Bibliography

Total Page:16

File Type:pdf, Size:1020Kb

Bibliography Bibliography Achinstein, P. (2001). The Book of Evidence, Oxford University Press. Alston, W. (1980). Level-confusions in epistemology, Midwest Studies in Philoso- phy 5(1): 135–150. Alston, W. (1983). What’s wrong with immediate knowledge? Synthese 55 (73–95). Alston, W. (1986). Epistemic circularity, Philosophy and Phenomenological Research 47: 1–30. Alston, W. (1993). The Reliability of Sense Perception, Cornell University Press. Baker, A. (2011). Simplicity, in E. N. Zalta (ed.), The Stanford Encyclopedia of Philosophy, summer 2011 edn. Beebe, J. (2008). Bonjour’s arguments against skepticism about the a priori, Philosophical Studies 137: 243–267. Beebe, J. (2011). A priori skepticism, Philosophy and Phenomenological Research 83(3): 583–602. Bergmann, M. (2004a). Epistemic circularity: malignant and benign, Philosophy and Phenomenological Research 69(3): 709–727. Bergmann, M. (2004b). What’s not wrong with foundationalism, Philosophy and Phenomenological Research 68: 161–165. Bergmann, M. (2006a). Bonjour’s dilemma, Philosophical Studies 131: 679–693. Bergmann, M. (2006b). Justification without Awareness, Oxford University Press. Boghossian, P. (2001). Inference and insight, Philosophy and Phenomenological Research 63(3): 633–640. BonJour, L. (1978). Can empirical knowledge have a foundation? American Philosophical Quarterly 15(1): 1–13. BonJour, L. (1985). The Structure of Empirical Knowledge, Harvard University Press. BonJour, L. (1997). Haack on experience and justification, Synthese 112: 13–23. BonJour, L. (1998). InDefenseofPureReason, Cambridge University Press. BonJour, L. (1999). Foundationalism and the external world, Philosophical Perspectives 13: 229–249. BonJour, L. (2000). Critical study of Evan Fales, A Defense of the Given, Nous 43(3): 468–480. BonJour, L. (2001a). Precis of in defense of pure reason, Philosophy and Phe- nomenological Research 63(3): 625–631. BonJour, L. (2001b). Replies, Philosophy and Phenomenological Research 63(3): 673–698. BonJour, L. (2001c). Replies to Pollock and Plantinga, in M. R. DePaul (ed.), Resurrecting Old-Fashion Foundationalism, Rowman and Littlefield. BonJour, L. (2001d). Toward a defense of empirical foundationalism, in M. R. DePaul (ed.), Resurrecting Old-Fashion Foundationalism, Rowman and Littlefield. BonJour, L. (2004). C.I. Lewis on the given and its interpretation, Midwest Studies in Philosophy 28: 195–208. BonJour, L. (2006). Replies, Philosophical Studies 131: 743–759. 182 Bibliography 183 BonJour, L. and Sosa, E. (2003). Epistemic Justification: Internalism vs. Externalism, Foundations vs. Virtues, Blackwell. Brewer, W. and Lambert, B. (2001). The theory-ladenness of observation and the theory-laddenness of the rest of the scientific process, Philosophy of Science 68: S176–S186. Bromberger, S. (1966). Why-questions, in J. Colodny (ed.), Mind and Cosmos, University of Pittsburgh Press. Carnap, R. (1950). Logical Foundations of Probability, University of Chicago Press. Chalmers, A. (2013). What Is This Thing Called Science? 4th edn, Hackett. Chalmers, D. (2010). The Character of Consciousness, Oxford University Press. Chisholm, R. (1942). The problem of the speckled hen, Mind 51: 368–373. Chisholm, R. (1977). The Theory of Knowledge, 2nd edn, Prentice Hall. Christensen, D. (1994). Conservatism in epistemology, Nous 28: 69–89. Christensen, D. (2000). Diachronic coherence versus epistemic impartiality, The Philosophical Review 109: 349–371. Christensen, D. (2004). Putting Logic in Its Place, Oxford University Press. Clark, M. (1963). Knowledge and grounds: a comment on Mr. Gettier’s paper, Analysis 24: 46–48. Cohen, S. (1984). Justification and truth, Philosophical Studies 46: 279–295. Conee, E. and Feldman, R. (2004). Evidentialism: Essays in Epistemology,Oxford University Press. Daniels, N. (2008). Reflective equilibrium, The Stanford Encyclopedia of Philosophy Fall 2008. Daniels, N. (ed.) (1996). Justice and Justification: Reflective Equilibrium in Theory and Practice, Cambridge University Press. David, M. (2007). “Truth as the primary epistemic goal” in Matthias Steup and Ernest Sosa (eds), Contemporary Debates in Epistemology, Blackwell. Davidson, D. (1986). Truth and Interpretation: Perspectives on the Philosophy of Donald Davidson, Blackwell. Douven, I. (2013). Inference to the best explanation, dutch books, and inaccu- racy minimisation, Philosophical Quarterly 63(252): 428–444. Dretske, F. (1970). Epistemic operators, The Journal of Philosophy 67: 1007–1023. Dretske, F. (1977). Laws of nature, Philosophy of Science 44(2): 248–268. Earman, J. (1992). Bayes or Bust? MIT Press. Feldman, E. C. R. (2008). Epistemology: New Essays, Oxford University Press, chapter Evidence. Feldman, R. and Conee, E. (2003). Evidence in Quentin Smith (ed.), Epistemology: New Essays, Oxford University Press. Field, H. (1996). The a prioricity of logic, Proceedings of the Aristotelian Society 96: 359–379. Fitelson, B. (2001). A bayesian account of independent evidence with applica- tions, Philosophy of Science 68(3): 123–140. Fitelson, B. (2005). Inductive logic, in J. Pfeifer and S. Sarkar (eds.), Philosophy of Science: An Encyclopedia, Routledge, pp. 384–394. Fitelson, B. and Hawthorne, J. (2010). The wason task(s) and the paradox of confirmation, Philosophical Perspectives 24: 207–241. Foley, R. (1983). Epistemic conservatism, Philosophical Studies 43: 165–182. Friedman, M. (1999). Reconsidering Logical Positivism, Cambridge University Press. 184 Bibliography Fumerton, R. (1995). Metaepistemology and Skepticism, Rowman and Littlefield. Fumerton, R. (2005). Speckled hens and objects of acquaintance, Philosophical Perspectives 19: 121–138. Fumerton, R. (2008). Epistemic conservatism: theft or honest toil? in T. S. Gendler and J. Hawthorne (eds), Oxford Studies in Epistemology, Vol. 2, Oxford University Press, pp. 63–86. Fumerton, R. and Foley, R. (1985). Davidson’s theism, Philosophical Studies 48: 83–89. Garrett, D. (1997). Cognition and Commitment in Hume’s Philosophy,Oxford University Press. Gendler, T. S. (2001). Empiricism, rationalism, and limits of justification, Philosophy and Phenomenological Research 63: 641–648. Gertler, B. (2001). Introspecting phenomenal states, Philosophy and Phenomeno- logical Research 63: 305–328. Gertler, B. (2011). Self-Knowledge,Routledge. Gettier, E. (1963). Is justified true belief knowledge, Analysis 23(6): 121–123. Goldman, A. (1979a). What is justified belief in G. Pappas (ed.), Justification and Knowledge, pp. 1–23. Goldman, A. (1979b). Varieties of cognitive appraisal, Nous 13: 23–38. Goldman, A. (1980). The internalist conception of justification, Midwest Studies in Philosophy 5: 27–52. Goldman, A. (2011). Toward a synthesis of reliabilism and evidentialism? in Trent Dougherty (ed.), Evidentialism and Its Discontents,OxfordUniversity Press, pp. 254–280. Good, I. (1960). The paradox of confirmation, The British Journal for the Philosophy of Science 11(42): 145–149. Goodman, N. (1952). Sense and certainty, Philosophical Review 61(2): 160–167. Goodman, N. (1965). Fact, Fiction, and Forecast, Bobbs-Merrill. Goodman, N. (1979). Ways of Worldmaking, Harvard University Press. Grice, H. (2001). Logic and conversation in A.P. Martinich (ed.), The Philosophy of Language, Oxford University Press, pp. 165–175. Haack, S. (1993). Evidence and Inquiry. Blackwell. Harman, G. (1965). Inference to the best explanation, Philosophical Review 74 (88–95). Harman, G. (1973). Thought,Princeton. Harman, G. (1986). Change in View: Principles of Reasoning, MIT Press. Harman, G. (1995). Rationality, in E.E. Smith and D.N. Osherson (eds), Thinking: Invitation to Cognitive Science, MIT Press. Harman, G. (1999). Reasoning, Meaning, and Mind, Oxford University Press. Harman, G. (2001). General foundations versus rational insight, Philosophy and Phenomenological Research 63(3): 657–663. Harman, G. and Sherman, B. (2004). Knowledge, assumptions, and lotteries, Philosophical Issues 14: 492–500. Hempel, C. G. (1945). Studies in the logic of confirmation (i.), Mind 213: 1–26. Hempel, C. G. (1966). Philosopy of Natural Science, Prentice-Hall. Hempel, C. G. (1965). Aspects of Scientific Explanation and Other Essays in the Philosophy of Science, The Free Press. Hempel, C. G. and Oppenheim, P. (1948). Studies in the logic of explanation, Philosophy of Science 15(2): 135–175. Bibliography 185 Henderson, L. (forthcoming). Bayesianism and inference to the best explanation, British Journal for the Philosophy of Science. Howard-Snyder, D. (2005). Foundationalism and arbitrariness, Pacific Philosophi- cal Quarterly 86: 18–24. Howard-Snyder, D. and Coffman, E. (2006). Three arguments against founda- tionalism: arbitrariness, epistemic regress, and existential support, Canadian Journal of Philosophy 36: 535–564. Howson, C. and Urbach, P. (1993). Scientific Reasoning: The Bayesian Approach, 2nd edn, Open Court. Huemer, M. (2001). Skepticism and the Veil of Perception, Rowman and Littlefield. Huemer, M. (2003). Arbitrary foundations? Philosophical Forum 34: 141–152. Huemer, M. (2009). Explanationist aid for the theory of inductive logic, British Journal for the Philosophy of Science 60: 345–375. Huemer, M. (2011). Does probability theory refute coherentism? Journal of Philosophy 108: 463–472. Hume, D. (2007). An Enquiry Concerning Human Understanding,OxfordUniversity Press. Hylton, P. (2007). Quine,Routledge. Jackson, F. (1982). Epiphenomenal qualia, Philosophical Quarterly 32: 127–136. Jenkins, C. (2008). Romeo, Ren´e, and the reasons why: what explanation is, Proceedings of the Aristotelian Society 58(1):
Recommended publications
  • Haack on Justification and Experience
    LAURENCE BONJOUR HAACK ON JUSTIFICATION AND EXPERIENCE Evidence and Inquiry1 is a wonderfully rich and insightful book. It contains compelling analyses and critiques of a wide variety of epistemological and anti-epistemological views pertaining to empirical knowledge, including recent versions of foundationalism and coherentism, Popper's ªepistemol- ogy without a knowing subjectº, Quine's naturalized epistemology, Gold- man's reliabilism, the scientistic views of Stich and the Churchlands, and the ªvulgar pragmatismº, as Haack quite appropriately refers to it, of Rorty and the more recent Stich. All of this material is valuable, and much of it seems to me entirely decisive. In particular, the critical discussion of reliabilism is by far the best and most complete in the literature; and the analysis and refutation of the various recent efforts to evade or dismiss the traditional epistemological projects and issues is nothing short of devas- tating. Indeed, it is its resolute refusal to be diverted from the pursuit of the traditional epistemological issues that seems to me the most valuable feature of the book. In this spirit, while applauding Haack's demolition of the various anti- epistemological views ± it was dirty work, but someone had to do it ± I will focus here on her discussions of the views that attempt to solve rather than dissolve the traditional epistemological issues concerning empirical knowledge. I will begin by considering Haack's critique of recent versions of coherentism and foundationalism. I will then turn to a more extended exposition and evaluation of her own proposed third alternative, which she dubs foundherentism. 1. I begin with the view that has, until fairly recently, been closest to my own heart, namely coherentism.
    [Show full text]
  • COSMOS + TAXIS | Volume 8 Issues 4 + 5 2020
    ISSN 2291-5079 Vol 8 | Issue 4 + 5 2020 COSMOS + TAXIS Studies in Emergent Order and Organization Philosophy, the World, Life and the Law: In Honour of Susan Haack PART I INTRODUCTION PHILOSOPHY AND HOW WE GO ABOUT IT THE WORLD AND HOW WE UNDERSTAND IT COVER IMAGE Susan Haack on being awarded the COSMOS + TAXIS Ulysses Medal by University College Dublin Studies in Emergent Order and Organization Photo by Jason Clarke VOLUME 8 | ISSUE 4 + 5 2020 http: www.jasonclarkephotography.ie PHILOSOPHY, THE WORLD, LIFE AND EDITORIAL BOARDS THE LAW: IN HONOUR OF SUSAN HAACK HONORARY FOUNDING EDITORS EDITORS Joaquin Fuster David Emanuel Andersson* PART I University of California, Los Angeles (editor-in-chief) David F. Hardwick* National Sun Yat-sen University, The University of British Columbia Taiwan Lawrence Wai-Chung Lai William Butos University of Hong Kong (deputy editor) Foreword: “An Immense and Enduring Contribution” .............1 Trinity College Russell Brown Frederick Turner University of Texas at Dallas Laurent Dobuzinskis* Editor’s Preface ............................................2 (deputy editor) Simon Fraser University Mark Migotti Giovanni B. Grandi From There to Here: Fifty-Plus Years of Philosophy (deputy editor) with Susan Haack . 4 The University of British Columbia Mark Migotti Leslie Marsh* (managing editor) The University of British Columbia PHILOSOPHY AND HOW WE GO ABOUT IT Nathan Robert Cockram (assistant managing editor) Susan Haack’s Pragmatism as a The University of British Columbia Multi-faceted Philosophy ...................................38 Jaime Nubiola CONSULTING EDITORS Metaphysics, Religion, and Death Corey Abel Peter G. Klein or We’ll Always Have Paris ..................................48 Denver Baylor University Rosa Maria Mayorga Thierry Aimar Paul Lewis Naturalism, Innocent Realism and Haack’s Sciences Po Paris King’s College London subtle art of balancing Philosophy ...........................60 Nurit Alfasi Ted G.
    [Show full text]
  • A Critical Examination of Bonjour's, Haack's, And
    A CRITICAL EXAMINATION OF BONJOUR’S, HAACK’S, AND DANCY’S THEORY OF EMPIRICAL JUSTIFICATION Dionysis CHRISTIAS ABSTRACT: In this paper, we shall describe and critically evaluate four contemporary theories which attempt to solve the problem of the infinite regress of reasons: BonJour's ‘impure’ coherentism, BonJour's foundationalism, Haack's ‘foundherentism’ and Dancy's pure coherentism. These theories are initially put forward as theories about the justification of our empirical beliefs; however, in fact they also attempt to provide a successful response to the question of their own ‘metajustification.’ Yet, it will be argued that 1) none of the examined theories is successful as a theory of justification of our empirical beliefs, and that 2) they also fall short of being adequate theories of metajustification. It will be further suggested that the failure of these views on justification is not coincidental, but is actually a consequence of deeper and tacitly held problematic epistemological assumptions (namely, the requirements of justificatory generality and epistemic priority), whose acceptance paves the way towards a generalized scepticism about empirical justification. KEYWORDS: Laurence BonJour, Susan Haack, Jonathan Dancy, empirical justification, epistemic priority requirement, justificatory generality requirement, scepticism 1. Introduction Most of our empirical beliefs seem at first sight perfectly justified. For example, ordinary observational beliefs (of the form “the table on which I’m writing is red” or “the chair on which I’m sitting is blue”), mnemonic beliefs (“I was watching television in the morning”), testimony beliefs (“the first world war begun in 1914”) and even non-observational, scientific beliefs (“protons consist of quarks”) seem to be paradigms of justified empirical beliefs.
    [Show full text]
  • Does All Knowledge Have an Epistemic Foundation?
    Philsoc Student Essay Prize, Hilary term, 2020 – 2nd Prize Does all knowledge have an epistemic foundation? If so, then explain what such foundations must be like and evaluate how extensive our knowledge is in the light of this requirement. If not, then explain why. By Michelle Hogan The question of epistemic foundations is about the structure of knowledge, and the justification of our empirical beliefs. The three options which Agrippa's trilemma presents us with regarding justification are that our beliefs are: (i) unsupported; (ii) supported by a circular chain of justification, or (iii) supported by a non-repeating infinite chain of justification. Epistemic foundations are concerned with the unsupported beliefs which are deemed to be non-inferential, and this theory is known as foundationalism. In this essay, I will consider the strengths and weaknesses of foundationalism, and contrast them with those of circular chains of justification, known as coherentism. I will also discuss the merits of Susan Haack's 'foundherentism', which is a combination of these two views. There is, obviously, no end to the infinite chain of justification, known as infinitism, which is problematic, because its completion looks impossible, and it is difficult to see how knowledge could thereby be acquired. In his Theaetetus, Plato was concerned with determining what knowledge is, and said that it could be regarded as 'true judgement with an account'. This is often taken now to be justified true belief (JTB) and if we exclude Gettier cases, in which someone might have a JTB but not knowledge – such as by a stroke of luck – then we have a workable definition.
    [Show full text]
  • Read Book Epistemologies of the South 1St Edition
    EPISTEMOLOGIES OF THE SOUTH 1ST EDITION PDF, EPUB, EBOOK Boaventura de Sousa Santos | 9781317260349 | | | | | Epistemologies of the South 1st edition PDF Book The book examines its subject through the analysis of three main case studies, namely those of Colombia, India, and South Africa. It began to emerge as a distinct subfield in the 20th century. Rationalist views can range from modest views in mathematics and logic such as that of Gottlob Frege to ambitious metaphysical systems such as that of Baruch Spinoza. Eva Marques rated it really liked it Jun 28, Stanford Encyclopedia of Philosophy. Help Learn to edit Community portal Recent changes Upload file. Epistemologists study the nature of knowledge, epistemic justification , the rationality of belief , and various related issues. An alternative resolution to the regress problem is known as " infinitism ". Views that emphasize the importance of a posteriori knowledge are generally classified as empiricist. Sep 14, Kelly Dombroski rated it really liked it. In that case, we can't The word "epistemology" was properly introduced into Anglophone philosophical literature by Scottish philosopher James Frederick Ferrier in , who used it in his Institutes of Metaphysics :. Chicago: The University of Chicago Press. Gettier then goes on to offer a second similar case, providing the means by which the specifics of his examples can be generalized into a broader problem for defining knowledge in terms of justified true belief. Either there are some beliefs that we can be justified for holding, without being able to justify them on the basis of any other belief, or else for each justified belief there is an infinite regress of potential justification [the nebula theory].
    [Show full text]
  • Crosswords and Coherence David Atkinson and Jeanne Peijnenburg
    CROSSWORDS AND COHERENCE DAVID ATKINSON AND JEANNE PEIJNENBURG A COMMON OBJECTION TO COHERENTISM is that it cannot account for truth: if a true theory and a false theory are equally coherent (and equally simple, comprehensive, and so forth), coherentism gives us no reason to prefer the former over the latter. By stretching Susan Haack’s crossword metaphor to its limits, we show that there are circumstances under which this objection is untenable. Although these circumstances may seem remote, they are in accordance with our most fundamental and ambitious physical theories. Coherence might be truth conducive after all. I Susan Haack famously launched foundherentism as a fitting portrayal of the way in which we build up knowledge of the world.1 A foundherentist explicitly has an ecumenical intent, encompassing requirements of both coherentists and foundationalists. Like the coherentist, a foundherentist stresses that our beliefs about the world must hang together in one way or another; and like the foundationalist, she emphasizes that they must somehow be grounded in the world around us. Foundherentism is thus an amalgam which draws on important insights of two factions that are often pictured as being opposed to one another. In a happy clarification of the nature of foundherentism, Haack introduced her metaphor of the crossword puzzle. The solution of a crossword combines features that are reminiscent both of foundationalism and coherentism. It mirrors the coherentist creed by demanding that words must intersect other words on the same letter, while it reflects the foundationalist stance by the existence of ‘clues’ that provide grounds, as it were, for each entry in the puzzle.
    [Show full text]
  • David Atkinson Jeanne Peijnenburg Probability and the Regress Problem
    Synthese Library 383 Studies in Epistemology, Logic, Methodology, and Philosophy of Science David Atkinson Jeanne Peijnenburg Fading Foundations Probability and the Regress Problem Synthese Library Studies in Epistemology, Logic, Methodology, and Philosophy of Science Volume 383 Editor-in-Chief Otávio Bueno, University of Miami, Department of Philosophy, USA Editors Berit Brogaard, University of Miami, USA Anjan Chakravartty, University of Notre Dame, USA Steven French, University of Leeds, UK Catarina Dutilh Novaes, University of Groningen, The Netherlands More information about this series at http://www.springer.com/series/6607 David Atkinson • Jeanne Peijnenburg Fading Foundations Probability and the Regress Problem David Atkinson Jeanne Peijnenburg University of Groningen University of Groningen Groningen, The Netherlands Groningen, The Netherlands Synthese Library ISBN 978-3-319-58294-8 ISBN 978-3-319-58295-5 (eBook) DOI 10.1007/978-3-319-58295-5 Library of Congress Control Number: 2017941185 © The Editor(s) (if applicable) and The Author(s) 2017. This book is an open access publication Open Access This book is distributed under the terms of the Creative Commons Attribution 4.0 International License (http://creativecommons.org/licenses/by/4.0/), which permits use, duplication, adaptation, distribution and reproduction in any medium or format, as long as you give appropriate credit to the original author(s) and the source, provide a link to the Creative Commons license and indicate if changes were made. The images or other third party material in this book are included in the work’s Creative Commons license, unless indicated otherwise in the credit line; if such material is not included in the work’s Creative Commons license and the respective action is not permitted by statutory regulation, users will need to obtain permission from the license holder to duplicate, adapt or reproduce the material.
    [Show full text]
  • Ucin1028837654.Pdf (108.79
    UNIVERSITY OF CINCINNATI _____________ , 20 _____ I,______________________________________________, hereby submit this as part of the requirements for the degree of: ________________________________________________ in: ________________________________________________ It is entitled: ________________________________________________ ________________________________________________ ________________________________________________ ________________________________________________ Approved by: ________________________ ________________________ ________________________ ________________________ ________________________ BONJOUR’S RECONSIDERATION OF FOUNDATIONALISM A thesis submitted to the Division of Research and Advanced Studies of the University of Cincinnati in partial fulfillment of the requirements for the degree of MASTER OF ARTS in the Philosophy Department of the College of Arts and Sciences 2002 by Fred J. Harrington B.A., The Ohio State University, 1995 Committee: Robert C. Richardson, Ph.D. (Chair) Robert A. Skipper, Ph.D. Thomas W. Polger, Ph.D. BonJour’s Reconsideration of Foundationalism Fred Harrington ABSRTACT: In BonJour’s recent essay, “The Dialectic of Foundationalism and Coherentism,” he argues for a reconsideration of foundationalism. BonJour makes three assumptions: (i) that the realist conception of truth as correspondence with the appropriate region of mind-independent reality is correct; (ii) that foundationalism is offering an account of “the fundamental structure of the epistemic justification of contingent or empirical
    [Show full text]
  • Foundherentism: Basic Concepts and Distinctions 1
    Philosophy 3340 - Epistemology Susan Haack's Foundherentist Theory of Empirical Justification 1. Foundherentism: Basic Concepts and Distinctions 1. S-beliefs versus C-beliefs: "A's S-belief that p": A mental state of A's that is A's believing that p. "A's C-belief that p": The content of A's S-belief that P - namely, the proposition that p. 2. Evidence for p can be divided into S-evidence and C-evidence: A's S-evidence with respect to p consists of the "set of states of A causally related to his S-belief that p." A's C-evidence with respect to p consists of "a set of propositions capable of standing in logical or quasi-logical relations to the C-belief that p." 3. Not just any type of state can be part of a person's S-evidence: "'A's S-evidence with respect to p' will refer to those experiential and belief-states of A's which belong, at the time in question, to the causal nexus of A's S-belief that p." (421) 4. Haack divides S-evidence with respect to p up into two components: (1) A's S-reasons with respect to p is that part of A's S-evidence with respect to p that consists of other beliefs. (2) A's experiential S-evidence with respect to p is that part of A's S-evidence with respect to p that consists of A's "perceptions, his introspective awareness of his own mental goings-on, and memory traces of his earlier perceptual and introspective states." (421) 5.
    [Show full text]
  • Iceberg Epistemology David Henderson; Terrence Horgan Philosophy and Phenomenological Research, Vol
    Iceberg Epistemology David Henderson; Terrence Horgan Philosophy and Phenomenological Research, Vol. 61, No. 3. (Nov., 2000), pp. 497-535. Stable URL: http://links.jstor.org/sici?sici=0031-8205%28200011%2961%3A3%3C497%3AIE%3E2.0.CO%3B2-E Philosophy and Phenomenological Research is currently published by International Phenomenological Society. Your use of the JSTOR archive indicates your acceptance of JSTOR's Terms and Conditions of Use, available at http://www.jstor.org/about/terms.html. JSTOR's Terms and Conditions of Use provides, in part, that unless you have obtained prior permission, you may not download an entire issue of a journal or multiple copies of articles, and you may use content in the JSTOR archive only for your personal, non-commercial use. Please contact the publisher regarding any further use of this work. Publisher contact information may be obtained at http://www.jstor.org/journals/ips.html. Each copy of any part of a JSTOR transmission must contain the same copyright notice that appears on the screen or printed page of such transmission. The JSTOR Archive is a trusted digital repository providing for long-term preservation and access to leading academic journals and scholarly literature from around the world. The Archive is supported by libraries, scholarly societies, publishers, and foundations. It is an initiative of JSTOR, a not-for-profit organization with a mission to help the scholarly community take advantage of advances in technology. For more information regarding JSTOR, please contact [email protected]. http://www.jstor.org Mon Oct 29 22:54:42 2007 Philosophy and Phenomenological Research Vol.
    [Show full text]
  • Foundationalism, Representationalism, and Truth
    Foundationalism, Representationalism, and Truth The Debate Between Haack and Rorty A thesis submitted to fulfil requirements for the degree of Master of Arts (Research). Alistair Kitchen Faculty of Arts, The University of Sydney Word Count: 30,784 I certify that the intellectual content of this thesis is the product of my own work and that all the assistance received in preparing this thesis and sources have been acknowledged. Alistair Kitchen 1 Abstract: This thesis defends Rorty’s neo-pragmatism from the criticism of fellow pragmatist Susan Haack. Rortian neo-pragmatism threatens to undermine Haack’s own theory of justification, foundherentism, which Haack argues is superior to foundationalism and coherentism. Haack claims that Rorty, first, has no good arguments against epistemology and, second, proffers an unappealing alternative. I suggest that Rorty does have a good argument against epistemology, and that that argument is illuminated by a closer look at Haack’s notion of “ratification”. Ratification is shown to be an unachievable and yet self-imposed standard. Understanding the motivations which cause Haack to pursue ratification requires an investigation of truth. I explicate in some detail Rorty’s conception of truth and contrast it with Haack’s interpretation of his position. I develop this reading by marrying Rorty’s earlier and later discussions on the matter, and conclude by suggesting ways to develop Rorty’s approach further. The result is a minimal account of truth that avoids the pitfalls of Haack’s reading, and an approach to epistemology that bypasses the need for ratification and the worries of the epistemological sceptic. 2 Table of Contents Introduction ..........................................................................................
    [Show full text]
  • Epistemology.Pdf
    Epistemology An overview Contents 1 Main article 1 1.1 Epistemology ............................................. 1 1.1.1 Background and meaning ................................... 1 1.1.2 Knowledge .......................................... 1 1.1.3 Acquiring knowledge ..................................... 5 1.1.4 Skepticism .......................................... 7 1.1.5 See also ............................................ 7 1.1.6 References .......................................... 8 1.1.7 Works cited .......................................... 9 1.1.8 External links ......................................... 10 2 Knowledge 11 2.1 Knowledge ............................................... 11 2.1.1 Theories of knowledge .................................... 11 2.1.2 Communicating knowledge ................................. 12 2.1.3 Situated knowledge ...................................... 13 2.1.4 Partial knowledge ...................................... 13 2.1.5 Scientific knowledge ..................................... 13 2.1.6 Religious meaning of knowledge ............................... 14 2.1.7 See also ............................................ 15 2.1.8 References .......................................... 15 2.1.9 External links ......................................... 16 2.2 Belief ................................................. 16 2.2.1 Knowledge and epistemology ................................. 17 2.2.2 As a psychological phenomenon ............................... 17 2.2.3 Epistemological belief compared to religious belief
    [Show full text]