOMAS C. LEONARD Department of Economics Fisher Hall Princeton University Princeton, NJ 08544 United States [email protected] phone: (609) 258-4036 fax: (609) 258-5561 1999 Private Vices, Scientific Virtues: Using Economics to Think about Science Abstract This paper makes a case for using economics to study science and its product, scientific knowledge. Traditional theories of science – due mainly to epistemology – imply that science is successful because scientists are selfless truth seekers, and because they rigidly adhere to a method. Post-modern theories of science – due mainly to sociology and literary theory – argue that science cannot be successful, because scientists are neither disinterested nor selfless, and because methodological rules derive from a faulty epistemology. An economic theory of science argues that, contra the traditional view, successful science doesn’t require the restrictive premises of Traditional theory of science, and that, as a result, contra the Post-modern view, successful science is not ruled out when those premises are. An economic theory of science accommodates both a realistic conception of scientific motivation and procedure, and the possibility of genuine scientific success. In so doing, it offers an intellectual means to address a central question in the theory of science: how do self-interested scientists, who have wordly goals, come to produce the collectively beneficial outcome of reliable scientific knowledge. Keywords Economics of science, philosophy of science, bounded rationality, institutions, scientific knowledge, economic methodology 2 1. Introduction This paper takes up a conundrum that immediately presents itself to the economist considering science.
    [Show full text]
  • The Oberlin Colloquium in Philosophy: Program History
    The Oberlin Colloquium in Philosophy: Program History 1960 FIRST COLLOQUIUM Wilfrid Sellars, "On Looking at Something and Seeing it" Ronald Hepburn, "God and Ambiguity" Comments: Dennis O'Brien Kurt Baier, "Itching and Scratching" Comments: David Falk/Bruce Aune Annette Baier, "Motives" Comments: Jerome Schneewind 1961 SECOND COLLOQUIUM W.D. Falk, "Hegel, Hare and the Existential Malady" Richard Cartwright, "Propositions" Comments: Ruth Barcan Marcus D.A.T. Casking, "Avowals" Comments: Martin Lean Zeno Vendler, "Consequences, Effects and Results" Comments: William Dray/Sylvan Bromberger PUBLISHED: Analytical Philosophy, First Series, R.J. Butler (ed.), Oxford, Blackwell's, 1962. 1962 THIRD COLLOQUIUM C.J. Warnock, "Truth" Arthur Prior, "Some Exercises in Epistemic Logic" Newton Garver, "Criteria" Comments: Carl Ginet/Paul Ziff Hector-Neri Castenada, "The Private Language Argument" Comments: Vere Chappell/James Thomson John Searle, "Meaning and Speech Acts" Comments: Paul Benacerraf/Zeno Vendler PUBLISHED: Knowledge and Experience, C.D. Rollins (ed.), University of Pittsburgh Press, 1964. 1963 FOURTH COLLOQUIUM Michael Scriven, "Insanity" Frederick Will, "The Preferability of Probable Beliefs" Norman Malcolm, "Criteria" Comments: Peter Geach/George Pitcher Terrence Penelhum, "Pleasure and Falsity" Comments: William Kennick/Arnold Isenberg 1964 FIFTH COLLOQUIUM Stephen Korner, "Some Remarks on Deductivism" J.J.C. Smart, "Nonsense" Joel Feinberg, "Causing Voluntary Actions" Comments: Keith Donnellan/Keith Lehrer Nicholas Rescher, "Evaluative Metaphysics" Comments: Lewis W. Beck/Thomas E. Patton Herbert Hochberg, "Qualities" Comments: Richard Severens/J.M. Shorter PUBLISHED: Metaphysics and Explanation, W.H. Capitan and D.D. Merrill (eds.), University of Pittsburgh Press, 1966. 1965 SIXTH COLLOQUIUM Patrick Nowell-Smith, "Acts and Locutions" George Nakhnikian, "St. Anselm's Four Ontological Arguments" Hilary Putnam, "Psychological Predicates" Comments: Bruce Aune/U.T.
    [Show full text]
  • Scientific Prediction in Nicholas Rescher's Conception
    Scientific Prediction in Nicholas Rescher’s Conception: Philosophico-Methodological Analysis Ph.D/Doctoral Dissertation by Amanda Guillán Dopico Volume I of II Volumes Supervisor: Wenceslao J. González Programa de Doctorado Interuniversitario de Lógica y Filosofía de la Ciencia (RD 1393/2007) 2015 SCIENTIFIC PREDICTION IN NICHOLAS RESCHER ’S CONCEPTION : PHILOSOPHICO -METHODOLOGICAL ANALYSIS ABSTRACT Scientific prediction is a central problem in philosophy and methodology of science. This topic has been particularly relevant in Nicholas Rescher’s philosophy. On the one hand, scientific prediction appears as a key concept within his philosophical proposal, which is a system of pragmatic idealism; on the other, a number of his publications are devoted to the study of scientific prediction from different angles. De facto , he offers a rigorous and detailed conception of prediction in science. Within this context, this Ph.D. research has two main objectives, which are interrelated. First, the analysis of the philosophico-methodological characters of scientific prediction in Rescher’s conception is the focus of the attention. To do this, the research deals with different thematic realms: semantic, logical, epistemological, methodological, ontological, axiological, and ethical. These are grounded in the different components of science (language, structure, knowledge, processes, activity, ends, and values). Second, the critical reconstruction of Rescher’s philosophy of science is searched. His approach is a pragmatic idealism that is open to some important realist elements. This second line of research is developed in parallel with the first one, because his system of pragmatic idealism modulates the characters of scientific prediction. LA PREDICCIÓN CIENTÍFICA EN LA CONCEPCIÓN DE NICHOLAS RESCHER : ANÁLISIS FILOSÓFICO -METODOLÓGICO RESUMEN El problema de la predicción científica es un tema central para la Filosofía y Metodología de la Ciencia.
    [Show full text]
  • Donald Davidson ERNEST LEPORE and KIRK LUDWIG
    Midwest Studies in Philosophy, XXVIII (2004) Donald Davidson ERNEST LEPORE AND KIRK LUDWIG avidson, Donald (Herbert) (b. 1917, d. 2003; American), Willis S. and Marion DSlusser Professor, University of California at Berkeley (1986–2003). Previ- ously Instructor then Professor in Philosophy at: Queens College New York (1947–1950), Stanford University, California (1950–1967), Princeton University (1967–1969), Rockefeller University, New York City (1970–1976), University of Chicago (1976–1981), University of California at Berkeley (1981–2003). John Locke Lecturer, University of Oxford (1970). One of the most important philosophers of the latter half of the twentieth century, Donald Davidson explored a wide range of fundamental topics in meta- physics, epistemology, ethics, and the philosophies of action, mind, and language. His impact on contemporary philosophy is second only to that of his teacher W. V. O. Quine, who, along with Alfred Tarski, exerted the greatest influence on him. Given the range of his contributions, his work emerges as surprisingly systematic, an expression and working out of a number of central guiding ideas. Among his most important contributions are 1. his defense of the common sense view that reasons, those beliefs and desires we cite in explaining our actions, are also causes of them [11], 2. his groundbreaking work in the theory of meaning, and his proposal, based on Tarski’s work on recursive truth definitions for formal languages, for how to formulate a compositional semantic theory for a natural language [29, 46, 47, 50, 51], 3. his development of the project of radical interpretation as a vehicle for investigating questions about meaning and the psychological attitudes involved in understanding action [7, 15, 42, 44, 48], 309 310 Ernest Lepore and Kirk Ludwig 4.
    [Show full text]
  • VOLUME LXXII, Number 1 September 2018 NICHOLAS RESCHER
    VOLUME LXXII, Number 1 September 2018 NICHOLAS RESCHER, Distant Posterity: A Philosophical Glance along Time’s Corridor Moralists tell us to care for the interest of others. Epistemologists enjoin us to achieve consensus with others. But accommodating these “others” will be a real problem—seeing that most of them will live beyond our reach and outside our knowledge in their distant future. Philosophers do not seem to worry about distant posterity and yet cannot but acknowledge its relevancy for their concerns. This paper tries to identify and to clarify some of the many important issues that arise here. SYLVAIN DELCOMMINETTE, Plato on Hatred of Philosophy Since its inception, philosophy has aroused both fascination and hostility. What is it about philosophy that provokes such contrasting emotions? Plato’s works offer a valuable opportunity to explore this question, not only because of the dialogue form, which makes it possible to present a range of attitudes toward the practice of philosophy, but also because of Plato’s persistent efforts to define, describe, and defend philosophy as a radically unique activity. In this paper, the author collects and organizes the evidence in order to show that, although Plato presents a wide array of motives for hostility toward philosophy, these are all grounded upon some form of ignorance that is a source of pain. The author also shows how, in well-disposed individuals, a special kind of ignorance can become a source of love rather than hatred, and how these people experience a special kind of pleasure—the very pleasure of practicing and loving philosophy.
    [Show full text]