I am delighted if you decide to quote this paper—please send me an email if you do. Comments are welcome. Yours, ZZs. NAMINGWITH NECESSITY ZsófiaZvolenszky DepartmentofLogic,InstituteofPhilosophy,EötvösUniversity(ELTE),Budapest [email protected] August15,2007

I.INTRODUCTION Despitealltheattentionphilosophershavebeenpayingto Naming and Necessity ,theyhave notrealizedjusthowaptthetitleis:namingand necessity are intimately connected, even moreintimatelythenSaulKripkehasledustobelieve.Theconceptionofnecessityclarified byKripke—metaphysicalorcounterfactualnecessity—helpsusunderstandwhatourordinary practiceofusingpropernamesisabout;andpropernameusageinturnhelpsusunderstand whatcounterfactualsituations(possibleworlds)areabout.Myaimistoproposeyetanother picture: (i) inherent in propername usage is the expectation that names refer to modally robust individuals :1 individuals that can sustain modal predications like ‘is necessarily human’, or ‘might have discovered Goldbach’s conjecture’; (ii) these modally robust individualsarethefundamentalbuildingblocksonthebasisofwhichpossibleworldsshould be conceived in a modal intended to mirror the conceptual apparatus behind ordinarymodaltalk. InPartII,Idescribe(i)and(ii),whatIcalltheindividualdrivenpicture.InPartIII,I relate this picture to others. The preKripkean pictures of individuals and modality were markedly different. First, there was the conception of modality as logical or analytic necessity.Second,therewastheconceptionofpossibleworldsneededforphysicalnecessity, givingrisetoissuesaboutthetransworldidentificationofindividuals.ThirdcameKripke’s proposalthatpropernamesarerigiddesignators.Fourth,inthewakeofKripke’s Naming and Necessity lectures, David Kaplan suggested that proper names were directly referential expressionswhosepropositionalcontributionwastheirreferent.Sections1–4summarizeeach ofthesefourmilestones.Kripke’sviewwasclosetotheindividualdrivenpicture.Kaplan’s was even closer—when he was not talking about and what proper names contributetothem.Butsubsequentproponentsofdirecttheoryandtherelatedview ofMillianismpickeduponthepropositionsframework.Theyfeltthatthesemanticsofproper namescouldandshouldsteerclearofmetaphysicalconsiderationsaboutmodality.Section5 describesonestrikingexampleofthis:JosephAlmogfoundtheconnectionsbetweennaming and necessity developed by Kripke “much too intimate”, and proceeded to develop a “different,substantivelydifferent,pictureofnaming”—namingwithoutnecessity,ashecalled it(Almog1986,210).Iwillarguethatweshouldput the necessity back into naming. By rediscoveringtheindividualdrivenpicture,wecangleancrucialinsightsaboutbothnaming andnecessity. 1 This paper has benefited from Kit Fine`s incisive comments. Thanks are due to him as well as to Stephen Schiffer, both of whom gave extensive comments on an ancestor of this paper ‘Analyticity and Kripke’s SemanticTurn’.Theygentlyconvincedmetotakeanaltogetherdifferenttackandframethingsintermsofwhat Inowcallmodallyrobustindividualsandtheindividualdrivenpicture.Butthesearen’tmyterms,atleastnot thefirstone—itisShamikDasgupta’slabel,suggestedtomebyKitFine.

1 II.THEINDIVIDUAL DRIVENPICTURE Thatweinterpretmodalclaimslike‘Goldbachmighthaveeschewedmathematicsaltogether’ inabreezeisafactthatgoeslargelyunnoticed.Weshouldnoticeitthough,fortheeaseof interpretationallowsustohomeinontheconceptualbuildingblocksassociatedwithproper nameuse(andmoregenerally,withsocalledderemodalclaims):modallyrobustindividuals (Section1).Thisthesisofmodallyrobustindividuals does mean we can construe possible worlds—counterfactualsituations—intermsofmodallyrobustindividuals,yieldingahitherto unrecognizedconceptionofpossibleworlds;thisisexploredinSection5.Butbeforegetting there,itiswelltoclarifyacoupleofthingsthethesisdoes not mean.Itdoesnotmeanthat every proper name refers to a modally robust individual. Instead only what I will call anchored propernamesdo—forexample,‘JacktheRipper’,despitebeingpartoftheEnglish vocabulary,isnotanchoredbecauseithasnotbeenfiguredoutwhoJackwas(Section2).Nor doesthethesismeanthateveryindividualismodally robust: an unspecified counterfactual sisterofmine,forexample,isnot(Section3).Indeed,anattempttointroduceapropername forsuchanindividualwouldbethwarted;thissituation is worse than the fate of ‘Jack the Ripper’,whichhasbeenintroducedintoEnglish(andhasbecomea common currency name , inKaplan’sterminology)butisawaitinganchoring.Inaddition,thethesisdoesnotmeanthat takingmodaltalkatfacevaluewouldrequireustogiveupon —accordingtowhich only actual individuals exist, merely possible ones, like my unspecified, merely possible sister,donot(Section4). 1. Interpreting modal claims: de dicto and de re Goldbach’sconjecturewasdiscoveredbyaman.Butthecourseofhistorycouldhavegone otherwise: the discovery might have been made by a woman instead. Modal concerns what might or must be the case (representedby the sentence operators  and , respectively)asopposedtowhat is thecase.Wehavejustencounteredamodalclaim(‘GC’is shortfor‘Goldbach’sconjecture’): (1) Itmighthavebeenthat:awomandiscoveredGC. Possibly:awomandiscoveredGC thediscovererofGCisawoman (1)isreadilyinterpreted:itconcernsacounterfactualsituation,anunrealizedcircumstancein whichawomanwasthediscovererofthehypothesisthateveryevennumbergreaterthan2is the sum of two primes; for example, we could envision a scenario in which Madam du ChâteletbeatGoldbachtothediscovery.Wedonotknow ifthisreallyispossible,butwe haveahunchitis.Thiswayofthinkingabout(1)iseasyandoverwhelminglynatural. Interpretingthefollowingisequallystraightforward: (2) Goldbachissuchthat he himself mighthaveeschewedmathematics. Goldbachissuchthatpossibly:he himself eschewsmathematics Goldbachissuchthat he himself eschewsmathematics (3) ThepersontodiscoverGCissuchthat he himself mighthaveeschewedmath. ThediscovererofGCissuchthatpossibly: he himself eschewsmathematics ThediscovererofGCissuchthat he himself eschewsmathematics Both(2)and(3)invokeacounterfactualsituationinwhichChristianGoldbach,thePrussian mathematicianfromKönigsberg,the man himself ,choosesaprofessiondifferentfromtheone

2 he actually had; for example, we could envision a scenario in which Goldbach trains to becomeadoctor.Wedonot know ifthisreallyispossible,butwehaveahunchitis.Thisway ofthinkingabout(2)and(3)isalsoeasyandoverwhelminglynatural. Considering counterfactual situations, as we just did, involves the counterfactual conception of necessity and possibility—which Saul Kripke called the metaphysical conception.Itisabouthowthingsmightormusthavebeen hadthingsgonedifferentlywith respecttodetailsoftheactualcourseofhistory:hadGoldbachchosenadifferentcareer,or hadMadamduChâteletlivedpastherforties.This conceptionis aboutdifferentwaysthe world might have been; it is not about linguistic matters like the following: ‘Christian Goldbach’ introduced as a name for someone else, or the Goldbach conjecture bearing a differentname. (1)isnotaboutanyoneinparticular—itisnomoreaboutGoldbachthanitisabout MadamduChâtelet,oracounterfactualsisterGoldbachmighthavehad.Really,(1)isnot about anyonespecific,insteaddescribingasituationinwhich some woman or other discovers the conjecture. General modal claims of this sort aresaidtoinvolve modality de dicto. By ,(2)and(3)areaboutsomeonespecific:Goldbach.Bothdescribewhatmighthave happened to him , had his life gone differently. This way of ascribing modal properties to individualsdirectlyinvolveswhatiscalled modality de re .Forvariousreasons,deremodality had,inthepast gained notoriety,whileitsdedicto sibling has been considered relatively harmless.SectionsIII.1andIII.2willgivesomeofthereasons. Acrucialpointworthstressing:weareattimesundecided,baffled,ordoubtfulabout the truth ofcertainmodalclaims:thehunchisabsent,isweaker,conflictswithotherhunches, or points in the opposite direction. But issues about hunchstrength and hunchclarity are completelyirrelevanttobothofthefollowing:thedivergingreputationsofdedictomodality (the tame one) and de re modality (the notorious one); and the ease with which the counterfactual conception of modality allows us to interpret dere and dedicto modal claims alike ,asillustratedabove.Herearetwoexampleswhereourhunchesforsakeus: abafflingdedictomodalclaim: (4) thediscovererofGCeschewsmathematics, andabafflingderemodalclaim: (5) Goldbach/ThediscovererofGCissuchthat (s)heisawoman. Ourbafflementisoverwhether(4)and(5)are true ,andwhatitwouldbeforthemtobetrue. (4)invitesustoenvisionascenarioinwhichsomeonediscoversGoldbach’sconjecture and avoids mathematics. (Serially accomplished deeds? No problem. But simultaneously? Dubious.) (5) prompts us to imagine the man Goldbach as a woman. (Could he undergo genuinegendertransformation?Whoknows.CouldGoldbachhavebeenawomanfrombirth, orfromconception?Doubtful,ifnotincoherent.)Still, interpreting (4)and(5), making sense ofthemisstraightforward,posingnomoredifficultythan(1)–(3):(4)describesaspossiblea scenario in which someone discovers the conjecture and eschews mathematics, while (5) deemspossibleascenarioinwhichGoldbach(actuallyaman)himself isawoman.Thefact that we are at a loss as to whether these really are possible scenarios does not thwart the interpretiveeffort. Thefollowingholdsnosurpriseseither: (6) Goldbachmighthaveeschewedmathematics or:ItmighthavebeenthatGoldbacheschewedmathematics Possibly:Goldbacheschewsmathematics

3 Goldbacheschewsmathematics Justlikethedere (2),wehaveaclaimaboutGoldbachhimself—thathemighthaveeschewed mathematics.Forourpurposes,whatmattersisa semantic distinctionbetweendereandde dictostatements:interpretingtheformer(butnotthelatter) presupposes the intelligibility of ascribing modal properties directly to individuals .2Accordingly,(6)isaderemodalclaim. Wecanmakeamoregeneralobservation.Considerthecombinationof“ingredients”in(6):  the metaphysical or counterfactual conception of necessity and possibility (about counterfactualsituations),and  propernames. This combination automatically yields a de re modal claim. With respect to metaphysical necessity, proper name occurrences are invariably de re. In this sense, proper names are special de re vehicles.Bycontrast,the“exportation”ofadefinitedescription(yielding (3) from(1))involvedamovefromdedictotodere. 2. Proper names: anchored, underway, and unanchorable Deremodalclaims—withorwithoutpropernames—poseaninterpretivetask.Andwiththe metaphysical conception of modality on board, we have just seen that task effortlessly accomplished.Thekey:theindividualssuchclaimsareaboutmustbeonesthatcansustain modalpredications—theymustbe modally robust .Forexample,thename‘Goldbach’refers to a modally robust individual of whom it makes sense to that he might have becomeadoctor,thathemusthavebeenofmathematician,thatheisnecessarilyhuman,or possibly a woman. Of course, de re modal claims about objects (tables, buildings), geographicallocations,corporationsarejustaseasytointerpret.Bafflementover truth value iseasiertocomeby formodalclaimsinvolvingnames like ‘Flatiron Building’, ‘Madison Square’, ‘Manhattan’, ‘Tiffany & Co.’, but as before, that creates no interpretive obstacle. ‘Whatismore,wecaninterpretderemodalclaimsaboutmathematicalentitiesandfictional characters in a breeze. Accordingly, de re vehicles include proper names like ‘π’, ‘Holly Golightly’,allpresupposingastheirreferencemodallyrobustindividuals. 3 Does this mean that proper names always purport to refer to modally robust individuals?Yes.Forwithrespecttometaphysicalmodality,propernamesalwaysyielddere modalclaims.Doesit meanthatpropernamesalways refer tomodallyrobustindividuals? No.Quiteoften,apropernameisintroducedintothelanguagetodubanactualindividual, 2Thedistinctioncanbedrawndifferently,insyntacticterms:modalitydereinvolvesquantifyingacrossamodal operator(quantifyingin),whilemodalitydereneednot(Fine1989,43;Kaplan1986,268–72).(Thesyntactic distinctionisthecentraloneintheofSectionIII.1,aboutlogicaloranalyticnecessity.) 3Propernamesformathematicalentitiesandfictionalcharactersareintriguing;Iwillnotdwellonthemhere, exceptfornoting,asIdid,thatanaturaloftheproposalthatpropernamespresupposemodallyrobust individualsastheirreference,istotreatnumbersandfictionalcharactersasmodallyrobust.KaplanandKripke havemadesuggestionstoextendtheirownviewsalongtheselines(Kaplan1989b:107–8,n101).Whatkindof modallyrobustindividualmightamathematicalentityorafictionalcharacter be ?Theusualandobviousanswer is:anabstractentity.KitFinehasamorenuancedview:someexistentsdonotenjoyaformofworldlyexistence (theydonotexistintheworldorhaveanyworldlyproperties).Finementionsmathematicalentitieslikesetsand doesnotmentionfictionalcharacters;buthisframeworkcaneasily makeroomforthem.Accordingly,πand Cinderellaarenotworldlyexistents;theydononethelessenjoyaformof unworldly or transcendent existence (with unworldly properties, relations applying to them—for example, the formal relation of identity) (Fine 2005a,341–5,353–4).Fine’sviewis,Ithink,mostnaturallyinterpretedwithmodallyrobustindividuals,some ofwhichenjoyaworldlyaswellasanunworldlyformofexistence(Goldbachissuchanindividual),andsome ofwhichpartakeinthelatteronly(π,forexample).Seeespeciallythesuggestion(2005a:342)that“modalfacts aretranscendental”.

4 andthenameissuccessfullyanchoredtotheintendedindividual:‘ChristianGoldbach’,and ‘Königsberg’are anchored names .Whenfirstintroducedin1846,theplanetname‘Neptune’ wasnotyetanchored—theexistenceofaplanettoexplainperturbationsintheorbitofUranus wasinferredbasedonmathematicalcalculations;thenamewasintroducedbydescription. 4 Initially,‘Neptune’wasadmittedintothelanguageon“newemployeeprobationstatus”—it wasan underway proper name .Subsequentsightings,evenifsomeweremistakenlyregarded as sightings of Neptune, eventually converged on a single planet, anchoring the name ‘Neptune’ to the planet. But names of hypothetical objects were not always such success stories.InthewakeofhissuccesswithNeptune,theFrenchastronomerLeVerrierputforth another hypothesis about the existence of an intraMercurial planet (named ‘Vulcan’), to explainperturbationsintheorbitofMercury.‘Vulcan’ was thus admitted as an underway propername.TherewerevariousindependentsightingsmistakenlybelievedtobeofVulcan beforeenthusiasmdwindled;By1916,Einstein’sgeneraltheoryofrelativityconfirmedthat the perturbations were produced by the gravitationalfieldoftheSun;there wasnointra Mercurialplanetatall;theVulcanhypothesiswasrefuted;‘Vulcan’turnedoutnottoreferto anything;andwiththis,thenamewasdeemed unanchorable . Whataboutacounterfactualsituationinwhichthename ‘Vulcan’ is also a success story?Imagineacounterfactualscenariowiththelawsofphysicsslightlydifferent,andthere being an intraMercurial planet affecting the orbit of Mercury; Le Verrier puts forth his hypothesis; there are sightings converging on the planet, the name ‘Vulcan’ becomes anchored.Butthatisnot our term‘Vulcan’thatgetsanchoredinthecounterfactualsuccess story,butadifferentone. Itispreposteroustothink that in coining the name, Le Verrier managed to dub that counterfactual object even though his dubbing attempt failed in the actual world. 5‘Vulcan’mighthavebeenasuccessstoryjustas‘Königsberg’mighthavebeen introducedasanameforariverinsteadofacity;butthatisirrelevanttohowandwhether these strings, asparts of our language,became anchored. 6 No counterfactual situation can accomplishtheanchoringof our name‘Vulcan’,giventhatinfact,itwasnotanchored.Sothe name lacks a referent in every counterfactual situation; it is unanchorable. Kaplan (1973) makesthispointeloquentlywithrespecttoafictionalnamelike‘Pegasus’ 7.Butwhatisfar

4SeeDonnellan(1979),andKripke(1980,79,n33). 5MyargumenthereisdifferentfromKripke’smetaphysicalthesisagainsttheviewthatnamesofnonexistents refertomerelypossibleindividuals(Kripke1980, 156–7): regarding the various hypothetical winged horses, which one is Pegasus?—one cannot say which one. In Section II.4, this is construed as a problem that some individualsareinsufficientlyspecific.IagreewithKaplanthatthisproblemaffectsnamesintroducedformerely possibleentities,butisnottheproblemthatemptynameslike‘Vulcan’,or‘Pegasus’present(Kaplan1989b: 608–9). 6SeeKripke(1971,145;1980,102–3). 7 Kaplan (1973, 506–8) is appealing to what I call the inverseSinatra principle with respect to names from fiction: Suppose we start out by acknowledging that the Pegasusmyth is FICTION. Still it is, in a sense, possible.Shouldwenottake‘Pegasus’todenotewhatitdenotesinthe world of the myth? Wemustbe verycarefulnow.… Themythispossibleinthesensethatthereisapossibleworldinwhichitistruthfully told. Furthermore,therearesuchworldsinwhichthelanguage,withtheexceptionofthepropernamesin question,issemanticallyandsyntacticallyidenticalwithourown.Letuscallsuchpossibleworldsof themyth ‘M worlds’.Ineach Mworld,‘Pegasus’willhaveoriginatedinadubbingofawingedhorse. The Friend of Fiction, who would not have anyone believe the myth…, but yet talks of Pegasus, pretendstobeinan M worldandspeaksitslanguage . But beware the confusion of our language with theirs! If wisan M world, then their name ‘Pegasus’ will denote something with respect to w, and our description ‘the x such that x is called “Pegasus”’ will denote the same thing with respect to w, but our name ‘Pegasus’ will still denote nothing withrespectto w. Also,indifferent M worlds,differentpossibleindividuals may havebeen

5 moreinterestingisthat thepointholdsfor‘Vulcan’!Wecansaythefollowingaboutthis name,aswellasotherpropernames: if it cannot make it here, it cannot make it anywhere. If thenameisunanchoredhere(intheactualworld),itisunanchorable.Callthisthe inverse- Sinatra principle for proper names .8 Consideranotherhypotheticalindividual:Theia,featuredinthesocalledbigwhack (orgiantimpact)hypothesis,accordingtowhichtheMoonformedasaresultofacollision betweenEarthandtheMarssizedcelestialbodyTheia.Itisstillanopenquestionwhetherthe hypothesisiscorrect,andwhetherTheiaexisted.WedonotknowifTheiaexisted.Wedo knowthefollowingthough:‘Theia’isanameintroducedintoourlanguage;giventheopen issues,itiscurrentlyanunderwaypropername;evenifitreferstosomething,thatthingno longerexists;ifthebigwhackhypothesisisrefuted,thenbytheinverseSinatraprinciple,the namebecomesunanchorableanddoesnot refer inanypossibleworld(sharingthe fateof ‘Vulcan’);ifthehypothesisisconfirmed,then observed data, further findings may anchor ‘Theia’,inwhichcaseitwould,fromthenon,refertoamodallyrobustindividual(sharingthe fateof‘Neptune’);alternatively,thenamemightremainunderwayforever,inwhichcasethe propernamenevergetstorefertoamodallyrobustindividual. The last point—that ‘Theia’ does not call for reference to a modally robust individual—maywellseemlikeacontentiousone.Forsuppose100yearsfromnow,‘Theia’ getsanchored;cannotwethensaythatthroughoutthe21 st century,peoplehavebeenreferring to the individual Theia, using the name ‘Theia’? Here is a more cautious (and far less problematic)stancewecouldtakeinstead:priortotheanchoring,thenamedoesnot refer toa modallyrobustindividual,althoughitdoesdenoteit—justlikethedefinitedescription‘the bodywhosecollisionwithEarthcreatedtheMoon’would.Thisstancereliesonadifference thathassomeintuitiveappeal—betweenreferenceand.The underway statusof ‘Theia’ keeps it from referring to anything; but a definite description denotes whatever uniquelysatisfiesit,evenifweareforeverbarredfromfindingoutmoreaboutwhetherthe denotationexists,andifso,whatitis.9Denoting may be a coincidence, but reference is not.10 Those who are not prepared to accept this difference between denoting something and referencetoamodallyrobustindividual,canstillacceptthefollowing:givenhowweuseand interpretsentencesinvolvingthename‘Theia’,weareundernopressuretotake‘Theia’as referring to a modally robust individual, even if we think that names like ‘Neptune’, ‘Goldbach’,andotheranchoredpropernamesdorefertomodallyrobustindividuals. Theforeverunderwaystatusiswidelythoughtlikely for theproper name ‘Jack the Ripper’. 11 Giventhattheserialkillingshavebeenextensivelystudied,itseemsincreasingly dubbed‘Pegasus’;toputitanother way , our description ‘the x suchthat x iscalled “Pegasus”’ may denotedifferentpossibleindividuals withrespecttodifferent M worlds. Idonotobjecttotheinhabitantsofoneofthe Mworldsremarkingthattheirname‘Pegasus’ denotessomethingwithrespectto ourworldthatdoesnotexistsinourworld.ButIreservetherightto retortthat our name‘Pegasus’doesnotevendenotewithrespecttotheirworld. 8FrankSinatrasangaboutNewYorkCity:“IfIcanmakeitthere,I’llmakeitanywhere”. 9 This parallels Russell’s (1905) theory that definite descriptions are denoting or quantified expressions. His examplewas:‘thecenterofmassofthesolarsystematthefirstinstantofthetwentiethcentury’.Thedescription maywelldenoteapointthatsatisfiesthedescription,inaccordancewithRussell’stheory.Butmyclaimisthatif weintroduceanameforthispointbasedonthesamedescription,thenonlyafterthenameisanchoredwillwe beabletosaythat,thenamereferstoacertain,specifiedpoint. 10 KaplanquotesHarryDeutsch:“referenceisnocoincidence”(Kaplan1989b:608).Thiswassaidagainstthe ideathat‘Pegasus’refersinotherpossibleworlds.ButIthinktheremarkisevenmoreaptandilluminatingwith respecttonamesthatareintroducedwiththeintentiontorefertosomethingreal,exceptthatforonereasonor another,theyneverbecomeanchored—eitherbecausethereisnoobjecttoreferto(asisthecasewith‘Vulcan’), or because we are destined to have insufficient informationtoanchorthe name(asthecase mightbe with ‘Theia’). 11 Kripkediscussesthisexampleaswellasthatof‘Neptune’(1980,79,79n33).

6 unlikelythatwewouldcometopossessevidencethatwouldanchorthepropernametoa givenindividual,oralternativelydeemthenameunanchorable(because,say,wefindoutthat each of the murders that had been attributed to a single serial killer had a different perpetrator).Crucially, our expressions‘Theia’and‘JacktheRipper’,aslongastheyremain underway,areneitheranchorednoranchorablewithrespecttootherpossibleworldseither. Ournamesareintroducedintheactualworld,soitishere,andhereonly,thattheycanbe anchoredordeemedunanchorable;andtheirfateheredeterminestheirfateinotherpossible worlds—ascapturedbytheinverseSinatraprinciple. Foranunderwaypropername,theintroductionofthenameasafullfledgedproper nameisyettobecompleted,theanchoringismissing.Oncethemissingdetailisprovided— asthenamebecomesanchored—thenamedoesrefertoamodallyrobustindividual.Thiswas the case with ‘Neptune’, for example; typically, names are introduced in such a way (by ostension)thattheanchoringtocompletetheintroductionofthenameisnotdelayedtheway the anchoring of ‘Neptune’ was. It is unclear what we should say about the reference of underwaypropernamesthatareyettobecomeanchored;infact,thisisathornyquestion.The crucial point is that the claim about anchored proper names referring to modally robust individualsisindependentofwhatwedecidetosayaboutunderwaypropernames. Insum,itisanchored proper names (whether theybe anchored to a concrete or an abstract individual) that definitely refer to modally robust individuals; underway proper names(like‘JacktheRipper’)neednot,andunanchorablenames(like‘Vulcan’)donot. 3. Proper names in de re modal claims Mythesisthatlanguagetakesanchoredpropernamestorefertomodallyrobustindividuals doesnotimplythatbasedonlinguisticconsiderations,everyindividualwemighttalkabout and think wecanmakederemodalclaimsaboutismodallyrobust.Here,again,propernames as special de re vehicles are a source of guidance:oneindicationthatanindividualisnot modallyrobustisthatinonewayoranother,wearepreventedfromanchoring anyproper namewemightintroducefortheindividualinquestion.Thisis,inturn,asymptomthatsuch individualsarenotingeneralpropersubjectsfor de re modal claims (whose interpretation calls for modally robust individuals), even if they can feature in de dicto modal claims. Considerthedubbingofmerelypossibleindividualsontheonehand,andfutureindividuals ontheother.Adedictoclaimlike‘Possibly,Goldbachhadasister’mentionsacounterfactual sisterofGoldbach’s,wemighttrytogiveheraname:‘Ilke’.DavidKaplanconsideredthe dubbingofafutureindividual“inabsentia,asbysolemnlydeclaring‘Iherebydubthefirst child to be born in the twentysecond century ‘Newman 1’” (Kaplan 1969, 135). Our questionsare:canpropernamesbeintroducedintheseways,andifso,whatrequirementdo theyhavetomeetforreferringtomodallyrobustindividualsandfeaturinginderemodal claims? Drawingafourwaydistinctionwillhelpilluminatematters: (A) ascribing tosomeoneadere aboutanindividual, (B) makingadere assertion aboutanindividual, (C) using a common currency proper name tomakeadereassertionaboutanindividual, and (D) usingan anchored commoncurrencypropername tomakeadereassertionaboutan individual.

7 WhatIwanttosayaboutderemodalclaimshastodowith(C)and(D).Togetabettersense ofthem,IwillrelatethemtoNathanSalmon’s(2004)distinctionbetween(A)and(B);Ifind Salmon’ssuggestedcontrastplausible,butmypurposehereisnottoargueforit. About(A):Kaplan(1969,131–38)suggeststhathaving a de re belief about Goldbach imposesseveralrequirementsonthebeliever.First,herinternalvocabularymustincludea vivid name forGoldbach.“Thevividnames‘represent’thosepersonswhofillmajorrolesin that inner story which consists of all those sentences that [the believer in question] ”; 12 a contemporary mathematician might have a richer role for ‘Goldbach’ in her innerstory,butformanylaypeople,includingallreadersofthispaper,‘Goldbach’isvivid enoughtocountasavividname.Second,thenamemustbeaname of the mathematician Goldbach for the believer—“analogous to the sense in which a bad photograph may be a picture of anobjectthatitdoesnotresemble,andfailtobe a picture of another object to whichitbearsanuncannyresemblance”(Salmon2004, 247)). ‘Ilke’ and ‘Newman 1’ are plausibly nonvivid for English speakers, but independently of that, both founder on the second requirement: they are not names of anyone for any of us, contemporary English speakers. 13 As Kaplan (1969, 138) says: the range of individuals with whom we are en rapport is restricted, and it excludes Newman 1 as well as merely possible sisters of Goldbach. (B)standsinsharpcontrastwith(A).AsNathanSalmonputsit:“Sayingsomething about Newman 1 is a piece of cake. Forming a belief about him/her, by contrast, requires somedegreeofcognitiveconnection,howeversparing.Dereconnectednessisrequiredforde rebelief,notfordereassertion(2004,247).” 14 Heillustratesthecontrastasfollows: ItisindeeddubiousthatNewman1’sfuturecontemporariescouldtruthfullyutter‘Somephilosophers ofthelatetwentiethcenturybelievedthatyouwouldnotbebornuntilthetwentysecondcentury’.For despiteKaplan’sheroicefforts,wesimplyarenotsufficiently en rapport tohavederebeliefsabout Newman 1. The de re connection is lacking. By contrast, there is no reason why Newman 1’s contemporariescouldnottruthfullyutter‘Somephilosophersofthelatetwentiethcenturyhadaname foryou,andusingthatname,theysaidaboutyouthatyouwerenotknowablebythem(thatyouwould 12 Kaplan1969,136;emphasisinoriginal. 13 Kaplanlistsathirdcondition:thatthenameinquestionmust denote Goldbach(andnotsomeoneelse,say, Voltaire).WecansetthisconditionasidebecauseitisbasedontheFregeanRussellianidea—thereceivedview throughthe1960’s—thatpropernameshaveadescriptivecontentthatcompetentusersofthenameareawareof, andtheindividualdenotedbythenameistheonethatfitsthedescription,orfitstheclusterofdescriptionsthe best,orfitsthecoreofthecluster.Inthepassagesinquestion,Kaplan(1969)istryingtosynchronizehistorical origin (what Kaplan calls the name’s genetic character) with its descriptive content, so the name is of the individual denoted. It was not until 1970 that we find Kripke giving decisive arguments against Fregean Russelliantheoriesthatholdthatdescriptionsspeakersassociatewithapropernamedetermineitsreference.The criticism in a nutshell goes as follows. Euler was the first to formulate the socalled Goldbach’s (strong) conjecture(inreactiontoaletterinwhichGoldbachproposedarelated,weakerconjecture,whatisnowcalled Goldbach’sweakconjecture);andthedescriptionweassociatewith‘Goldbach’is“themanwhofirstformulated ‘Goldbach’s(strong)conjecture”.Butdescriptivefit is neither necessary for determining the reference of the name(eveninthelightofthislittleknownpieceofinformationaboutEuler,‘Goldbach’continuestodenote Goldbach),norisitsufficient(Eulersatisfiesthedescription,yet‘Goldbach’doesnotrefertohim).SeeKripke (1980,80–7);argumentsalongtheselinesprobablyappearedinearliertalksbyKripke,buttheearliestwritten versiondatesfrom1970. 14 Bycontrasting(A)and(B),Salmon(2004,247)reconcilesKaplan’scommentsonthename ‘Newman1’. Initially,Kaplanhadwantedtoblocktheintroductionofsuchnames(Kaplan1969,135),forhethoughtthat wouldenablespeakerstohavedere beliefs aboutNewman1,anundesirableoutcome.Kaplanchangedhisview lateron,suggestingthatthenamecouldbeintroducedafterall,andsubsequentlyusedtomake assertions about thefirstchildborninthe22 nd century(Kaplan1978,303;1989a560,n76). Lateron,Kaplantriedtosteermidwaybetweenthesetwoextremes(1989b:606);expressingtheneed forsomesortof“epistemicconnection”withthepersondubbed(ornamed),whichinthecaseof‘Newman1’, mightbesuppliedasthe22 nd centurycomesaround.Hisviewis,IthinkclosetowhatIdiscussunder(C)and (D),that‘Newman1’and‘Theia’presentlyhaveunderway,unanchoredstatus.

8 beborninthetwentysecondcentury,etc.)’.Theymightadd,‘ofcourse,theydidnotknow(oreven believe)thattheyweretalkingabout you —howcouldthey?—butyouweretheonetheyweretalking about.(2004,251) Indeed,alongtheselines,wecanimaginedere assertions involvingthename‘Theia’or‘Jack theRipper’,providedthatthenameswillsomedaybecomeanchored.Oncetheyare,English speakerswholivetowitnesstheanchoringwillbeinapositiontosay:whenpeoplelivingin the 20 th century were talking about a protoplanet named ‘Theia’ and an individual named ‘JacktheRipper’,itisthisprotoplanet,andthat individual they were making de re claims about.But‘Ilke’isstillproblematic;wesimplycannotspecifythingsfurther about Ilke .We couldenvisionvariousspecificallydescribedindividuals(identifyingactualeggspermpairs thatnevermetbutcouldhave,resultingindistinctbabygirlsthatwouldhavebeensistersof Goldbach),butnoamountofinformationaboutthesebabieswoulddecidewhichonewould havebeen Ilke. 15 Wecouldsay:(A)isaninternalaffair(internaltothebelieverinquestion);(B)isan external affair (potentially external to our contemporary language community); (C) is in between:itiswhatwemightcall public or community affairs .Letmeexplain,echoingDavid Kaplan’s Words (1990)aboutthecommoncurrencyconceptionofwords. Languageschangeconstantly,theEnglishlanguageisnoexception:  newwordsenterthevocabulary;oldwordsundergomeaningshifts(100yearsago,‘livid withanger’meant‘palewithanger’;nowitprimarilymeans‘furiouslyangry’);  wordsundergochangesinspellingandorpronunciation(‘Tiziano’turninginto‘Titian’);  sometimes several alternative spellings or pronunciations survive (we encounter the names ‘Occam’ and ‘Ockham’; we hear ‘Kant’ pronounced by Americans as the Brits wouldpronounce‘can’t’,andbyBritsastheAmericanswouldpronounce‘can’t’).Our linguistic community now has alternate spellings of the same word ‘Occam’ and ‘Ockham’.Arguably,‘CarolusLinnaeus’and‘CarlvonLinné’arevariantsofthesame word.  ThenameofthephilosopherNeilTennantiscertainlyadifferentwordthanthenameof the pop singer Neil Tennant (of Pet Shop Boys fame). These two qualitatively indistinguishableyetdistinctnameshavedifferenthistories(theyweregiventodifferent people),keptseparatewithinthelinguisticcommunity.Oneisaname of thephilosopher andispassedaroundassuch;theotherisaname of thepopsinger,andispassedaround assuch;thesamenessofsoundandspellingisnoobstacle, just as photographs of one armadillocanbekeptapartfromphotographs of another.16 Therearenamesthat“catchon”,becomeestablished—both‘NeilTennant’sarelikethis;as are the alternate forms of Ockham’s, von Linné’s and Titian’s names. They have become common currency words—whose identity lie in their “continuity, both interpersonal and intrapersonal” (1990, 117). 17 ‘Vulcan’, ‘Theia’, and ‘Jack the Ripper’ have been and will 15 ThisisKripke’smetaphysicalthesis(1980,156–7),whichKaplan(1989b:608–10)remarksisanappropriate argument with respect to names of merely possible entities: “the intended dubbee is insufficiently specific to selectauniqueindividual”(1989b:609).Seefootnote5above.Fornamesfromfiction,Kaplanthinkswedo muchbetterwithKripke’sepistemologicalthesis:theexistenceofanindividualwithallfeaturesofPegasusdoes notestablish(byitself,withoutanyhistoricalconnectionbetweenthefictionandindividual)thatitisPegasus (Kripke1980,157–8).MyargumentinSectionII.2.wasthatwithrespecttounanchorablenameslike‘Vulcan’ (andnotjustnamesoffictionalcharacters,themetaphysicalargumentdoesnotgettotheheartoftheproblem. SectionII.4takesupthisissue. 16 Evenifthetwoarmadillosaresiblings;andthatcanbetrickybecauseninebandedarmadillosalwaysgive birthtoidenticalquadruplets. 17 KaplanwritesaboutsomeBabylonianintroducinganameforHesperus/Venus:

9 continuetobecommoncurrencywords,independentlyofthefactthat‘Vulcan’turnedoutto beunanchorable,andwiththeothertwo,itisstillwideopenwhethertheywillturnouttobe anchored,unanchorable,orremainforeverunderwaypropernames. Crucially,themereactofintroducinganamedoesnotmakeitacommoncurrency name.18 Introducing anamelike‘Newman1’canbeaonemanshow(itwas),but turning it into a common currency word takes more. It seems to me that ‘Ilke’ cannot become a commoncurrencywordatall;dependingonourcommunalpurposes,‘Newman1’couldget provisionallyadmittedasanunderwaypropername.Oncefurtherinformationisobtained(as timedrawsnearertoNewman1’sbirth),theunderwaystatusmaychange. 19 Butthegeneral pointholds:creatinganewcommoncurrencywordtakescommunitycoordination,andthis process plausibly has a broad normalizing influence, curbing deviously coined names, or declaringthemasunderway,yettobeanchorednames—hence,commoncurrencynamesthat are unanchored (‘Newman 1’, ‘Theia’, ‘Jack the Ripper’) are atypical. 20 But the requisite circumstancesdohavetobequitespecial;ingeneral,theretendstobequitesomeresistance toadmittingnameslike‘Newman1’intothelanguage.Thisresultsinamorerobustsortofde Asitwentthroughdifferentcommunities,thewaythiswordwaspronouncedandwrittenchangedin verydramaticways,throughwhateverprocessesaccountfordialectalvariation.Theof theseprocessesofchangearetheprinciplesofcontinuityinaccordancewithwhichachangingword retains its identity. As we pass through various communities at various stages in our lives, we also changedramatically . (IthinkIamprobablymoredifferentnowfromthewayIwaswhenIwas,say, eightyearsold,thantheword‘Hesperus’isnowfromthewayitwaswhenitwas,say,fiveminutes old).(1990,101) Alongthesamelines,Kripke(1980,91–7)arguesthatthereferenceofapropernameisdeterminedbya chainofcommunicationleadingbacktoaninitialbaptism(whichKaplancallsdubbing),whentheindividualin question,thereferent,wasnamedordubbed.Asanamelike‘Neptune’wasadmittedasacommoncurrency word,speakersusedittorefertotheintendeddubbeenamedbymeansofthedescription‘theplanettoexplain suchandsuchperturbationsintheorbitofUranus’,evenbeforethenamebecomesanchored.Speakersdothisin virtueofachainofcommunicationlinkingtheiruseofthewordwiththedubbor’s.Thisissometimescalledthe new theory of reference, or the causalhistorical theoryofreference—attributedtoKripke,Kaplanas well as KeithDonnellan(1970).Itisworthnotingthatcallingita causal theoryismisleadinginthatacausalchainneed notleadbacktothereferent,onlytothe dubbing ofthereferent.Thedubboristypicallyincausalcontactwith thedubbee,butneednotalwaysbe:namesintroducedwithoutsuchcontactinclude‘Neptune’,‘JacktheRipper’, and, plausibly, names of abstract individuals (mathematical entities and perhaps even fictional entities, see footnote3above).SeeBurgess(2006)forinsightfuldiscussiononthisissueandrelatedones. 18 See Evans (1973, 279–80). Evans talks about an expression being a „name for a community”—this correspondstothenotionofacommoncurrencyword. 19 Kaplan(1989b)appearstofavorthissortofview,ashereviseshisviewsabout’Newman1’yetagain(see alsofootnote14): …allnames…howeverintroduced,carrytheirreferentasmeaningbutnotallnamescarry knowledge of theirreferent.Thosenamesthatwereproperlyintroduced,byostensionorbasedonsomeotherform of knowledge of the referent, carry and transmit the requisite epistemic connection. But in a tiny fractionofcases theconnectionisabsent—semantics(ormetasemantics)doesnotrequireit—andin thesecaseswehavedirectreference,andexpressibility,butnotapprehension.[Footnote:]A name may later take on the required epistemic connection when the referent appears upon the scene and is recognized as the named object .(1989b,606n98,emphasisadded). Thelastsentenceisaboutthesubsequentanchoringofanamethathadbeenanunderwaycommoncurrency name.‘Theia’andperhaps‘Newman1’maylatertakeontheepistemicconnectionthatwouldallowthemto become anchored. The crucial difference between Kaplan’s view and mine is that unlike me, he thinks the semantics of‘Newman1’doesnotrequirethatthenamebeanchored before itgetstorefertoanindividual;by contrast, I think such a requirement is in place. This means that even though anchoring and reference to a modallyrobustindividualgohandinhand,introducinganameandreferringtoamodallyrobustindividualneed not. 20 Kaplanmakesasimilarpoint,thoughheusesittoadifferentend:“Theintroductionofanewpropernameby meansofadubbingintermsofadescription…constituteaformofcognitiverestructuring;theybroadenour range of thought. To take such a step is an action normally notperformedatall,andrarely,ifevery, done capriciously”(1989a560,n76).

10 reconnectednessinvolvedin(C)—usingacommoncurrency name to make a de re claim aboutanindividual—thaninthe(B)typedereassertioncase(which,ifwebelieveSalmon, allows de re assertions about Newman 1). The difference consists in the community’s normalizinginfluence,whichtranslatesintoanimprovementon(A)and(B):accordingto(C) makingsenseofderemodalclaimsinvolvingcommoncurrencynamesrequiresinterpreting themaspurportingtorefertomodallyrobustindividuals. 21 Giventhatwecanreadilyinterpret such claims, common currency proper names must purport to refer to modally robust individuals.Wecansaythismuchwithoutworryingabout‘Newman1’,‘JacktheRipper’,or ‘Ilke’. ThecommoncurrencywordsofcontemporaryEnglisharethewordsweexpecttofind in an uptodate unabridged dictionary of the English language. With time, that dictionary becomesobsolete,asnewcommoncurrencywordsareintroducedandoldonesassumenew meanings.Somesortofcommunityconsensus(withweightgiventoexpertlyopinionfrom linguists,sociologists,scientists)driveswhatthenewadditionsandchangesaresupposedto be(recallthecaseof‘lividwithanger’).SoanEnglishdictionaryeffective now reflectsthe state of English now . By construing common currency words as dictionary entries, remarkablyhelpfulguidelinesemergeforwhataredistinctcommoncurrencywords,andwhat arevariantsofasingleword(theseareissueshavingtodowithwordindividuation,Kaplan 1989b:599,1990,94): Weexpectthefollowingfromourdictionaryentries:  thecurrententryunder‘livid’isdifferentthanitwas100yearsago;  under‘Kant’theBritishandAmericanpronunciationsarebothlistedfortheonecommon currencyword.  under‘Occam’, wefind‘Ockham’ asanalternativespellingofthesameword;andthe otherwayaround;  under‘Titian’,‘Tiziano’islistedasavariantofthesameword;andtheotherwayaround; thesamegoesforthepair‘CarolusLinnaeus’and‘CarlvonLinné’;  two‘NeilTennant’entriesarelisted,oneforthephilosopher,theother,forthepopsinger. Indeed, these expectations bear out. Moreover, the dictionaryentry analogy runs deep: our intuitionsaboutindividuatingcommoncurrencywordsareexactlytheintuitionsthatdrivethe structuringofdictionaryentries.Forexample,the common currency words ‘Hesperus’ and ‘Phosphorus’havedistinctoriginsthataredistinguishabletothisday(Venuspresentedasthe evening star, and Venus presented as the morning star, respectively). They are therefore distinct common currency words, not variants of the same word, or derived forms of one another or some third word.22 By contrast, we cannot say the same about ‘Tullius’ and ‘Cicero’,botheithervariantsorderivedformsofasingleword:‘MarcusTulliusCicero’;or about‘JohnF.Kennedy’,‘JackKennedy’,and‘JFK’,alleithervariantsorderivedformsofa singleword:‘JohnFitzgeraldKennedy’. Howdoes(D),aboutusing anchored commoncurrencynames,fitintothepicture? Whatdoesitaddto(C)?Salmon’spointthat22 nd centuryEnglishspeakersareinaposition tosaythatwe,20 th centuriansweremakingdereassertionsaboutNewman1goesbeyondthe language spoken by us now —because unlike the 22 nd centurians, we cannot now anchor ‘Newman1’(andweknowwecannot).Thispointstowardsalimitationin(C),tobehandled in(D).Commoncurrencywordsareobjectscreatedandmodifiedbylanguageusers—whose 21 Giventheassumptionwehavetaken—thatthenaturalreadingsinvolvemetaphysicalmodality—anyproper nameoccurrenceinamodalclaimpurportstobedere. 22 Iamrelyingontheintuitivedistinctionbetweenvariantsandderivedforms,leavingitopenthatitcanbemade (ifitcannot,thatjustmakesthingssimpler).

11 collective knowledge we might call community consensus opinion. In many ways then communityconsensusopinion(whichiswhatgetsreflectedintheunabridgeddictionaryof thelanguagespokenbythecommunity)isthedefinitiveauthorityonthecommoncurrency wordsofthecommunity—whatthosewordsare,andwhattheymean.Communityconsensus opinionisthereforeimmunetocertainsourcesoferroraboutitswords.(“‘Livid’hasalways meant‘pale’,buteverybodynowusesitimproperly,”aprescriptivistmightlament—buther stanceisabsurd;thewayeverybodyuses‘livid’insystematicallydifferentwaysthanbefore indicatesthatthewordnolongermeanswhatitusedto.Thesamepointcanbemadeabout changesinspellingandpronunciation.) Thereare,howevervarioussourcesoferrortowhichcommunityconsensusopinionis stillsusceptible—herearetwoexamples:(i)keepingtabsonwhenandwhetherapropername becomesanchoredand(ii)keepingtabsoninprogresschangesinmeaning.Aninstanceof (ii) is when it is recognizedin hindsight thatthe referent of a common currency name has changed over time, even though the intentions of speakers had been to preserve the old referent,tousethewordinaccordancewithitspreviouslyestablishedhistory;butsomething misfired.ThinkofGarethEvans’s(1973,276)example,thename‘Madagascar’,mistakenly believedbyMarcoPolotorefertotheislandinsteadofaportionoftheAfricancoast.There are two ways we might tell the story of what happened: the word ‘Madagascar’ was unwittingly reanchored from the coastal region to the island; alternatively, a new word ‘Madagascar’wasinadvertentlyintroducedandgotanchored,replacingtheoriginalwordthat hadbeenanchoredtothecoast.Oncethetransitionhastakenplace,eitherstorycouldclarify thechangeduseof‘Madagascar’. 23 Butitislikelythatasthetransitionisinprogress,itisnot part of the community consensus opinion that a once firmly anchored word is “losing its grip”.Thetransitionperiodword‘Madagascar’isappropriatelyregardedasunderwayrather thananchored(whetheritbeanewwordyettobeanchored,ortheoldwordwithitsanchor weighed, awaiting reanchoring), until its use is stabilized again; but the community’s consensusopinionwillnotconvergeonthisuntillater.(Thatishowthepreanchoredword ‘Neptune’was.)Duringthetransitionperiod,contrarytothecommunityconsensusopinion, thecommoncurrencyname‘Madagascar’needdoesnotfeatureinderemodalclaims. Inotherwords,theconsensusopinionispronetomakingthemistakeofcarryingon withtheassumptionthatanameisstillanchored, whenitfactitisnot.(i)givesrisetoa similarkindofmistake.Gobackto1878;thename‘Vulcan’hadbeenacommoncurrency wordforoveradecade;new,compellingobservationsthoughttobeofVulcancomeinfrom severalreliableastronomers;thereiscommunityconsensusthatthesightings have converged onasingleobject(ashadbeenthehappyoutcomewithNeptune),and‘Vulcan’isputdown asfinallyanchored,nolongerunderway.Again,itisonlyinhindsightthatthe20 th century linguistic community is in a position to discern that the sightings had been mistakenly attributedtoVulcan,andthenamewasnotanchoredafterall—itcouldnothavebeen,forit has since been found unanchorable. Again, the community consensus opinion notwithstanding,‘Vulcan’cannotandnevercouldfeatureinderemodalclaims. Insum,thecommunityconsensusopinionmayerrinregardingunderwaynamesas anchoredwordsofthelanguage.Thiscanleadtomistakes about which proper names can featureinderemodalclaims.Still,whatweneedtokeepinmindisthatthevastmajorityof thepropernamesweuseare indeed anchored.Thevicissitudesof‘Vulcan’,‘JacktheRipper’, and‘Madagascar’aretheexception.Therule:propernames—introducedforpeople,places, objects, events, numbers, and even fictional entities become anchored (typically upon introduction)andremainanchored.Itisthisvastarrayofunexceptionalpropernames—ones 23 The story can go either way; I lean towards the alternative that a new, distinct word, a new name was inadvertently introduced along the way; Kaplan’s (1990, 117–8) leanings are similar, but he thinks it is a substantivepointaboutwordsthatreferenceshiftsarealwaysaccompaniedbytheintroductionofanewword.

12 thatarenotmerely regarded as anchoredbutare indeed anchored,asspecifiedin(D)—that canfeatureinderemodalclaimslikethefollowing: (6) Goldbacheschewsmathematics Recallthatpropernamesprovidebutonewaytomakederemodalclaims.Thereare others;hereisonefrombefore: (3) ThediscovererofGCissuchthat he himself eschewsmathematics Theforegoingdiscussionisalsorelevanttosetting general conditionsformakingderemodal claims:agenuinederemodalclaimofthesortthatconcernsusisonethatsinglesoutan individualforwhomweareinapositiontohaveananchoredcommoncurrencypropername in our language. Paralleling the case of ‘Ilke’, ‘Newman 1’, and ‘Vulcan’ (names which wouldnotfitthebill)thefollowingwouldthusbeexcludedasdereclaims: (7) AmerelypossiblesisterofGoldbach’sissuchthat she herself discoversGC (8) Thefirstchildborninthe22 nd centuryissuchthat he/sheisbald (9) AmerelypossibleintraMercurialplanetissuchthat itstraysoffcourse Again,theintendedreadingsofpossibilityarestill counterfactual, not epistemic (the latter would be captured with the help of a prefix “for all we know, the soandso is such that possibly…”).Butthesereadingsseembogus;aseasyasithadbeentointerpretthelikesof (3),and(6),itdoesnotgiveusawaywith(7)–(9).Whatsister,child,planetaretheytalking about?Wearestalled—andthisveryfactindicateswehavegottentotheheartofthematter byfocusingonmodallyrobustindividuals.Whenavailable,modallyrobustindividualsmake interpretationstraightforward,whentheyarenot,wearestumped. 4. Times and worlds: presentism versus actualism Wherearewenow?Wehavemanagedtozoominontherelevantderemodalclaims—which include those with anchored proper names—whose interpretation calls for modally robust individuals. It is also overwhelmingly plausible, even platitudinous, that parallel considerations apply with respect to time. Thatis, these same de re modal claims call for temporally robust individuals 24 —individualsthatcansustaintemporalascriptionslike ‘was bornin1690’,‘wroteupaconjecturein1742’,‘neverprovedGoldbach’sconjecture’,or‘no longerexists’.GoldbachandAristotlearebothtemporallyrobustindividualsthatsustainsuch temporalpredications—thesepredicationsaretrueoftheformerindividual,butnotthelatter. Takingtheinterpretationofderemodalclaimsat face value makes two choices attractive: (i) assume modallytemporally robust individuals as basic units, and not as composites(assemblages)oftemporalandmodalstages(individualstages);(ii)assumethe standardquantificationalsemanticsoftenseandmodality andaccordingly quantifyoverall the modallytemporally robust individuals there are. (i) is about , (ii) is about ontology.Idothinktherearecompellingreasonstooptfor(i)and(ii),butitisimportantto keepinmindthatmythesisthatanchoredpropernamesrefertomodallyrobustindividualsis noncommittalineitherdirection.Instead,thethesissaysthatmodallyrobustindividualsare conceptually basic : the conceptually basic units of proper name reference. The temporal analogueofthethesisisthattemporallyrobustindividualsareconceptuallybasic,something

24 Kaplan(1973,503–4)thinksitwouldbebizarre not tothinkthatindividualsaretemporallyrobust.

13 quite plausible even if one does not believe that this thesis dictates the ontology or metaphysicsofindividuals. Evenso,itisinstructivetoconsidertheconsequencesofoptingfor(ii)—theyturnout to diverge for the temporal and modal cases. In the temporal case, we get a denial of presentism,theviewthatonlypresentexistentsexist, there are no merely past and merely futureexistents.25 TheproblemiswithmerelypastexistentslikeGoldbachandAristotle,both modally and temporally robust individuals. (‘Newman 1’, a name for a merely future individual,isnotanchored;sothereisnoneedtopositamodallyrobustindividualasits reference,aswehaveseeninSectionII.3.) The modal analogue of presentism is actualism, according to which only actual existentsexist,therearenomerelypossibleexistents. 26 Evenifweassume(ii),actualismis compatiblewiththethesisaboutmodallyrobustindividuals:Ihavegivenargumentsagainst treating ‘Ilke’ and ‘Vulcan’ as names that refer to modally robust individuals. In fact, the upshot has been that only anchored proper names refer to such individuals, and anchoring guaranteesthatwestaywithinanactualistuniverse. There is one further kind of merely possible individual that we have not yet mentioned—butthiskindtheactualistcanreadilyadmitinheruniverse.Imaginealecternkit thatnevergetsassembled.Wedecidetogivethename‘Woody’tothemerelypossiblelectern thatwouldhaveresultedfromassemblingthepartsbyfollowingtheinstructionsinthekit.It wouldseemunwarrantedtodenythepossibilityofdubbinganonexistentinthisway.27 To make things even smoother, let us imagine that no parts (not even screws) can be interchanged for others in assembling the lectern—each component has a unique intended spot,andWoodyisthelecternthatwouldresultfromplacingallpartswheretheybelong.Our questionsare:Does‘Woody’haveashotatbecomingananchoredcommoncurrencyname? CanwemakederemodalclaimsaboutWoody? Recall that the chief problem with ‘Ilke’ was the lack of specificity of the dubbed sister.WecouldspecifythingsaboutacounterfactualsisterofGoldbach’sthatwouldhave beenbornhadacertaineggandspermmet;buttherewouldbenowayoftellingthatthiswas Ilke(seefootnote5and15above).ThisproblemdoesnotariseforWoody:itissufficiently specificdespitethefactthatitisamerelypossibleexistent.Wecanthenmakederemodal claims as easily about Woody, as we can about Goldbach, and lecterns that are actually assembled. After all, Woody’s parts are all actual, and there is just one way they can fit togethertoyieldWoody.Thefurnitureoftheuniverse,asitactuallyis,containsallthereisto Woody, apart from the specific arrangement that would have brought Woody itself into existence.Thisisenoughto(i)specifyamodallyrobustindividualand(ii)anchorthename ‘Woody’. In addition, it is more thanwhatisneededforadmittingWoodyinanactualist universe. The actualist need only maintain that all of Woody’s parts are actual; and that argumentdoesnotevenrelyonthefullyspecifiedassemblyinstructionsonwhich(i)and(ii) cruciallydepend. Therequirementthatthedubbedmerelypossibleindividualbesufficientlyspecificis trickytokeeptrackof(callthisthespecificityrequirement).Hadtheinstructionsfailedto provideforauniquemodeofassemblingWoody’sparts(sosomemajorpartsofthelectern wereinterchangeable),wewouldbebacktowhere‘Ilke’hadfoundered.Hereiswhy.Ifour intuitionwerethatthevariousspecificmodesofassemblywouldyield distinct lecterns(just asaplatemoldedfromachunkofclaywouldhavebeenadistinctobjectfromavasemolded 25 SeeforexamplePrior(1970). 26 SeeforexampleAdams(1974),Fine(1977),andPlantinga(1976). 27 SeeKaplan(1989b:607–8;1973,517,n19).Also,Salmon(1981,39,n41)reportsKaplan’sandKripke’s willingness(inlecturesandconversation)toallowtheintroductionofthename‘Noman’toname“theperson who would have developedfromtheunionof this spermand that egg,hadtheybeenunited .”

14 from the same chunk), then we would have no way of deciding which of the variously assembled counterfactual lecterns is Woody. Things become even less transparent if we consider specifying merely possible organisms (is the dubbed merely possible person sufficientlyspecificifwepinpointthezygotefromwhichshemighthavebeenborn?Thisis verymuchanopenquestiongiventhatthezygotemightsplitintoseveralembryosthatcould developintodistinctidenticaltwins).Howdoweknowifwehavegivenenoughdetailsto meetthespecificityrequirement?Oftenwewillhavenoclearanswer,forfurtherdetailsabout biology and physics might alter our judgments concerning (i) when the individual is sufficientlyspecific(apertinentquestionmightbe:whenisahumanzygotepastthestageof splitting into several embryos?), and (ii) what is essential to being that lectern or that organism(isinitialmaterialconstitutionessentialtoalectern?Andishis/hersexessentialtoa person?).Still, if wefulfillthespecificityrequirement,theindividual is modallyrobust(anda nameforitcanbecomeanchored). Justhowtrickyitistodeterminewhatcountsassufficientlyspecificshouldmakeus appreciatethefactthatwithrespecttoindividualsthat actually existorexistedinthepast,the specificityrequirementisautomaticallyfulfilled:theactualorpastexistentistheretostandin withallitsspecificdetails,mostofwhichweneedknownothingaboutwhendubbingor making reference to the individual. Nameanchoring and reference to modally robust individuals that can thus “represent themselves” is not subject to the vicissitudes of the specificityrequirement. In sum, merely possible objects that are sufficiently specific are modally robust individuals—theycanbedubbed,andnamesforthemcanbecomeanchored.Bysatisfyingthe specificityrequirement,apropernameisguaranteedtorefertoanindividualthathasaplace in an actualist universe. It is therefore clear thatactualismremainsanavailableoption,no matter what metaphysical and ontological assumptions we might make in addition to the conceptualclaimthatpropernamesrefertomodallyrobustindividuals.Evenmoreimportant is the insight that with actual existents, the otherwise thorny specificity requirement is automaticallyfulfilled. 5. Possible worlds with modally robust individuals In the preceding sections I argued that the way we understand proper names featured in (counterfactual / metaphysical) modal claims tells us something important about their reference:thattheypurporttorefertomodallyrobustindividuals.Moreover,whenthenames areanchored,theyaretherebyguaranteedtorefertomodallyrobustindividuals.Itisinthe lightofthemetaphysicalconceptionofmodalitythatthiscrucialaspectofpropernamesis revealed. The link works the other way around as well: having revealed modally robust individualsasconceptuallyfundamental,thepictureof(metaphysically) possibleworldsis radically transformed—in the following way. Modally robust individuals are specified actuallyaswellascounterfactually;theyarethestartingpoints,thebuildingblocksforwhat wecancallmetaphysicallypossibleworlds.Thingsdonotworktheotherwayaround(ashad beenthoughtsincetheadventofmodallogic):namely,thattherearethepossibleworlds(or worldstates)andcertainbitsofthemarewhatmakeupindividualsacrossworlds.Inother words:itisbasedonourconceptionofindividualsthatapictureofmetaphysicallypossible worldsemerges;nottheotherwayaround.Thewaywe interpret certainparts of language revealsaconceptionofindividuals(asmodallyrobust);anditisbasedonthoseindividuals thatweconstruepossibleworlds. This isthe individual-driven picture . Throughout the paper, by ‘possible worlds’ I will mean metaphysically possible worlds.Whenitcomestothemetaphysicalconception,thejustmentionedrealization—that individualsarethebasisfordefiningpossibleworldsratherthanpossibleworldsbeingthe

15 basis for defining individuals across worlds—effectively excludes two forms of skepticism about de re modality .OneofthemisacombinationofwhatKitFine(2005b:30–9)calls:  metaphysical Haecceitism :theidentityofindividualsintheactualworldissimply given,andisnotinneedoffurtherexplanation(2005b:32);and  modal anti-Haecceitism : “possible worlds must ultimately be given in purely qualitativeterms”(2005b:31). Fine(2005b:35)continueswithaninsightfulillustrationofthecombinationinquestion: …ourmodalantiHaecceitistdoesnotregardhisindividualsashavingagenuinetransworldidentity. He takes the identity of individuals to be given and then thinks of the identificatory paths as mere artificialdevices,designedtosecureameaningforcrossworldattributions . It is not as if the objects had a modal underside, a fifth dimension, and that he was attempting to explain their identity in this dimension, just as other philosophers attempt to explain the identity of objects in space and time. Rather the objects come first, and the modal dimension is something tacked on later. Theidentificatorypaths thatemanatefromtheobjectarenotpartsoftheobject,sotospeak,butappendages… ThepointbecomesespeciallyvividifwecomparethemodalantiHaecceitistwithhisdoxastic counterpart. The doxastic antiHaecceitist … is certainly not going to suppose that individuals are extendedindoxasticspaceandthat,inconstructingidentificatorypathsacrossthedoxasticalternatives, heissomehowexplainingwhattheyare.(emphasisadded) Letusexaminethecombinationdescribedherebeforemovingontotheothercombination excludedbytheindividualdrivenpicture:atheorycombiningmetaphysicalandmodalanti Haecceitism. Along the lines quoted, we can bring out a crucial contrast between doxastic and metaphysicalmodalities.Thecombinationdescribedaboveturnsouttobeuntenable,because ofakeydifferencebetweendoxasticandmetaphysicalmodalities.Letusseehow.Wemay well opt for a combination of metaphysical Haecceitism and doxastic (or epistemic) anti Haecceitism. And this is reflected in the fact that interpreting belief and knowledge ascriptions involving proper names is problematic in ways in which interpreting (counterfactual)modalclaimsisnot.Contrast(10)and(11)with(12)and(13): (10) DOXASTICMODALITY a.Theactresswhoplayed Lois Lane 28 believes thatGoldbach’sbirthplaceis Königsberg. true b. The actress who played Lois Lane believes that Goldbach’s birthplace is Kaliningrad. false (11) EPISTEMICMODALITY a.Itis apriori thatKönigsbergisKönigsberg. true b.Itis apriori thatKaliningradisKönigsberg. false (12) METAPHYSICALMODALITY :POSSIBILITY ,bothtrue a.Itis metaphysically possible thatGoldbach’sbirthplaceisKönigsberg. b.Itis metaphysically possible thatGoldbach’sbirthplaceisKaliningrad. (13) METAPHYSICALMODALITY :NECESSITY ,bothfalse 28 Lois of ‘Lois and Clark: The New Adventures of Superman’ isplayedbyTeriHatcher,a math majorin college. Let us assume that she is therefore somewhat knowledgeable about the history of mathematics but ignorantaboutgeography:sheknowsthatGoldbachwasborninKönigsberg,butisunawarethatKönigsberg andKaliningradareoneandthesamecity.

16 a.Itis metaphysically necessary thatGoldbach’sbirthplaceisKönigsberg. b.Itis metaphysically necessary thatGoldbach’sbirthplaceisKaliningrad. Itisplausibletoassumethat(10)through(13)bearthetruthvalueslistedabove.Inthecase of(10)and(11),thetruthvaluesof(a)and(b)comeapart.Bycontrast,for(12)and(13),the truthvaluesof(a)and(b)donotcomeapart;whatismore,theycannot comeapart;itisinthe natureofmetaphysicalnecessitythattheycannot.Thisisneededifwewanttomaintain(asI do) that (12)–(13) are de re modal claims about Kaliningrad, a modally robust individual. (Goldbachislikewiseassumedtobemodallyrobust,buttheculprithereisthecityvariously knownas‘Königsberg’and‘Kaliningrad’.)Bycontrast,whenconsideringtheintuitive(non de re) readings in doxastic and epistemic contexts, we see the truth values diverging with respectto‘Kaliningrad’and‘Königsberg’in(10a)and(10b);andlikewisein(11a)and(11b). Thissymptomalonepreventsusfrominterpretingthesespecificreadingsof(10)and(11)as de re modal claims about the city. (10) and (11) thus fail to motivate the proposal that anchored proper names refer to doxastically or epistemically robust individuals; on the contrary,(10)and(11)are evidence against suchaproposal. Moreover,aproposalofdoxasticallyandepistemicallyrobustindividualsisgenuinely bizarre. We do think of the doxastic and the epistemic dimensions not as dimensions of individuals,butassomethingtackedonlater.Thisbringsoutjusthowinterestingitisthatthe situation is markedly different for metaphysical modality: inherent in our interpretive practicesistheassumptionthat the modal dimension is one of the dimensions of individuals in additiontotheirtemporal(andspatial)dimension;itisnotsomethingtackedonlater.Based on our ways of interpreting de re modal claims (with or without proper names), modally robustindividualsareconceptuallybasicunitsofreference. But does not this way of blocking modal antiHaecceitism rely on assuming metaphysicalHaecceitism?Itdoes.Thelatterviewisveryplausibleinitsownright.Forit seemsoverwhelmingly naturaltotakeindividualsto be temporally robust , as described in SectionII.4,Goldbach(thetemporallyrobustindividual)istheonebornin1690,writingupa conjecturein1742,neverprovingGoldbach’sconjecture.Whenourtalkofsuchtemporally robustindividualsistakenatfacevalue,wegetmetaphysicalHaecceitism. Whenmodaltalkisnottakenatfacevalue,westillneedtoaccountforthefactthat modallyrobustindividualsareconceptuallybasic.Thisissomethingthatwouldhavetobe accounted for, even by a metaphysical anti-Haecceitist , who holds that “the identity of individuals—or,atleast,ofcertainindividuals—istobeexplainedintermsoftheirpurely qualitativefeaturesorintermsoftheirqualitative relationships to other individuals” (Fine 2005b:31).Butitisherethatthetaskthatthe metaphysical antiHaecceitistisupagainstis manageable, and markedly unlike the daunting task that the modal antiHaecceitist is up against.Theformercanrelyontheindependentavailabilityoftemporalstagesforindividuals (timeslices,nonmodallyspecified),andbyclaimingthemtobebasic,constructtemporally robustindividuals(theconceptualunitsneededforpropernamereference)intermsofthem. The proposal might be: the nonmodally specified individual stages form a supervenience baseonwhich“our”conceptuallybasicindividuals supervene. There is nothing farfetched aboutappealtothesebasicunits.Bycontrast,aparallelmoveforthe modal antiHaecceitist involvesfarfetchedbasicunits:forshewouldhavetotakefor granted certain featuresthat formasuperveniencebasisonwhichtheconceptuallyrequiredmodallyrobustindividualsare supposedtosupervene.Buttheelementsofthislattersuperveniencebase(unlikemomentsof timeandstagesofindividuals)arenotonesthatwecanplausiblytakeforgrantedorconsider available. They are, after all, qualitative descriptions of (metaphysically) possible worlds! Surely our handle on, access to, and grasp of modally robust individuals (supposedly supervenient) is far more immediate and unproblematicthanourhandleon,accessto,and

17 graspofqualitativedescriptionsofpossibleworlds(supposedlyprovidingthesupervenience base). Thisobjectionpointstowhatwe aremissingouton when we assume (along with DavidLewis1968,1986)thecombinationofmetaphysicalandmodalantiHaecceitism:that individualsareinneedofnofurtherexplanationoncewerecognizewhatderemodalclaims aresupposedtomean.Tokeepthisinperspective,weneedtoremindourselvesthatthingsdo not always resolve themselves automatically like that—recall the intractable specification requirementassociatedwithamerelypossibleindividuallikeWoody,andtheinterpretative obstacleassociatedwithdoxasticandepistemicmodalities(in10and11).Wewillseemore ofthelattersortofproblemwithconceptionsofnecessityotherthanthemetaphysicalonein III.1. Theforegoingmightpromptsomeonetoask:whynotconstruetheindividualdriven picture as the denial of modal antiHaecceitism? The individualdriven picture would then amount to modal Haecceitism—according to which possible worlds and the crossworld identitiesofindividualsaresimplygiven.Thislatterviewcapturesthemodalrobustnessof individuals—that the subjects of de re modal claims are crossworld individuals. But the individualdrivenpicturemakesafurthercommitment:notonlydoesittakemodallyrobust individualsasbasic,butitalsotakespossibleworldstobenonbasic,construingtheworldsin terms of the individuals. The ease with which we conceive of counterfactual scenarios and interpret claims about counterfactual situations is explained in two steps: first certain expressions of our language purport to refer to modally robust individuals; second, and implicitinourunderstandingofsuchindividualsisanunderstandingofhowtheseindividuals mighthavebeenotherwise—anunderstandingofpossibleworldsapartfromtheactualone.It isthesecondstepthatremainsunappreciated. In sum, with modally robust individuals on board as conceptually basic, two innovations follow: first, modal antiHaecceitism becomes a nonstarter; second, a new, individualdrivenpictureofpossibleworldsemerges.Thatpicturehasit that possible worlds are alternative ways modally robust individuals are.Itisnotthatmodallyrobustindividuals areindividualswhosefatesvaryfromonepossibleworldtothenext.Ourstartingpointisthe modally robust individual, a conceptually basic unit that provides us an easy way of conceivingofwhatpossibleworldsare.Wegettheindividualsfirstandtherebythepossible worlds;nottheotherwayaround. III.MODALITY ,POSSIBLE WORLDS ,AND INDIVIDUALS:VARIOUS CONCEPTIONS The individualdriven picture takes on board a specific conception of individuals and a specificconceptionofmodality.Individualsaremodallyrobust—deremodalclaimsinform us that proper names purport to refer to such individuals. This gives us more than the metaphysical conception of modality; we also get to construe possible worlds as ways modally robust individuals might have been. The individualdriven picture concerns a conceptualpoint:whatisreflectedinour ways of understanding of language about which notionsareconceptuallybasic(modallyrobustindividuals),andwhichonesarenot(possible worlds). The significance of this new picture can be better appreciated in the light of the distancewehavehadtocovertogethere.Previousworkinlogicandphilosophyhasbeen dominatedbyradicallydifferentoutlooksonconceptionsofmodality,possibleworlds,and individuals.WithC.I.Lewis’ssystemofmodallogic(1918) 29 beganahalfcenturylongera 29 It was not until later—Lewis and Langford (1932)—that (logical) necessity and possibility were treated as sentenceoperators.Thusbeganthecareerof and .

18 ofnecessityunderstoodaslogical(andanalytic)necessity.ItwasthisconceptionthatW.V. Quineattackedfromthe1940’sonward(Section1):hearguedthatitsderemodalclaims were unintelligible. Quine’s criticism has shaped expectations and qualms about other conceptionsofmodalityaswell—doxastic,epistemic,andphysicalconceptions.Inparticular, foreachstripeofmodality,anaccountwasneededforhow(ifatall)itsderemodalclaims were rendered intelligible. It was increasingly recognized that scientific claims call for necessityunderstoodnotaslogicaloranalyticnecessity,butasphysicalnecessity(aprecursor tometaphysicalmodality).Buttheattendantconceptionofpossibleworldsandindividuals confrontedphilosopherswiththearduoustaskofsettingcriteriatoidentifyindividualsacross possibleworlds(Section2).Transworldidentitywasanissueinthecontextofderemodal claims,butnotdedictoones,contributingtothenotoriousreputationoftheformer. Withsuchpreliminaries,SaulKripke’s1970proposal about rigid designation—laid outinSection3—wasrevolutionaryindeed.Hedrewattentiontothemetaphysicalconception of modality and distinguished it from others. In addition, he came extremely close to recognizing that proper names refer to modally robust individuals, though certain details about nonexistence—what, if anything does the name ‘Nixon’ refer to in a Nixonless world?—steered him offcourse. Still, he realized that on an overwhelmingly natural interpretationofmodaltalk,transworldidentityisanonissue:onanalternativeconceptionof possibleworldsandindividuals,transworldidentityis given ,innoneedofexplanation. In the wake of Kripke’s arguments, David Kaplan put forth a similar idea: proper names are directly referential (Section 4). He criticized Kripke for going offcourse on the nonexistence issue—which was exactly what had kept Kripke from making the point that proper names purport to refer to modally robust individuals. Meanwhile, Kaplan construed directreferenceintermsofstructuredpropositions:directlyreferentialexpressionscontribute their referent to propositional content—what is expressed on a certain occasion by the utteranceofadeclarativesentence.Yetagain,withtalkofpropositions,thepointthatthese referents were modally robust individuals, became blurred. And subsequently, this point disappearedaltogetherinMillianism—aviewinspiredbydirectreferencetheory—according to which the sole semantic contribution of a proper name is its referent (Section 5). It is thereforeatimelyendeavortoregainthelostpoint,clarifyit,andinaddition,recognizethat modallyrobustindividualsprovideabasisforconstruingpossibleworlds—inall,discoverthe individualdrivenpicture. 1. Analytic modality and Quine’s critique ForQuine,theinterpretivetaskwasverydifferent:necessity(andpossibility)werenotabout counterfactualscenarios,butaboutconstraintsinducedbylogicandbymeaning—logicaland analyticnecessity(andpossibility).30 Theanalyticconceptioncanbedefinedasfollows:  pistruejustincasethemeaningsoftheexpressions in pguarantee that p is true;and  pistruejustincasethemeaningsoftheexpressionsin pleave open that pis true. OnQuine’sanalyticconstrual,bothofthefollowingaretrue: (14) Kaliningrad=Kaliningrad (15)~ Kaliningrad=Königsberg,equivalently, Kaliningrad≠Königsberg

30 SeeespeciallyQuine’searlypapers(1943)and(1947).

19 ‘Kaliningrad=Kaliningrad’istrueinvirtueofmeaningalone,hence(7).But‘Kaliningrad= Königsberg’,thoughtrue,isnotverifiedbythemeaningsoftheexpressionsinvolved,hence (8).TodiscernthatKaliningradisKönigsberg,wecannotjustcheckmeanings;weneedto checktheworld. IntroducingquantifiersintomodallogicworriedQuine.Hedidnotthinkcasessimilar to the de dicto modal claim (1)—involving a quantificational treatment of the definite description‘thediscovererofGC’alongthelinesofRussell’stheoryofdescriptions—meant troublethough. (1') ∃!x(GCdiscoverer(x)&woman(x)) ‘Itis(analytically)possiblethatexactlyonepersondiscoveredGCandsheisa woman’ 31 (1')isreadilyinterpreted:itconcernsmeaninginducedconstraints,whethersuchconstraints leaveopenthatthediscovereroftheconjecturebeawoman.Theydo.So(1')isnaturallyread astrue.Here,‘ ’attachestoaclosedformula,oneinwhichalloccurrencesofvariableshave alreadybeenboundbya. Quineworriedaboutthefollowingsortsofderemodalclaimsthough: (16) Kaliningradissuchthat it isnecessarilyidenticalwithKaliningrad. ∃x(x=Kaliningrad& Kaliningrad=x) (17) Somethingissuchthat it isnecessarilyidenticalwithKaliningrad. ∃x Kaliningrad=x (18) Königsbergissuchthat it ispossiblydistinctfromKaliningrad. ∃x(x=Königsberg&~ Kaliningrad=x) (19) Somethingissuchthat it ispossiblydistinctfromKaliningrad. ∃x~ Kaliningrad=x Quine thought (16) through (19) were unintelligible: what does it mean for it to be analytically necessary for an object ,anindividual,tobeidenticaltoKaliningrad?(16)–(19) posethisinterpretivechallenge.Analyticnecessityisabouttruthinvirtueofmeaningalone; Andhowwespecifytheindividualinquestion—thecityofKaliningrad—affectswhetherthe resultisorisnotanalyticallynecessary.Specifyitas‘Kaliningrad’,andyouget‘Kaliningrad =Kaliningrad’,whichisanalyticallynecessary.Butspecifyitas‘Königsberg’,andyouget ‘Kaliningrad=Königsberg’whichisnotanalyticallynecessary.Quine’sdiagnosis:wecannot ascribeanalyticproperties(like‘beingnecessarilyidenticalwithKaliningrad’)toindividuals directly;onlytoindividualsunderacertainspecification. 32 Quine’sinitial(1943)lineagainstquantifiedmodallogicissimilar;bydoingnomore thanchangingtheexamplesandnumbering,wegetthefollowing:

31 ∃!x(GCdiscoverer(x)&woman(x))abbreviates ∃x(∀y(GCdiscoverer(y) y=x)&woman(x)). 32 Noticetheparallelwithdoxasticandepistemicmodality,in(10)and(11),discussedinSectionII.5above. There, following Fine (2005b), I emphasized how bizarre it was to think that individuals had a doxastic or epistemicdimension.Instead,bothareplausiblytackedonlater.Here,itislikewisebizarretothink individuals haveananalyticdimension.Bycontrast,itisexceedinglyplausibletothinkthatindividualshaveatemporaland amodaldimension;itisthisthattheindividualdrivenpictureaimstocapture.

20 “‘There is something which is necessarily identical to Kaliningrad’ is meaningless. For, would Kaliningrad,thatis,KönigsbergbeoneofthecitiesnecessarilyidenticaltoKaliningrad?Butsuchan affirmation wouldbeatoncetrueinthe formof(14)andfalseintheform negatedin(23).…This resistancetoquantification,observedinrelationtothecontext‘necessarily…’,isencounteredequallyin connectionwiththederivativecontexts‘possibly…’etc.”(1943,124). Casesofquantifyingin—withoutsidequantifiersvariables“trapped”insidethe of modal operators—require us to ascribe modal properties (being analytically identical to Kaliningrad)toindividualsdirectly.Thisisanalyticnecessitydere.33 Recallthewaywehad drawnthedere–dedictodistinctioninSectionII:theformerbutnotthelatterpresupposesthe intelligibilityofascribingmodalpropertiesdirectlytoindividuals.Basedonthis,(1')counts asdedicto.Butsodo(14)and(15),themetaphysicalnecessitysiblingsofwhichwouldhave beendere(like6)—aboutthecityvariouslyknownasKaliningradandKönigsberg.Neither (14) nor (15) imposes the intelligibility requirement; after all, they merely amount to: “‘KaliningradisKaliningrad’isanalytic”;“‘KaliningradisKönigsberg’isnotanalytic”.For analyticnecessity,propernamesdonotposeaspecialinterpretiveproblem.34 Quine’scharge arisesspecificallyincasesofquantifyingin,asin(16)–(19):the xs(correspondingto‘it’)are boundfromtheoutside.Thismeansthatineachcase, there comes a point when the open formula‘ Kaliningrad=x’hastobeinterpreted,andthisQuinetakestobeproblematic. QUINE ’SUNINTELLIGIBILITYCHARGE Wecannotinterpret,makesenseoftheopenformula Kaliningrad=x,giventhatthe followingaretrue:  Kaliningrad=Königsberg  Kaliningrad=Kaliningrad  ~ Kaliningrad=Königsberg Theupshothasbeen:giventheanalyticconceptionofmodalityassumedbyQuine, quantification in de dicto (1')—with the modal operator attaching to a closed formula—is readilyinterpreted.Butderemodalclaimsinvolvingquantifyingin—suchas(16)–(19),with the modal operator attaching to an open formula—are unruly, bringing on Quine’s unintelligibility charge. Thus began de re notoriety—with a problem specific to analytic modality. 2. Transworld identity As early as 1943, Quine was noting that he was concerned about the socalled strict modalities:analyticandlogicalnecessity.Herecognized,however,thattherewasa practical needtoclarifyotherconceptionsofnecessitythatwouldmakequantifyinginintelligible:

33 Thisisthesyntacticdere.Seefootnote2. 34 Infact,propernamescircumventanissuerelatedtodefinitedescriptionsthatisirrelevanttoQuine’schargeof unintelligibility, and has sidetracked responses. When the intelligibility charge was formulated with definite descriptions(‘9=thenumberofplanets’;seeQuine1947,123–4),oneinfluentialresponse—firstsuggestedby Smullyan (1947)—was that such phenomena with definite descriptions can be handled if we treat definite descriptionsasRussellianquantifiedexpressions(seefootnote9above).Furtherconfusionresultedfromthefact that in 1943, Quine was focusing on deducing (16) from (14) by existential generalization. That Quine was raisinganinterpretiveissuebecomesclearerinhis1947followup(1947,46).Twoilluminatingcommentaries onthehistoryofthedebatebetweenQuineandhiscontemporariesstandout(Burgess1998,andNeale2000), alongwithKaplan(1986)andFine(1989,1990),bothofwhomlayouttheinterpretivechargewithgreatclarity andsuggestwaystoresolveitforanalyticandlogicalnecessity.

21 In discussions of physics, naturally, we need quantifications containing the clause ‘ x is soluble in water’, or the equivalent in words; but… we should then have to admit within quantifications the expression … ‘necessarily if x is in water then x dissolves’. Yet we do not know whether there is a suitablesenseof“necessity”thatadmitspronounsreferringthustoexteriorquantifiers[thatis,whether wecanhaveaconceptionofnecessitythatallowsquantifyingin](1947,124). Weneedtoenvisionawaterdeprivedobjectinacounterfactualsituationinwhich it isplaced inwater(anddissolves).35 Howarewetotrackthisobjectfromthewaterfreesituationtothe wateryone?Thisisthethornyissueofthetransworldidentityofindividuals. Noticethatdedictoclaimslike(1)areeasy: (1) thediscovererofGCisawoman The counterfactual situation in question is described in general terms, so the issue of identifying the counterfactual woman in question with anyone in the actual world or in another counterfactual situation does not even arise. The need to specify criteria for the transworldidentityofindividualsarisesspecificallyinconnectionwithderemodalclaims. But now that we are again considering counterfactual modal claims rather than analytic necessity,propernamesbecomederevehiclesagain,raisingthetransworldidentityissue(see footnote2): (6) Goldbacheschewsmathematics How is the counterfactual man (whobecomes a doctor, say) related to our mathematician Goldbach? Transworldidentityisnotaproblemontheindividualdriven picture, which posits modally robust individuals and takes possible worlds to be defined in terms of such individuals. But not until Kripke’s Naming and Necessity did philosophers begin thinking alongthelinesofthefirsthalf,whereasthesecondhalfremainslargelyunappreciatedtothis day.TwoearlypassagesfromKaplan—bothfromthelatesixties—illustratethepreKripkean wayofthinkingaboutpossibleworlds: Numerals are reliable; they always pick out the samenumber.Buttosupposeastandardname36 for Quinewouldpresupposeasolutiontothemorepuzzlingproblemofwhatfeaturestotakeintoaccount indeterminingthatanindividualofonepossibleworldis‘thesameperson’asthatofanother.Often when the worlds have a common part, as when we consider alternative futures to the present, the 35 WeshouldpauseforamomenttonoticethatthisapproachisastraightforwardextensionofQuine’spoint raisedinthecontextoftheunintelligibilitychargeintheprevioussection:“whatisthis object thatisnecessarily suchthat…”;butthesuggestionthatwelocatethatveryobjectinacounterfactualsituationalreadygivesupon modalantiHaecceitism.SeeSectionII.5above. 36 Kaplanthoughtnumberscanbegivenstandardnames—thenumerals—intermsofwhichquantifyingincould then be interpreted. The proposal: only the standard names could be considered substitution instances for variablesincertainmodalcontexts—specifically,analytic,anddoxastic—wherethemodaloperatorattachesto anopenformula.Forpropernamesofindividualslikepeopleandobjects,Kaplanconsideredbeliefascriptions only;hissolutionthereinvolvesvividnames—discussedinSectionII.3above. Incidentally,RuthBarcanMarcus’s(1961)proposalthatpropernamesaremeretagsconstruespropernameson themodelofstandardnameslikethenumeralsfornumbers.ThishasacontentiousconsequenceQuineexplicitly (1943,1947,1962)rejects:coreferringpropernames like ‘Kaliningrad’ and ‘Königsberg’ are synonymous (if they are in fact genuine proper names). Without motivatingthisoutcomeinanyway,Marcus(1961)simply acceptsit(asdidSmullyan1947andFitch1949beforeher).Fordiscussion,seeNeale(2000),especiallyPartII, Section20.Bytalkingaboutnamesastags,MarcusissimplyrepeatingRussell’s(1918)claimthatgenuine(or logicallyproper)names—whatMarcuscallspropernames,which“simplytag”andhave“nomeaning”—give risetoidentitystatementswhich,iftrue,“mustbetautologicallytrueoranalyticallytrue”(Marcus1961,11–2, 13).Inotherwords,therearenoinformativeidentitystatementsinvolving genuine names.

22 individuals(s) can be traced back to the common part by the usual continuity conditions and there compared.Butforindividualsnotextantduringanoverlapsuchtechniquesareunavailing.Itseemsthat suchradicallydisjointworldsaresometimescontemplatedbymodallogicians. 37 Iamnotherepassing final judgment but only remarking the relevance of a second difference between Quine and Nine: namely,thathepresentsaveryrealproblemoftransworld identification while it does not. (Kaplan 1969,130–1). Implicit in this passage is the following: tracking individuals through time is manageable, becausewecanrelyoncontinuityovertime.ThismaywellbebehindKaplan’sthinking— apparentinanotherpaperhewroteinthelatesixties—thattemporallyrobustindividualsare basic(morebasicthantemporalstagesofindividuals),butmodallyrobustindividualsarenot (becauseindividualsspecifictoaworldarethemorebasicunits): “Ifindonintrospectionthatinmostcases(thoughnotall) it is the superentity that I think of as basic when considering temporal stages… (and similarly for spatial stages), and the slices, the entities specific to a stage, that I think of as somehow artificial . But when I think about different possible worlds proper (i.e., what might be but is not), the entities specific to a stage seem to be basic and naturally determined and the superentities (the transworld heir lines as I earlier called them) seem to me somehow artificial and determined only relative to certain interests. And I am not sure that further considerationoftheseintuitionswouldnotleadtothediscoveryofalogicaldifferencebetweenthetwo kindsofframeofreference.(Kaplan1979,104;emphasisadded). We will soon see that by the early 1970’s, Kaplan no longer thinks that transworld identification is a problem and that individuals across worlds (what he calls superentities above and I call modally robust individuals) are less basic than worldspecific stages of individuals. Taking stock: difficulties with identifying individuals across worlds provided yet anotherreasontoregarddedictomodalclaimsasharmless,anddereonesastricky.These considerations are very different from Quine’s though: we are no longer dealing with the analytic conception of necessity; and the issue is not that de re modal claims are unintelligible;onthecontrary,they seem intelligible;butinterpretingthemembroilsusinthe difficulttaskofspecifyingtransworldidentificationcriteria. 3. Rigid designation Saul Kripke revealed three key insights about the interaction between proper names and modality.First,heclarifiedthemetaphysicalconceptionofmodality(concerningwaysthings canormust be ),sharplydistinguishingitfromepistemicnotionslikeaprioriandaposteriori (concerningwaysthingscanormustbe known ).Second,hearguedthatwiththisconception, transworldidentityisnotaproblem.Third,heexplainedthatwehavea“directintuition”,or an “intuitive idea” 38 that proper names are rigid designators. He also offered a battery of argumentsandtestsforthethesisthatpropernamesarerigiddesignators,buttheappealto directintuitionswasthemostcompellingdetailintheargumentforrigiddesignation(though itdidnotturnouttobethemostinfluentialone).39 Iwillsummarizethesethreepointsinturn. Kripkefamouslyarguedthatbeingnecessaryandbeingaprioricancomeapart(ascan being contingent and being aposteriori). Examples of the necessary aposteriori include: (i) 37 Forexample,wemightneedtoconsiderasituationinwhichQuineisbornadayearlierandnothinggoes exactlythesamefromthenon.ThisisacounterfactualsituationinvolvingQuinewithnoperfectoverlapwith theactualcourseofQuine’slife. 38 Emphasizedinthe Preface subsequentlyadded(Kripke1980,4,5,14),andtoalesserextent,earlieraswell (1980,48–9). 39 ItwasovereightyearsagothatDavidBarnetthadtriedtoconvincemeofthis—andIdidnotgetwhathewas afterbackthen.SeealsoBurgess(2006,Section7).

23 identitystatementswithpropernames—‘KaliningradisKönigsberg’;and(ii)claimsaboutthe essencesofindividuals—‘Goldbachishuman’.Thefollowingissupposedtoholdforeach typeofclaim:giventhattheclaimistrue,itcouldnothavebeenotherwise,andistherefore necessary;butwecannotknowthattheclaimistrueindependentlyofexperience,andsoitis aposteriori. A great deal of emphasis was placed on the necessary aposteriori in Kripke’s lecturesaswellasinsubsequentworkbyothers.40 Itiswelltonote,however,thatthedistinctionbetween metaphysical necessity and epistemic notions does not require appeal to claims that are at once necessary and a posteriori .Alesserresultwillsuffice:ontheonehand,appealtoaposterioriclaimsforwhich itis open whethertheyarenecessaryorcontingent;ontheotherhand,appealtonecessary claimsforwhichitis open whethertheyareapriorioraposteriori.Fortheformer,(ii)type claimswilldo:weneednotappealtoessencesinany waytopointoutthat‘Goldbachis human’isaposteriori,yetitisopenissuewhether it is necessary. 41 For the latter, Kripke givestheexampleofGoldbach’sconjecture,forwhichnoproofexistsyet,anditisunclearif aproofcanbehad.Thismeansthatthefollowingiswideopen(1980,36–7;1971,150–1): (20)ItisapriorithatGoldbach’sconjectureistrue,oritisapriorithattheconjecture isfalse. Yetwedoknownow,withoutanyprospectforobtainingaproof,thatthefollowingholds— giventhatmathematicaltruthsarenecessarilytrueandmathematicalfalsehoods,necessarily false: (21) It is necessary that Goldbach’s conjecture is true, or it is necessary that the conjectureisfalse. Unlikemanycommentators,Kripkedidnotlosesightofthelesserresultaboutwhatis openandwhatisnot:42

40 Notonlyisthenecessaryaposterioriacentralthemein Naming and Necessity (1980,97–134),itisalso the definingthemeinKripke’s Identity and Necessity lecturedeliveredlessthanamonthlater(1971,135–44,151– 61).(Incidentally,inthatlecture,whatIcallthethreeinsightsfromKripkearepresentedinreverseorder.)The necessaryaposteriorihassetthebasisforthevast,rapidlygrowingliteratureontwodimensionalsemantics(for example,Chalmers1997). The necessary aposteriori is also central elsewhere, I will mention two notable examples. First, see Scott Soames’sextensive workintendedtodeveloptheunfinishedagendaof Naming and Necessity (seeespecially Soames(2002)andSoames(forthcoming),wherehearguesthatKripke’sclassificationwasrightabout(ii)but notabout(i)).Second,seeNathanSalmon’s(1981)influentialbookshowingthat(ii)typeclaims,whichamount to essentialism, rely on essentialist premises in addition to Kripke’s theory of names. Kripke never claimed essentialismcouldbederivedfromhistheoryofreference,butothersthoughtitcouldbe(Kripke1980,1,n2).In fact,Kripke’sstrategywastobringinexamplesaboutessencesforthepurposeofillustratinghowthenecessary and the apriori may come apart. (The next two footnotes are relevant to this point of Kripke’s and misunderstandingsabouthisview.) 41 “One might very well discover essence empirically,” he says (1980, 110). There is a caveat: the example worksaslongaswethink,asKripkedoes,thattherecanbenecessarystatementsinvolvingcontingentlyexisting individuals.Wewilltakeupthispointshortlyinthediscussionofrigiddesignation. 42 TwofurtherpassagesfromKripke:“Themainpointisthatitisnottrivialthatjustbecause…astatementis necessaryitcanbeknownapriori.…Andsothisshowsthatevenifeverythingnecessaryisaprioriinsome sense,itshouldnotbetakenasatrivialmatterofdefinition”(Kripke1971,151).“Atanyrate,andthisisthe importantthing,thequestionisnottrivial;eventhoughsomeonesaidthatit’snecessary,iftrueatall,thatevery evennumberisthesumoftwoprimes,itdoesn’tfollowthatanyoneknowsanythingaprioriaboutit”(Kripke 1980, 37). See also Kripke (1980, 39, n11; 110–5). Had commentators not lost sight of the lesser result, Salmon’s(1981)bookwouldnothavebeenneededtostraightenthingsout(seefootnote40above).

24 Moreimportantthananyparticularexampleofsomethingwhichisallegedtobenecessaryandnot a priori or a priori andnotnecessary,istoseethatthenotionsaredifferent,thatit’snottrivialtoargue onthebasisofsomething’sbeingsomethingwhichmaybewecanonlyknow a posteriori ,thatit’snota necessarytruth.It’snottrivial,justbecausesomethingisknowninsomesense a priori ,thatwhatis knownisanecessarytruth.(1980,39) Withthemetaphysicalconceptionofmodalitythusclarified,theroadwaspavedfor construingpossibleworldsascounterfactualsituations,aswaystheworldmighthavebeen.It isatthisstagethatweareconfrontedwiththeissueofidentifyingindividualsacrossworlds. Recallthatthisissuearoseforderemodalclaims (about, say, how Goldbach might have been), but not their de dicto siblings (about, say, the possibility of a woman discovering Goldbach’s conjecture). Kripke’s second major insight was that thinking about possible worldsintherightwayrevealstransworldidentityasapseudoproblem. Kripke thinks criteria for transworld identification are not needed to interpret de re modalclaimslikethefollowing: 43 (22) Nixonmighthavelostthe1968presidentialelection. Nixonlostthe1968presidentialelection Whycan’titbepartofthe description ofapossibleworldthatitcontains Nixon andthatinthatworld Nixon didn’twintheelection? Itmightbeaquestion,ofcourse,whethersuchaworld is possible.But, onceweseethatsuchasituationispossible,thenwearegiventhatthemanwhomighthavelostthe electionordidlosetheelectioninthispossibleworldisNixon,becausethat’spartofthedescriptionof theworld.…Thereisnoreasonwhywecannot stipulate that,intalkingaboutwhatwouldhave happenedtoNixoninacertaincounterfactualsituation,wearetalkingaboutwhatwouldhavehappened to him. (1980, 44,emphasisinoriginal) This suggests that given how we understand (22), an individual like Nixon is modally robust—abletosustainpredicationslike‘mighthavelostthe1968election’.Identifyinghim in a counterfactual situation is a nonissue. A possible world w in which someone who resemblesNixonbutisnothim(but,is,say,thecomedianDickFrye),andlosestheelection, is a world in which someone other than the modally robust individual Nixon loses the election;apossibleworld vinwhichNixonlosestheelectionisoneinwhichthemodally robust individual Nixon loses the election. No more can or needs to be said. Here is an analogy;imaginesomeoneinquiring:“IfIencounterabear,howdoIknowitisamammal?” Noassurancesandadvicecanorneedstobegiven—abear,ifitreallyisabear,cannotnotbe amammal;ifanonmammalisencountered(akoala,say),itcannothavebeenabeartobegin with,evenifitlookedbearlike. Atthisjuncture,dedictoclaims,whichhadbeenthoughtinnocuous,actuallyprove distracting.Forconsiderthepossibleworld uenvisionedhere: (23) It might have been that a cocker spaniel owner lost the 1968 presidential election. acockerspanielownerlostthe1968presidentialelection Wecannotanswerthefollowingquestion:is uthesameworldas w, v,orneither?Butthatis becauseforthepurposeofspecifying,“gettingat”possibleworlds,dedictoclaimslike(23) provideinferiormeansrelativetothemeansaffordedbyderemodalclaimslike(22).Thatwe cannotanswerthisquestionreflectsbadlyondedictoclaims,notdereones.

43 SeealsoKripke(1971,146–9;1980,39–47).

25 Theupshot:notonlyarederemodalclaims—interpreted in accordance with the metaphysicalconceptionofmodalityratherthanQuine’s—intelligible ,butmakingsenseof themis simple . What is missing from Kripke’s account then? First, he fails to recognize the individualdriven picture. Second, not only did his account of rigid designation steal the limelight;italsoblurredthesuggestionthatpropernamesrefertomodallyrobustindividuals. Theindividualdrivenpicturehasitthatpossibleworldsarealternativewaysmodallyrobust individualsare;theindividualsarethestartingpoint,theworldsarebasedonthem.Kripke comesveryclosetoofferingthispicturebysuggestingthatwebeginwithindividuals: 44 Wecanrefertotheobjectandaskwhatmighthavehappenedto it. So,wedonotbeginwithworlds (whicharesupposedsomehowtobereal,andwhosequalities,butnotwhoseobjects,areperceptibleto us),andthenaskaboutcriteriaoftransworldidentification;onthecontrary,webeginwiththeobjects, which we have, andcanidentify,intheactualworld.Wecanthenask whethercertain things might havebeentrueoftheobjects(1980,53). Here,therearestillremnantsoftheoldpictureofindependentlyspecifiedpossibleworlds: Kripkesaysthatindividualsidentifiedintheactualworldcome first ,andtheotherworldsare considered later ;buthedoesnotsaythattheformeraretheconceptualbuildingblocksin termsofwhichtoconstructthelatter.Hemayhavethoughtthatthisisapointonwhichhe canremainneutral,becausehisproposalaboutpossibleworldsandindividualsdoesnotrely onsuchanassumptionaboutpossibleworlds.Thathestopsshortofmakingthepointthat modallyrobustindividualsarethebuildingblocksofpossibleworldsisalsoapparentfromhis discussionofrigiddesignation,shortlybeforethequotedpassage. Kripkeexplainsthatapropernamelike‘Nixon’isa rigid designator : RIGIDDESIGNATOR :THENEUTRALDEFINITION Arigiddesignatordesignatesthesameindividual i ineveryworldinwhich iexist;and designatesnooneotherthan i inworldsinwhich i doesnotexist. Thisdefinitionremainsneutralbetweentwooptions,distinguishedbySalmon(1981,33–4): PERSISTENTLYRIGIDDESIGNATOR Arigiddesignatordesignatesthesameindividual i ineveryworldinwhich iexist;and designatesnooneinworldsinwhich i doesnotexist. OBSTINATELYRIGIDDESIGNATOR Arigiddesignatordesignatesthesameindividual i ineveryworld. Kripke’s aim was to maintain neutrality and avoid choosing between persistence and obstinacy(1980,20,n21;48);thereisonepassagewherehegivesthedefinitionforpersistent rigidity (1971, 146). He later clarified that it was the neutral definition he had in mind (Kaplan 1989b: 569–70). The second clause in the neutral definition—‘designates noone other than i in worlds in which i doesnotexist’—isintendedtosidestepcertainquestions Kripke takes tobe independent of his enterprise. He wants to claim that proper names of contingentexistentsarerigiddesignators;tosaythismuch,hethinksnothingneedstobesaid about how and whether to assign truth values to claims like ‘Nixon is human’ and ‘KaliningradisKönigsberg’inpossibleworldsinwhichNixonisneverborn,andthecityof

44 Followingthispassage,Kripkeimmediatelymovesontoanotherissue:fixingthereferenceofapropername versusgivingasynonym(1980,53–60).

26 Kaliningradisneverfounded.45 Buttheveryfactthatheappearstothinkitmightberegarded asmore puzzling totalkaboutthereferenceof‘Nixon’inaworldinwhichNixonisnever born(orconceived),thaninaworldinwhichheownsnocockerspaniel,reflectsthatattimes, heisnotquitethinkingofNixonasamodallyrobustindividual.Perhapsonoccasionheis stillinthegripoftheoldpictureofindependentlyspecifiedpossibleworlds,andthinksthatin aworldwhereNixondoesnotexist,wefindavoid wherethereferentshouldbe.Thatis becauseonthoseoccasions,heisnotthinkingofthereferentof‘Nixon’asamodallyrobust individual. Instead,thereissupposedtobetheactualNixon—whowonin1968,owneda cocker spaniel, resigned the presidency in 1974—and his name comes with a special transworld fishing rod that has its catch assigned for every possible world; except in the worldswhereNixondoesnotexist;there,thefishinglinedangleswithoutacatch(areferent). By contrast, on the individualdriven picture, ‘Nixon’ refers to Nixon, the modally robust individual, regardless of which world we are at. The relevant notion of rigidity is that of obstinaterigiditythen,withnonexistencenobarriertoreference.Onthispicture,theworlds are,afterall,waysmodallyrobustindividualsmighthavebeen—andthatincludesworldsin whichtheydonotexist,asmuchasworldsinwhichtheyownnocockerspaniel.HadKripke realizedthismuch,hewouldnothavethoughtNixon’scontingentexistenceposedanyspecial problemwhenthinkingabouthowandtowhat‘Nixon’refersinsuchaworld.Weareabout toseeKaplan(1989a,1989b)criticizingKripkeonthesamepoint. The proposal that proper names are rigid designators paints a false picture: proper names like ‘Nixon’ are thought special because they come equipped with the special transworldfishingrod,withthesamemanassignedasits“catch”ineachpossibleworld.By contrast,definitedescriptionslike‘thepersonwhowonthe1968presidentialelection’donot come with such equipment and are therefore nonrigid.Thisismisleading:whatisspecial aboutpropernamesisthattheyrefertomodallyrobustindividuals;theydothatonce,andno more fishing is needed as counterfactual situations come under consideration; the possible worldsarejustalternativewaysthoseindividualsare.Consideringacounterfactualsituation involving Nixon does not involve leaving one Nixon behind and homing in on another (howeverautomatically);thereisnoleavinghimbehind,sothereisnorepeatedhominginon himeither. In the 1980 Preface , to Naming and Necessity , Kripke defines rigid designators as expressionsthatplayadistinctiveroleinactualandcounterfactualtruthconditions(1980,6– 7).Consider: (24)Nixonlostthe1960presidentialelection. (25)The37 th U.S.Presidentlostthe1960presidentialelection. Asadescriptionoftheactualworld,(24),a(nonmodal)claimfeaturingtherigiddesignator ‘Nixon’ is true just in case Nixon (our Nixon) loses in 1960; and as a description of a counterfactualsituation,theclaimistruejustincasethatsameindividuallosesin1960.By contrast,thetruthconditionsof(25),withthenonrigiddescription‘the37 th U.S.President’, donotinvolveafixedindividualfromoneworldtothenext,butdifferentpeople,whoever happenstobethe37 th U.S.President(Nixonintheactualworld,HubertHumphreyinone counterfactualsituation,GeorgeWallaceinathird,andsoon).Kripkeconsidershis“main remark [to be] that we have direct intuition of the rigidity of names, exhibited in our understandingofthetruthconditionsofparticularsentences(1980,14).”Thinkingintermsof the distinctive truthconditional contribution of proper names is closely related to ideas Kaplan(1978,1989a)developedinthe1970’s,tothesewewillnowturn. 45 Kripkeaddressedthisissuebrieflyinhisearlierworkonthemodeltheoretictreatmentofmodallogic(1963, 65–6).

27 4. Direct reference TheofKaplan’sinfluentialmonograph Demonstratives (1989a),writtenin1977,was onthesemanticsofindexicalexpressions:suchas‘now’,‘I’,anddemonstrativeslike‘that’, ‘she’.Kaplanarguedthattheseexpressionsare directly referential inthattheycontributetheir objects—individuals—to thepropositions expressed, to propositional content . For example, when I point to a portrait of Laika and say ‘She died in space’, the demonstrative ‘she’ contributes Laika herself , the first dog in space, to the I expressed—to propositional content. The proposition thus consists of Laika, the dog, and the property of dying in space. This is a singular proposition about Laika. By contrast, the proposition expressedby‘Themostfamousastronautdogdiedinspace’,isa general proposition ;itisnot aboutLaikainparticular,butgeneralconditionsthatfitLaika,andheronly:namely,being themostfamousastronautdog.Boththesingularandthegeneralpropositionhasaninternal structure—is a structured proposition 46 —but only the former has Laika as a propositional constituent,duetothefactthatindexicals(includingthedemonstrative‘she’)aredevicesof directreferencewhereasdefinitedescriptionsarenot. Butthemeaningofindexicalsisnot exhausted by theircontent—theindividualthey contribute to the proposition expressed. ‘I’ also had a “second kind of meaning… which determinesthecontentinvaryingcontexts.Therule,‘“I”referstothespeakerorwriter’isa meaning rule of the second kind” (Kaplan 1989a: 505). Kaplan calls this kind of rule the character of‘I’,afunctionfromcontextsofutterancetocontents. Like indexicals, proper names are directly referential: the content (propositional contribution) of ‘Laika’ is Laika, the dog. ‘Laika died in space’ expresses a singular proposition,indeed,thesamesingularpropositionthatwehaveassociatedwithanutterance of‘Shediedinspace’.Unlikeindexicals,propernameslacka semantic rulethatdetermines theircontent,aruleofwhichcompetentEnglishspeakersareaware.Recallourdiscussionof commoncurrencywords 47 :thename‘Laika’wasintroducedintothelanguageforacertain dog,becameacommoncurrencyword,gotanchoredtothatdog,andhasbeenanchoredto hereversince.48 ButKaplanthinksthehistoryofintroductionanduseofthename‘Laika’isa presemantic matter.Forexample,thecontextofutteranceplaysapresemanticroleinhelping usdecidewhich word ‘hot’wasusedbyaspeakerinaparticularcontextofuttering‘I’mhot’ (was she talking about heat or about looks?). 49 Like ‘hot’, ‘Neil Tennant’ is ambiguous between(atleast)twodistinctcommoncurrencywords,oneforthepopsinger,andonefor thephilosopher(seeSectionII.3above).Ifwebelievethis(itishardnotto),theneach‘Neil Tennant’hasafixedcharacter:nomatterwhatthecontextofutterance,‘NeilTennant 1’refers tothepopsinger,and‘NeilTennant 2’tothephilosopher.Thehistoryofintroductionanduse ofeachnameplaysapresemanticrolethen,allowingustodecidewhich‘NeilTennant’was 46 Fine (2005b: 22–3) points out that direct reference theory does not require the structuredpropositions framework; the theory need only claim that certain propositions are singular , but it need not go so far as claimingthattheyare structurally singular .Onstructuredpropositions,seeKaplan(1975,1978,1989a,1989b). 47 SectionII.3,especiallyfootnote17. 48 Infact,therewassomeconfusionsurroundingtheintroductionofthename,because‘laika’inRussianisa labelforacertainbreedofdog.Newsreportersthoughttheywereadoptingthecommoncurrencypropername ‘Laika’ from Russian, but in fact, they inadvertently introduced a new name for the dog. This highlights yet another source of error to which community consensus opinion is susceptible (see Section II.3 above): the linguisticcommunityasawholemightmistaketheintroductionofanewwordforcarryingonwiththeuseofan alreadyestablishedcommoncurrencyword.Ifwethink(plausiblyenough)thatanewword‘Madagascar’for theislandwasinadvertentlyintroducedbywesterners,thenthatprovidesafurtherexampleofthissortoferror. This is not so important for my previous discussion of ‘Madagascar’, because the mistakes relevant involve thinkingthatawordisanchoredwheninfactitisnot;forthename‘Laika’anchoringwasneveranissue. 49 SeeKaplan(1989a:559–62;1989b573–77)aswellasStanleyandSzabó(2000,220–8).

28 usedonagivenoccasion.Butfixedcharactersalsomeanthatcoreferringpropernames(like ‘Kaliningrad’and‘Königsberg’) cannot havedistinctcharacters:theyrefertothesamecity and they therefore havethesamefixedcharacterandthesamecontent.50 Inthisway,for propernames,weseecharacter,content,andreferentcollapse,so“itisnotunnaturaltosayof propernamesthattheyhavenomeaningotherthantheirreferent”(Kaplan1989a:562).This outcomehasinspiredMillianism,theviewaccordingtowhichthesolesemanticfunctionof proper names is to pick out their referents because they connect to their referents directly, withoutthemediationofanysemanticrules.Thisview,alsoadvocatedbyKaplan(1989a), willbediscussedinthenextsection.Butbeforehand,itiswelltoexploreKaplan’scriticism ofKripke’sproposalthatNixonhasnoreferentinaworldinwhichNixondoesnotexist. Kripkedeliberatelyavoidedtalkofpropositions—singularorgeneral(1980,21). 51 But propositionsarenotessentialtothedirectreference view either. We can set apart directly referentialexpressionsfromothersbypointingoutthattheycontributetotruthconditionsina specialway—thetruthconditionsinvolvetheactualreferent,aspecificindividual,evenwhen theutteranceisevaluatedincounterfactualcircumstances(Martí2000).Thisisthefamiliar pointwehavealreadyseenKripkemakeaboutrigiddesignators:theyaredistinctiveinthat theindividualactuallysingledoutiswhatisrelevanttoactualaswellascounterfactualtruth conditions(thisholdsfor(24),withapropernamebutnot(25),whichinvolvesanonrigid description).Indeed,thetwotheses—thatpropernamesaredirectlyreferentialandthatthey arerigiddesignators—areboththesesaboutwhatnames“contributetothedeterminationof truthandfalsity”(Martí2000).Andthethesesagree:thecontributionisthereferentofthe name—theindividual.ButKaplanthinksdirectreferenceis“supposedtoprovidethedeep structure for rigid designation, to underlie rigid designation, to explain it” (Kaplan 1989b: 571).ThisbringsustoKaplan’scriticismandreformulationoftherigiddesignatordefinition. Kaplan’sargumentgoesasfollows.Theimportantsenseofrigiddesignation,theone Kripkeshouldhaveintended,isthis:apropernamereferstothesameindividualinevery possibleworld.Period.‘Nixon’referstoNixoneveninworldsinwhichNixondoesnotexist. This is the definition of an obstinately rigid designator .52 It is one thing to recognize the insight that proper names refer to the same individual in every possible world; but it is somethingelsetorecognizethattheydoso because of a special semantic feature: that they refer to their objects directly . There are expressions that happen to designate the same individualineveryworld:forexample,‘thesquarerootof64’rigidlydesignatesthenumber eight.Butthisisnotduetosemanticsatall.Also,‘themanwhoactuallyprovedGoldbach’s conjecture’ rigidly designates Goldbach. But this is not due to the semantics of definite descriptions in general ,buttothesemanticsof‘actually’. 53 Thatpropernamesreferdirectly to an individual is a profound fact about their semantics; that they rigidly designate that individualisasuperficialconsequenceoftheprofoundfact;instead,whatgetsattheheartof 50 Kaplan (1990, especially 114–7) argues for a conception of words according to which coreferring proper names can bedistinctcommoncurrencywords:‘Hesperus’and‘Phosphorus’areplausibleexamples.Butthen theirdistinctnessisnotsomething semantics wouldcapture.Onthispoint,seealsoKripke(1979,408,n43). 51 OneofthemostprominentfollowersofKripke,ScottSoames,doesnot.SeeforexampleSoames(2002). 52 See the three definitions of rigidity in Section III.3. See also the discussion in Kaplan (1989a: 493–97, especiallyn16;1989b:568–71),aswellasinSalmon(1981,32–40).Salmoncoinedthelabel‘obstinatelyrigid designator’,alsosuggesting(1981,34,n37)thatobstinaterigidityisanticipatedinKaplan(1969,128),inthe passage“weshouldrestrictourattentiontoasmallerclassofnames;nameswhicharesointimatelyconnected with what they name that they could not but name it. I shall say that such a name necessarily denotes its object…”.IdonotthinkKaplanisanticipatingobstinaterigidityhere;Salmonisquotinghimoutofcontext:the previoussentenceisabout“waysofspecifyingthenumbernine”.Necessaryexistentslikethenumberninedo not allow us to decide among the neutral, obstinate and persistent stripes of rigidity, because no situation in whichthenamefornineiswithoutadesignatedobjectarisesinthefirstplace. 53 Forinterestingdiscussionontheseissues,seeKripke(1980,21,n21),McGinn(1982),Kaplan(1989b:576– 7).Salmon(1981,32–41),andAlmog(1986,211–14,223–5).

29 the matter is thatproper names are obstinately rigidly designators. Kaplan thinks that had Kripkeseenthis,hewouldhaverecognizedthatthereferenceof‘Nixon’inaNixonlessworld is not a problem at all. Kaplan’s statement of this is clearest when he does not mention propositions:

Somehaveclaimedthatthoughapropernamemightdenotethesameindividual withrespecttoany possibleworld(or,moregenerally,possiblecircumstance)inwhichheexists,itcertainlycannotdenote himwithrespecttoapossibleworldinwhichhedoesnotexist.Withrespecttotsuchaworldthere mustbeagapinthename’sdesignation,itdesignatesnothing.Thisisamistake.Thereareworldsin whichQuinedoesnotexist.Itdoesnotfollowthatthereareworldswithrespecttowhich‘Quine’does notdenote.Whatfollowsisthatwithrespecttosuchaworld‘Quine’denotessomethingwhichdoesnot existinthatworld.Indeed,Aristotlenolongerexists,but‘Aristotle’continuestodenote(him).(Kaplan 1973,503) Notice Kaplan’s appeal to the temporal analogy: ‘Aristotle’ refers to an individual: Aristotle,whonolongerexists.Note,moreover,thatwearetalkingaboutatemporallyrobust individual, one that can sustain temporal predications. Likewise, ‘Quine’ refers to an individual,amodallyrobustindividual,noless,anddoessoeveninapossibleworldinwhich Quine does not exist. Kaplan is making the conceptual point that as devices of direct reference,proper namespurport to refer to temporallyandmodallyrobustindividuals;and giventhis,theissueofreferringtoindividualsatatimewhentheynolongerexist,orina possibleworldinwhichtheydonotexist,isnoproblematall.Indeed,wehavethewrong pictureifwethinkthereisanissuehere.Kripkewentwronginconstruingthereferentsof propernamesasindividualswiththespecialtransworldfishingrod.Onthisfalsepicture,in eachworld,thereisstillsomefishingtodo,howeverautomatedthatmightbeinthecaseof propernames;andfailingtofindthetargetcatchleavesuswithadanglingfishingline.In fact, no fishing is involved; we need only home in on the individual—a modally robust individual—once,intheactualworld,andfromthenon,we have theindividual.Had Kaplan argued along these lines, he would have had half of the individualdriven picture, about modally robust individuals, though not the other half, about possible worlds. But putting things in terms of structured propositions served to cover up the issue about what sort of individuals werethereferentsofpropernames.Itisnotsurprisingthenthatinadoptingthe structuredpropositions framework, proponents of Millianism completely lost sight of Kaplan’salmostarticulatedinsightaboutmodallyrobustindividuals.Beforetakingacloser lookatKaplan’sMillianlegacy,itiswelltoexplorethestructuredpropositionsframeworka bitfurther. Kaplan’s (1989a) primary concern were sentences containing indexicals. He developedaneleganttwostageinterpretationforthem.ImagineGoldbachsaying: (26)Imighthavebecomeadoctor. The interpretation of his utterance proceeds in two stages: first, we generate a structured proposition based on the context of utterance : a proposition whose constituents include Goldbach(whoisthespeaker—below),andthepropertyofbeingadoctor.Theseformthe singularpropositionalsoexpressedby(anutteranceof)‘Goldbachisadoctor’: 〈,Beinga doctor 〉.Thissingularpropositionisthefirsthalfofthepropositionexpressedby(26): (26')〈〈,Beingadoctor 〉,Beingpossiblytrue 〉 Second,we evaluate (26')relativetoa circumstance :inthiscase,themodalauxiliary‘might have’ instructs us to evaluate the proposition with respect circumstances other than the

30 context of the utterance—counterfactual circumstances; the proposition is true just in case thereisacounterfactualcircumstanceinwhichthesingularproposition 〈,Beingadoctor 〉 istrue—inwhichGoldbachwentintomedicine.Thefactthathewasnot actually adoctor,is irrelevanttotheevaluation,justasitisirrelevantwhoelsehaveactuallyuttered(26)onother occasions,andwhethertheyaredoctorsactually,orcounterfactually.Withindexicalslike‘I’, thetwostepshavetobedistinguished,becausecontextsofutteranceforthelikesof(26)(may and do) vary. If Goldbach utters (26), we are supposed to generate a proposition about Goldbach,andgoontoevaluateitwithrespecttocounterfactualcircumstances;ifMadamdu Châteletutters(26),wegenerateadifferentproposition,tobesubsequentlyevaluated. Noticeonecrucialdetailabouttheevaluationstage:fortheutteranceswemake,the circumstance of evaluation is typically the actual world. Usually we are not interested in whetherwhatwesaidwouldhavebeentrueinacounterfactualcircumstance . Counterfactual circumstances of evaluation matter to us in so far as they are relevant to the actual circumstanceofevaluation.ThisisinfactwhatwesawhappeningwithGoldbach’sutterance of (26): whether it is true in the actual circumstance of evaluation (in the actual world), depends on whether there is a counterfactual world in which the singular proposition 〈, Beingadoctor 〉 is true. The typical case thus involves an actual context of utterance generatingaproposition,the actual world as the circumstance of evaluation ,butthelatterin turninvolves evaluating some proposition in non-actual possible worlds. This setup has an adverse side effect: we get a misleading, flattenedpicture of the contentofpropositions.Whenweproceedtoevaluateutterances,thepropositionsthatmatter to the evaluation are non-modal. For example, evaluating (at the actual world) what is expressed by ‘Goldbach might have been a doctor’ (26' above), is computed based on evaluating the nonmodal proposition expressed by ‘Goldbach is a doctor’—〈, Beinga doctor 〉—invariousothercircumstances;callthesesubordinated circumstances of evaluation . Indeed,thisisexactlywhatpossibleworlds(ascircumstancesofevaluation)weresupposedto accomplish: capture what modal expressions contribute to truth conditions, and do this in terms of quantification over whatever the relevant possible worlds are. 54 (In the case of metaphysicalmodality,theworldsaresupposedtobethemetaphysicallypossibleones.)In the actual circumstance of evaluation, the modal expression calls for taking into account subordinated circumstances. The next section will show how this twostage evaluation picture—the division of labor between propositions and possible worlds outlined above— proved misleading by (i) completely covering up the conceptual point that proper names purporttorefertomodallyrobustindividuals(aclaimwehavealmostseenKaplanreach), andasaresult,(ii)providedafalse,nonmodalpictureofthereferencerelation. 5. Millianism Afurtherlineofthoughtaboutdirectreference(alongsideKaplan’sclaimsthatindexicalsand propernamesaredevicesofdirectreference)identifiesthevariableunderanassignmentas theparadigmofdirectreference:“Avariable’sfirstandonlymeaningisitsvalue”(Kaplan 1989a, 484). 55 Recall that in the case of proper names, character, content and referent

54 ElsewhereIarguethatforcertainconceptionsofmodality—forexample,deonticmodality,aboutobligations andpermissions—thisbasicframeworkofinterpretingmodalityintermsofquantificationoverpossibleworlds produces unintuitive truth conditions for a certain class of sentences: conditional obligations (‘If you spot an accidentonthehighway,youmuststoptohelp’isaconditionalobligation).(Zvolenszky2002,2006).There,the framework lands us in truth conditional trouble; here,itlandsusinconceptualtrouble(describedin Section III.5). 55 After Mill’s System of Logic , to which Kripke (1980,26–8) appeals. For the paradigm of a variable, see Kaplan(1989a483–8;1989b571–3,591–3).Martí(1995)notesthatinKaplan’s work,the“Millianintuition

31 collapse.Propernamesarethereforeclosertovariablesthanindexicalexpressionslike(‘I’) are, which come with a meaning rule, a character, fordeterminingtheircontentrelativeto context. Proper names and variables under an assignment do no more than represent their referents, stand in for them. The Millian theory of proper names ( Millianism for short) consistsintheclaimthatapropername’sfirstandonlymeaningisitsvalue.Thissuggests that there is a special way, unmediated by semantics, in which proper names latch on to individuals—theirreferents.Inthis,theyareunlikedefinitedescriptionsaswellasindexicals. The variable paradigm motivates further the twostage evaluation described in the previous section. Kaplan remarks that the assignment of a value to a variable “is not ‘evaluating’thevariableataworld,ratheritisgenerating anelementofcontent,anditisthe contentwhichisthen evaluated ataworld(1989b:591;emphasisadded).” ItispreciselythislinethatJosephAlmog,whoproposesaMillianreinterpretationof Kripke’s insights about proper names, follows in his Naming without Necessity (1986), arguingforwhathecallsatwostagepicture. 56 Recalltheinterpretationof(26),amodalclaim byGoldbach(‘Imighthavebecomeadoctor’):itsmodalaspect was capturedonly after a nonmodalpropositionhasbeengenerated.ThisisexactlywhatAlmoghasinmind:“Onthe twostagealternative,namingcomesupatthegenerationstage,necessityisconsideredonly later,attheevaluationstage”(1986,225).AlmogtakesthistosetthingsrightwithKripke’s proposal,whichdoesnotseparateapremodalstage: The traditional question … Are there genuine naming devices? is a semantical question. Kripke’s distinctivestrategyistotackleitbyattendingfirsttoa metaphysical question . Wefocusonobjects,the designata, andtheirmodalproperties.Wedonotbeginoursemanticalinvestigationbylookingatthe designators and their purely linguistic features. Not at all. The intuitive test for rigidity that Kripke devises(1980,48–9)reflectsthispoint.Westartwithanindividual(Nixon),andweobservethat that individualcouln’thavefailedtobeNixon.Thus,theproperty being Nixon appliestohimnecessarily(or atleastessentially…) This observation is an observation in “metaphysics”; it is surely not an observation in “linguistics.” However, there emerges from it a linguistic thesis: ‘Nixon’, the singular term used in expressingtheproperty,isarigiddesignator.Ontheotherhand,thatsameindividualcouldhavefailed tobethepresidentoftheUnitedStatesin1970(again,ametaphysicaljudgment).Hence,thesingular term‘thepresidentoftheUnitedStatesin1970’isanonrigiddesignator.Andsoitgoes;‘thesquare rootof81’isrigid;‘thenumberofplanets’isnot.Howso?Consultyourmetaphysicalintuitions. … [Kripke]didn’tfocusonthe way thedesignatordesignates;hefocusedonthedesignatumand its modal properties.(Almog1986,211) Oneversionoftheintuitivetest 57 Almogdiscussesisthis:taketheschema‘noone otherthan xmighthavebeen x’;substituteaterm tfor x;iftheresultistrue,then tisarigid designator;iftheresultisfalse, t isnonrigid.Wecanputthisinamorecompactform: KRIPKE ’SINTUITIVETESTFORRIGIDITY Aterm tisarigiddesignatorifandonlyif ‘nooneotherthan tmighthavebeen t’istrue.

remains backstage when the discussion is couched in terms of propositional constituents.” It nonetheless “surfacesintheparadigmofavariable.” 56 SeeAlmog(1986),especially219–21. 57 ThisisoneofthetestsassociatedwithKripke’smodal argument againstoneversionofthedescriptiontheory of proper names: that a proper name is synonymous with some definite description(s) speakers commonly associatewithit.Foracoupleofdefinitiveformulationsofthemodalargument,seeSalmon(1981,24–27),and Soames(2002,22–4).FordiscussionthatvarioustestsKripkementionsarenonequivalent,see(Almog1986, 222–3,n9).

32 Almogobjectsthatforvariousterms,answerstowhetherornotitpassestherigiditytestare basedonconsiderationshavingtodowithmetaphysics,notsemantics.Ourintuitionthat‘No one other than Nixon might have been Nixon’ is true, but ‘Noone other than the U.S. President in 1970 might have been the U.S. President in 1970’ is false. But what sort of intuitionisresponsibleforthesejudgments?Intuitionsaboutthemetaphysicsofindividuals— andthoseintuitionsarenotsupposedtoplayaroleinansweringquestionssemantic. MyassessmentofAlmog’spositionisasfollows:heisrightononecount,andwrong on two others. On the one hand, he is right to point out that (i) certain intuitions about metaphysicsplayaroleinKripke’sargumentaboutthesemanticsofpropernames.Onthe otherhand,Almogfailsto(ii)differentiatewhichintuitionsaboutmetaphysicsarerelevant, andwhicharenot,and(iii)onceweseparateouttherelevantintuitions,weseethatthesortof metaphysics Kripke injects into his semantics is very much called for; omitting the metaphysics(asAlmogdoes)missessomethingcrucialaboutthelinguisticfunctionofproper names.Iwilldiscussthesethreepointsinturn. Let us begin with (i). Indeed, Kripke talks about ascribing modal properties to individuals—thereferentsofpropernames—andmoregenerallyabouttheeasewithwhich we interpret de re modal claims. These observations got him within arm’s reach of the discoverythatpropernamespurporttorefertomodallyrobustindividuals.Hadheclaimed thatpropernameswereobstinatelyrigid,ratherthanjustrigidaccordingtohisowndefinition, hewouldhavenailedthefirsthalfoftheindividualdrivenpicture: When youask whetheritis necessaryorcontingent that Nixon won theelection, you areaskingthe intuitive question whether in some counterfactual situation, this man would in fact have lost the election.Ifsomeonethinksthatthenotionofanecessaryocontingentproperty(forgetwhetherthere are any nontrivial necessary properties [and consider] just the meaningfulness of the notion) is a philosopher's notion with no intuitive content, he is wrong. Of course, some philosophers think that something'shavingintuitivecontentisveryinconclusiveevidenceinfavorofit.Ithinkitisveryheavy evidenceinfavorofanything,myself.Ireallydon'tknow,inaway,whatmoreconclusiveevidenceone can have about anything, ultimately speaking…(Kripke 1980, 41–2; italics in original, underlining added) We see that Kripke embraces what Almog calls “ modal individualism , the doctrine thatitismeaningfultoattributetoindividuals,bythemselves,modalproperties”. 58 Themodal individualismhechargesKripkewithamountstothesamethingasthefollowing:deremodal claims designate 59 modally robust individuals. Rigid designation is not alone in its commitmenttomodallyrobustindividuals;directreferenceisnodifferent: …themereattempttoshowthatanexpressionisdirectlyreferentialrequiresthatitbemeaningfultoask ofanindividualinonecircumstancewhetherandwithwhatpropertiesitexistsinanothercircumstance. If such questions cannot be raised because they are regarded as metaphysically meaningless, the questionofwhetheraparticularexpressionisdirectlyreferential(oreven,arigiddesignator)cannotbe raised. 60 (Kaplan1989a:504). By contrast, a Millian like Almog expressly disavows any commitment to modal individualism;hedoesnotthinkatheoryofnamingshouldbringonboardacommitmentof

58 Almog(1986,226;emphasisinoriginal).Thepassagecontinues:“inthepossibleworldsframework,modal individualismemergesasthedoctrinethatthetransworldidentityofindividualsisgiven”. 59 Ifollowthecommonusagehere:‘designate’isthebroaderterm—bothpropernamesanddefinitedescriptions may designate individuals;butonlytheformermay refer tothem. 60 Kaplancontinues:“Ihaveelsewherereferredtotheviewthatsuchquestionsaremeaningfulas haecceitism. ” (1989a:504).RecallFine’s(2005b)distinctionbetween modal and metaphysical haecceitism.Kaplanmeansthe former,notthelatter.SeeSectionII.5above.

33 thissort.61 Thisisbecausehethinksatheoryofnamingisaboutthegenerationstage:that propernamesareMillianreferentialdevicesmeansthattheycontributetheirreferenttothe proposition generated . Modal considerations arise at the subsequent evaluation stage and thereonly. 62 In sum, Almog is right with respect to (i): Kripke is committed to the modal robustnessoftheindividualsderemodalclaimsareabout;thisisaboutwhatourwaysof interpretingnaturallanguage(specificallyderemodalclaims)assumeaboutthemetaphysics ofindividuals. Letusmoveonto(ii).AlmogarguesthatKripke’s metaphysical commitments go beyond modal individualism. Is the offspring born from a certain gamete N necessarily Nixon?Ourintuitions(accordingtoKripke)say‘yes’;theintuitivetestabovemakes‘Noone otherthantheoffspringbornfromgameteNmighthavebeentheoffspringbornfromgamete N’comeouttrue,showingthat‘theoffspringbornfromgameteN’isarigiddesignator.Isit necessarythatthenumbereightisthenumbereight?Ourintuitions(accordingtoKripke)say ‘yes’again;theintuitivetestmakes‘Nothingotherthanthenumbereightmighthavebeenthe numbereight’comeouttrue;‘eight’isarigiddesignatorthen.Inthefirstcase,theintuitionis aboutthenatureoflivingthings;inthesecond,about the nature of mathematical objects. ThereissomejustificationforAlmog’schargeofexcessivemetaphysicalcommitment.First Kripke’sdiscussionofessencesandessentialpropertiesisonoccasionmisleading.Second, thefactthatKripkedid not definerigidityasobstinaterigidity,muddlesthings.Butoncewe setthingsstraightonthesetwocounts,Kripke’smetaphysicalcommitmentsdonotgobeyond modalindividualism.Itistimetosetthingsstraightthen. Onthefirstcount,consideragaintheunderlinedclauseinthepassageIquotedfrom Kripke:“forgetwhetherthereareanynontrivialnecessaryproperties[andconsider]justthe meaningfulness of the notion”. Here, Kripke makes clear that he is interested in whether it makes sense toattributenecessaryproperties(likebeingbornfromgameteN)toindividuals (likeNixon);heis not interestedinuncoveringwhat are necessarypropertiesoflivingthings or inanimate objects; even less is he suggesting that nontrivial necessary properties of individualscanbe derived fromthethesisthatpropernamesarerigiddesignators. 63 Wehave already encountered asimilarsortofmisinterpretation:inSectionIII.3,Iarguedthatashe wasgivingvariousillustrationsforhownecessityandaprioritycancomeapart,Kripkedid notlosesightofthefactthathisargumentsdidnotrelyonthere being aposteriorinecessities; allheneededwasthelesserpointthatthereare(amongothers)aposterioritruthsforwhichit is open whether they are necessary. One example we have already considered is ‘Nixon is human’.‘NixonisbornfromgameteN’isanotherexampleofthissort:it is anaposteriori truth(assumeNistheNixongamete);butitis open whetherornotitisnecessary—we can say this much independently of what we think about the metaphysics of living things . Kripke’sfocusisonthedesignatumandthatit can havemodalproperties(becauseit isamodallyrobustindividual);butthatdoesnotmeanheisfocusingonthemodalproperties thedesignatum has —whichofitspropertiesithasnecessarilyandwhichonlycontingently.In thelightofthis,thecriticalquestionisnot whether anexpressionpassestherigiddesignator test,orfulfillstherigiddesignatordefinition;instead,whatmattersis the basis onwhichit passesifitdoes.IfKripkehadbeenmorecareful,hewouldhavesaid:‘Nixon’isguaranteed 61 Martí(1995,seeespeciallyn17)concurs.Shepointsoutthreekeydifferencesbetweendirectreferencetheory and Millianism. First, indexicals are directly referential but not Millian referential devices. Second, direct referenceisaboutthetruthconditionalcontributionofexpressions,whereasMillianismisaboutthenatureofthe linkbetweenMillianreferentialdevicesandindividuals.Third,becauseofthislastpoint,directreferencetheory iscommittedtomodalindividualismbutMillianismisnot. 62 SeeAlmog1986,228–9. 63 ButseveralcommentatorsofKripke’slecturesdidthinkhispositionwasthatessentialismcouldbederived fromKripke’sthesis.Seefootnotes40and42aboutSalmon(1981)clearingthisup.

34 topasstherigiditytestconceptuallyguaranteed,noless;beingapropername,‘Nixon’works inawaythatguaranteespassingtherigiditytest:itreferstoamodallyrobustindividual.For ‘theU.S.Presidentin1970’, there is no such guarantee either way .Therewasnoneedtogo sofarasclaimingthat‘NooneotherthantheU.S.Presidentin1970mighthavebeentheU.S. President in 1970’ is false . Indeed, even if this is false, its falsity is not conceptually guaranteed . The fact that it seems so overwhelmingly plausible that it is false provided Kripkewithahandydemonstrationofthecontrastbetweentherigiddesignator‘Nixon’and the(plausibly)nonrigiddesignator‘theU.S.Presidentin1970’.Butweshouldnotlosesight of the metaphysical commitments Kripke needs totakeonboard—adetailhedidnotlose sightofinwaysinwhichcommentators,includingAlmog,did. The second count is about straightening the definition of rigidity. In Section III.3 above, we have already noted that Kripke could haveprovidedadefinitionthatwasmore revealing than the deliberately cautious neutral definition he gave (in a Nixonless world, ‘Nixon’eitherreferstoNixon,orhasnoreferent),andtheevasive definition of a persistently rigid designator (‘Nixon’hasnoreferentinaNixonlessworld)whichhedidgiveonone occasion(Kripke1971,146).Salmon(1981)andKaplan(1989a,1989b)arguedthatKripke shouldhavegiventhe definition of an obstinately rigid designator (‘Nixon’referstoNixon. Period.)RecallKaplan’spoint:thethesisthatpropernamesareobstinatelyrigidcapturesa deeper fact than the claim that they are persistently rigid, or rigid based on the neutral definition.Moreover,obstinaterigiditybecomesespeciallyinterestinginthecaseofproper namesofcontingentexistents:whenthere is apossibleworldinwhichtheactualreferentdoes notexist,butthepropernamestillreferstohim orher. Thisisbecauseitisnotjustany individualwearetalkingabout,butamodallyrobustone,towhomascribingthepropertyof possiblynotexistingisjustasstraightforwardasascribingapossibleelectionloss.Aname foranecessaryexistentlikethenumberninenevergetstoshowoffitsobstinatenatureinthe waynamesofcontingentexistentsdo. 64 So the paradigm of rigid designation that is truly revealing is that of obstinately rigid designators of contingent existents. HadKripkerealized this,hewouldhavenailedthefirsthalfoftheindividualdriven picture: proper names are obstinately rigid—and that means they purport to refer to modally robust individuals; wheneverthey are anchored,theydorefertomodallyrobustindividuals. Insum,Kripkecouldhavegivenabetterdefinitionofrigidity—anddefinedobstinate rigidity. But that does not give rise to additional metaphysical commitments. His commitments still do not extend beyond modally robust individuals, beyond modal individualism. Movingonto(iii):what,ifanything,istheMillianmissingaboutthesemanticsof propernames?RecallAlmog’stwostagepicture:“Ingeneratingthepropositionalconstituent correspondingtothename‘Quine’,wehavecorrelatedthenamewithanindividual and an individual only. WhenIsay‘Quineisaphilosopher’,aparticularindividual,Quinebecomes thesubjectconstituentofthepropositionIexpress”(1986,220).Necessityisconsideredonly later,attheevaluationstage.But what sort of individual isitthat‘Quine’refersto?Inthe Millianframework,thisquestionisnotasked.Therearetworeasonsforit,oneofthemis obvious,theotherisfarmoreinteresting.Theobviousreason:Millianismisonlyaboutthe generation stage—it is the view that ‘Quine’ contributes an individual to the proposition expressed,so‘Quineishuman’expressesasingularproposition.Wehavealreadyseenthat thisviewisneutralaboutthenatureofindividuals:theycouldbemodallyrobust,theycould beindividualswhoseidentificationacrossworldsrequiresnontrivialidentifyingcriteria,or theycouldbeindividualsforwhomtransworldidentitydoesnotmakesense. 65 64 Seefootnote52. 65 Almogremarksthat“DavidLewiscouldhavebeenaMillianwithoutalteringhismetaphysicsofworldbound individuals”(1986,229).

35 The more interesting reason why a Millian does not ask what sort of individual ‘Quine’refersto,isbecausehisframeworkofpropositionsmakesitimpossibleforhimtoask this question. This is because propositions are, at bottom, construed as nonmodal (extensional),andsoaretheirconstituents,includingtheindividualsthatMillianreferential devices“placeinto”thepropositionsbeinggenerated. On the twostage picture, the modal dimensiongets“ironedoutof”asingularproposition,andoutofitsconstituentindividual: bothbecomewhatwemightcall modally flat .Hereiswhy.Attheendoftheprevioussection, Idiscussedamodalclaimsimilartothisone: (27)Goldbachmighthavebecomeadoctor. First,wegenerateaproposition:itisnotthepropositionaboutGoldbachpossiblybecominga doctor though; instead, it is the possible truth of the singular proposition expressed by ‘Goldbachisadoctor’(involvingGoldbachhimself).Wecouldrenderitthus: 66 (27')〈〈,Beingadoctor 〉,Beingpossiblytrue 〉 Theevaluationiswithrespecttotheactualworld;butthelastbit,the modalcomponent, instructs us to consider other evaluation circumstances: counterfactual possible worlds. In thosecounterfactualscenarios(whichIhavecalledsubordinatedcircumstances),whatmatters is whether the singular proposition, 〈, Beingadoctor 〉, is true. The modal dimension of (27') is captured by shifts in evaluation circumstance; the presence of a modal expression instructs us to consider subordinated circumstances with respect to which the singular propositionisevaluated.Thebasicpropositionsarenevermodalthen—theyaremodallyflat. Amodalcomponent,ifthereisone,isaccountedforthroughtheshiftsinthecircumstances with respect to which simpler, nonmodal propositions are evaluated. In this picture, individualsarefeaturedaspropositionalconstituentsintroducedbyMillianreferentialdevices like proper names. They, too, are therefore modally flat: the individual is singled out (as modallyflat),“inserted”intotheproposition,sotheevaluationandcircumstanceshiftingmay begin. We see the twostage picture depicting a division of labor between evaluation circumstances (possible worlds) and modally flat propositions that completely reshuffles a function we had thought natural to assign to proper names: that they purport to refer to modally robust individuals. In the twostage picture, nothing performs this function; moreover, nothing could performit.Onehalfofthefunctionispackedinto the generation stage(gettingthemodallyflatindividualintotheproposition),theotherhalfistakencareof elsewhere:attheevaluationstage,whenwefind—withasighofrelief—thatthetransworld identificationofmodallyflatindividuals(whichcouldhavecausedtrouble)isautomatically accomplished. But why and how it is automatically accomplished remains a mystery. Nowhere in the twostage picture are we able to locate what accounts for the fact that transworldidentificationisgiven,itneedsnoexplanation. Theconceptuallybasicunitsofpropernamereference—modallyrobustindividuals— cannotbelocatedwithinthetwostagepicture.Theirfunctionhasbeendispersedamongother units—thebuildingblocksofthetwostagepicture:modallyflatpropositions,modallyflat individuals,andpossibleworldsasevaluationcircumstances.Wearefurtherthaneverfrom recognizingtheconceptuallybasicbuildingblocksoftheindividualdrivenpicture:modally robustindividuals,whichinturncanprovideabasisforaconceptionofpossibleworldsas nonbasic:aswaysmodallyrobustindividualsmighthavebeen.

66 SeeAlmog(1986,237–8).Notethat(26')and(27')areidenticalpropositions.

36 Moreover,thebuildingblocksthatthetwostagepicturedoesincludeareasourceof confusion. We might be puzzled over the following, deliberately casual description from Kaplan: If the individual is loaded into the proposition (to serve as the propositional component) before the proposition begins its round-the-worlds journey ,itishardlysurprisingthat the proposition manages to find that same individual at all of its stops, even those in which the individual had no prior, native presence .Thepropositionconductednosearchforanativewhomeetspropositionalspecifications;it simply‘discovered’whatithadcarriedin.Inthiswayweachieverigiddesignation.Indeed,weachieve the characteristic, direct reference, form of rigid designation, in which it is irrelevant whether the individual exists in the world at which the proposition is evaluated. (Kaplan 1989b: 569; emphasis added) Whatdoesitmeanthatthepropositionistakingajourney,andthattheindividualiscarriedin andisdiscoveredeveninaworldinwhichit hasnonativepresence?Whatisthe‘it’?What doesitmeanforamodallyflatpropositiontobemovedinandoutofworlds?Andfora modallyflatindividualtobecarriedintoaworld?67 Theonlywaythiscanbemadecoherent isifwethinkthattherearemodallyrobustindividualsasthereferenceof‘it’.Wecouldretain themodallyflatindividualsaspropositionalconstituentsandtheinworld“embodiments”of modally robust individuals; but we will definitely need the modally robust individuals, in which case it becomes unclear why we still want the modally flat individuals, too. With modallyrobustindividualsadmitted,modallyflatpropositionswillprove“tootight”:because some(ifnotall)singularpropositionswillhavemodallyrobustindividuals“inthem”.This wouldactuallymaketheroundtheworldsjourneymorecoherent.Butwealsofindthatthe journeyisnolongercalledfor.We have theindividuals;theyaremodallyrobust;andwhen interpretingderemodalclaims,weareconsideringwaystheseindividualsmighthavebeen. Asfarasweareconcerned,thisisallthereistopossibleworlds.Thisisthesecondhalfofthe individualdrivenpicture. 67 Inarecentvolumeondirectreference,MatthewDavidson(2007)chargesthatproponentsofdirectreference theoryandMillianismareinthegripofafalsepicture of possible worlds—what he calls “bad metaphysical picturethinking”—which generates conceptual confusion of the sort exposed in the questions just listed. He arguesthatforaMillianaswellasadirectreferencetheorist,‘Nixondoesnotexist’cannotbetruewithrespect to a possible world. He thinks any attempt along the lines given by Kaplan above is bound to rely on a distinctionbetween‘beingtrueinaworld’(whichconcernswhatis inside aworld)and‘beingtrueataworld’ (whichconcernsmatters outside theworld).‘Nixondoesnotexist’isnottrueinanyworld,butistrueatsome worlds—theNixonlessones.(ThedistinctionandtheterminologyareAdams’s(1981,22).)Butthedistinction, andinparticular truth at cannotbemaintainedaccordingtoDavidson: Truthatlookstobebasedonanincoherentmetaphysicalpicture.Indeed,itisbasedonthesamesortof pictureonwhichtheproblemoftransworldidentityisbased.Again,wethinkofworldsasobjectswith insidesandoutsides.However,again, worldsareabstract,anditisincoherenttothink ofa worldas having an “inside” and an “outside.” Also, propositions are abstract objects, and can’t be “carried” anywhere.Norcantheysitoutside(norinside)possibleworlds.(2007) I disagree with Davidson’s assessment. Truth at is perfectly coherent; it makes perfect sense on the individualdrivenpictureaswellasinFine’sframework(1985,194;seealsohis2005a).Weneed truth at ;we needittocapturethewayinwhichderemodalclaimsareinterpreted.Thefactthat truth at isincoherentonthe twostage picture with modally flat propositions, modally flat individuals, and possible worlds as our basic buildingblocks,meansweshouldabandonthetwostagepicture,not truth at .Intheend,Davidsonhimselfends upinthegripofthetwostagepicture,losingsightofalternativewaysofconstruingindividuals,propositions, andpossibleworlds.Itisincoherentforworldstohaveinsidesandoutsidesonlyinsofaraswefailtorecognize that individuals (modally robust individuals) definitely can have insides and outsides with respect to a or circumstance :thatIexistandamabrunetteareinsideaffairswithrespecttotheactualworld;thatIam possibly blond and possibly nonexistent are outsideaffairs,perhaps moreaptlycalled worldindependent or unworldlyaffairs(seefootnote3onFine2005a).

37 Insum,theMilliantwostagepictureisconceptuallymisleading:itsuggeststhatthe nonmodalstageofgeneratingaproposition—amodallyflatpropositionwithamodallyflat individualinit—isseparatefromthesecond,evaluationstagewherepossibilityandnecessity are captured through shifting between worlds as evaluation circumstances.Nowhere do we findheremodallyrobustindividuals;fortheMillian,referencetoanindividualisreferenceto a modally flat individual. We lose sight of the insight that natural language comes with expressions—propernames—thatmakemodaltalkaboutindividualsstraightforward. IV.CONCLUSION My aim in this paper has been twofold. My first goal was to lay out and motivate the individualdrivenpictureasaframeworktoexplainsomeofthemostbasicfactsabouthow weinterpretmodaldiscourse.Mysecond goal wasto show how conceptions of necessity “evolved”overtimetobringtheindividualdrivenpicturewithinarm’sreach,onlytohaveit disappearagain.Wehadbeensoclose:SaulKripkearrivedatthemetaphysicalconceptionof modality, and formulated the notion of a rigid designator. David Kaplan cleared up a conceptualconfusionaboutrigiddesignation,thushominginonmodallyrobustindividuals astheunitsofpropernamereference;buthispreferredframeworkofstructuredproposition hadseveraladverseconsequences.Straightaway,itblurredKaplan’sinsightaboutthemodal robustness of individuals. Subsequently, it inspired a mistaken picture of reference: Millianism,inthecontextofwhichtheinsightthathadbeengainedvanishedentirely.We sawitdissolvecompletelywithinAlmog’sMilliantwostagepicture. Inclosing,Iwouldliketorelatesomelessonsaboutpropernamestothedistinction betweendereanddedictomodalclaims.Thestartingpointfordevelopingtheindividual driven picture was the interpretive task with which de re modal claims—about specific individuals—presented speakers. Proper names were onetypeofderevehicle,butnotthe onlytype: (3) ThediscovererofGCissuchthat he himself eschewsmathematics Thetaskofinterpreting(3)issimilartothatof(6): (6) Goldbacheschewsmathematics For both (3) and (6), the meaningfulness of attributing modal properties to individuals is presupposed;thatistosay,both(3)and(6)purporttobeaboutmodallyrobustindividuals. Propernamesthereforedonotaddtotheexpressivepoweroflanguageinthesensethatwedo not need themtomakederemodalclaims.Wecouldhavearrivedattheindividualdriven picturebyconcentratingon(3)only,andtheconceptualrequirementsimposedonusbythe taskofinterpretingit.Thewaytocapture(3)wouldbethroughquantifyingin:themodal operatorattachestoaformulawithfreevariablesinit,whicharethenboundfromoutsidethe modaloperator.ThefactthatinthiswaywelandaderemodalclaimunderscoresKaplan’s remark that for the special way of designating an individual characteristic of directly referentialexpressions,thevariableunderanassignmentservesasaparadigm.Variablesin theopenformulaneedtodosomethingspecialtobemadesenseof:theyhavetobeassigned modallyrobustindividualsastheirvalues.Nowonderthenthattheaccomplishmentsof(6) and(3)aresosimilar:bothinvolvethedesignationofamodallyrobustindividual—oneuses apropernametothisend,theother,avariable.

38 That variables normally function otherwise—designating individuals that are not modallyrobust—isafalseimpressioncreatedbydedictomodalclaims,traditionallythought innocuous: (1) thediscovererofGCisawoman Here,wehavethefleetingluxuryoffocusingjustonwhatgoeson inside acounterfactual circumstance—intraworldaffairsinapossibleworldwhosepopulationneednotberelatedto the actual world, and its population. We are talking about there being someone in the counterfactual population who is a woman, discovering Goldbach’s conjecture. We can simply assign as values to our variables individuals that are not modally robust. But just becausewecangetawaywiththishere,andbecauseindividualsthatarenotmodallyrobust justseemsimplerthantheirmodallyrobustsiblings,does not meananyofthefollowing:  assigningthenonrobustindividualsasvaluesis conceptually simpler;  dedictomodalclaimsprovideasimplemodel,inneedofnospecialexplanation; incomparison,deremodalclaimsserveupacomplication;  we should accept a conception of possible worlds suggested by nonrobust individuals:possibleworldsconstruedascompletesituationswiththeirinhabitants and goingson, where the crossworld identity of individuals is an extra, outside affair. Themodelofdedictomodalclaimshassystematicallymisleadphilosophers,logicians andlinguistsaboutconceptionsofindividuals,ofmodality,andofpossibleworlds.Dedicto modalclaimsareinfactquiteunusualinthatthey,andtheyaloneenableustotalkabout merelypossibleindividualsthatarenonrobust.68 Bycontrast,deremodalclaims—bethey formulatedonthemodelof(3)or(6)—arefirmlygroundedintheactualworld;theycanbe aboutactualindividualsonly.Andthoseindividualsaremodallyrobust.Moreover,theease withwhichderemodalclaimsarecommonlyinterpretedmakesobviousthatmodallyrobust individualsareconceptuallybasic.Wecanrecognizethisfactbyconsideringcasesinwhich modallyrobustindividualscannotbereliedupon:whenwearetalkingaboutanunspecified counterfactual sister of Goldbach’s; when we are using a name like ‘Vulcan’ that is unanchorable;whenapropernameisnotyetanchoredandstillunderway,forexample,‘Jack the Ripper’ and ‘Newman 1’. These examples are discussed in Sections II.2–3, where I suggested that the dynamics of introducing and maintaining proper names within the vocabularyofalinguisticcommunityinvolvesanimplicitaim:ofattachingnamestomodally robustindividualsandthoseonly. Modally robust individuals also turn the previous, dedictoinspired conception of possible worlds upside down. Indeed we no longer have any reason to retain the old conceptionofpossibleworlds;allmodaltalkinvolvesbeyondthemodallyrobustindividuals is ways those individuals might have been. It becomes natural to take the individuals as conceptuallybasic,andtheworlds,asnonbasic;nottheotherwayaround. AlmogcloseshispaperNaming Without Necessity thus:“Ihavediscussedsomeissues concerningtheconnectionbetweennamingandnecessity.Ifanylessoncanbedrawnfrom thediscussion,itisyetagaininBishopButler’ssense:namingisnaming,andnecessityis necessity”(Almog1986,242).Thispassagehelpshighlightourdifferences.Millianismdoes notgetusclosertotheindividualdrivenpicture;quitetheopposite:itreversescrucialsteps 68 ButseeII.4aboutWoody,themerelypossiblelecternthatcanbeconstruedasmodallyrobustandthesubject ofderemodalclaims.Whatlooklikederemodalclaimsabout non robustindividuals(see7–9attheendofII.3 above)areproblematic:weareatalossastowhattransworldidentitytheseindividualsaresupposedtohave.

39 Kripke and Kaplan have taken towards that picture. Both of them came very close to recognizingthattheindividualtowhomapropernamerefersisnotjustanyindividual:itisa modallyrobustone.WhatMillianismdoesismakenamingandnecessityindependentofeach other;asaresult,crucialdetailsaboutthenatureofbothareleftunexplained,includingthe modalrobustnesspoint.Bycontrast,theindividualdrivenpictureaffordsinsights—someold, andsomenew—aboutinterconnectionsbetweennamingandnecessity,thusrevealingwhat the two notions really are about. I therefore propose to draw the opposite lesson: without (metaphysical) necessity, naming is not naming; and without naming, necessity is not necessity.

40 Adams,JohnM.1974.TheoriesofActuality.InThe Possible and the Actual ,ed.MichaelJ. Loux,1991,190–209.Ithaca,NewYork:CornellUniversityPress. Almog,Joseph.1986.NamingwithoutNecessity. Journal of Philosophy 83:210–42. Burgess, John 1998. Quinus ab Omni Nævo Vindicatus. In Meaning and Reference: Canadian Journal of Philosophy Supplement 23,ed. A.A.Kazmi.25–65. Burgess,John.2006. Saul Kripke, Naming and Necessity. In Central Works of Philosophy. Vol.5.,edJohnShand.London:AcumenPublishing. Chalmers,DavidJ.1997. The Conscious Mind .Oxford:OxfordUniversityPress. Davidson,Matthew.2007.TransworldIdentity,SingularPropositions,andPictureThinking. InOn Sense and Direct Reference, ed.MatthewDavidson.NewYork:McGraw–Hill. Donnellan,Keith.1970.ProperNamesandIdentifyingDescriptions. Synthese 21:335–58. Donnellan,Keith.1979.TheContingent A Priori andRigidDesignation.InContemporary Perspectives in the ,eds.PeterFrench,TheodoreUehling,and HowardWettstein.Minneapolis:UniversityofMinnesotaPress.12–27. Evans,Gareth.1973.TheCausalTheoryofNames.In Philosophy of Language ,3rd Edition, ed.A.P.Martinich,1996,271–83.Oxford:OxfordUniversityPress. Fitch,FrederickG.1949.TheProblemoftheMorningStarandtheEveningStar. Philosophy of Science 16:137–41. Fine, Kit. 1977. ‘Prior on the Construction ofPossible Worlds and Instants’, Postscript to Worlds, Times and Selves. InModality and Tense ,133–75 . Oxford:OxfordUniversity Press,2005. Fine,Kit.1985.PlantingaontheReductionofPossibilistDiscourse.In Modality and Tense , 176–213.Oxford:OxfordUniversityPress,2005. Fine,Kit.1989.TheProblemof De Re Modality.In Themes from Kaplan ,eds.JosephAlmog, John Perry, and Howard Wettstein, 197–272. Oxford: Oxford University Press. Page numbers to the reprint in: Modality and Tense , 40–104. Oxford: Oxford University Press, 2005. Fine,Kit.1990.QuineonQuantifyingIn.InProceedings of the Conference on Propositional Attitudes ,eds.C.A.Anderson,andJosephOwens,1–26.Stanford:CSLI. Fine, Kit. 2005a. Necessity and NonExistence. In Modality and Tense, 2005, 321–54. Oxford:OxfordUniversityPress. Fine,Kit.2005b.Reference,Essence, and Identity. In Modality and Tense ,19–39 . Oxford: OxfordUniversityPress,2005. Kaplan,David.1969(1967).QuantifyingIn.InReference and Modality , ed.LeonardLinsky, 112–44.Oxford:OxfordUniversityPress,1971. Kaplan,David.1973.BobandCarolandTedandAlice.In Approaches to Natural Language , eds.,JaakkoHintikka,JuliusMoravcsik,andPatrickSuppes,490–518.Dordrecht:D. Reidel. Kaplan,David.1975.HowtoRussellaFregeChurch. In The Possible and the Actual , ed. MichaelJ.Loux,210–24.Ithaca,NewYork:CornellUniversityPress,1991. Kaplan, David. 1978. (1970) DThat. In Philosophy of Language , 3rd Edition, ed. A. P. Martinich,292–305.Oxford:OxfordUniversityPress1996. Kaplan,David.1979(1967,1978).TransworldHeirlines.InThe Possible and the Actual ,ed. MichaelJ.Loux,88–109.Ithaca,NewYork:CornellUniversityPress,1991. Kaplan,David.1986.Opacity. In The Philosophy of W. V. Quine,eds.LewisE.Hahnand PaulA.Schilpp,229–89.LaSalle,IL:OpenCourt.

41 Kaplan,David1989a.(1977).Demonstratives.In Themes from Kaplan ,eds.JosephAlmog, JohnPerryandHowardWettstein,481–563.Oxford:OxfordUniversityPress. Kaplan,David1989b.Afterthoughts.In Themes from Kaplan ,eds.JosephAlmog,JohnPerry andHowardWettstein,565–614.Oxford:OxfordUniversityPress. Kaplan,David.1990.Words.ProceedingsoftheAristotelianSociety,SupplementaryVolume 64,93–119. Kripke,Saul.1963.SemanticalConsiderationsonModalLogic. Acta Philosophica Fennica 16, 83–94. Page references to the reprint in Reference and Modality , ed. Leonard Linsky,63–72.Oxford:OxfordUniversityPress,1971. Kripke,Saul.1971(1970).IdentityandNecessity.In Identity and Individuation , ed.Milton K.Munitz,135–64.NewYork:NewYorkUniversityPress. Kripke,Saul.1979.APuzzleaboutBelief.In Philosophy of Language , 3rd Edition,ed.A.P. Martinich,382–409.Oxford:OxfordUniversityPress,1996. Kripke,Saul.1980(1970,1972). Naming and Necessity .Cambridge,MA:HarvardUniversity Press. Lewis,C.I.1918. Survey of Symbolic Logic. Berkeley:UniversityofCaliforniaPress. Lewis,C.I.–Langford,C.H.1932. Symbolic Logic. NewYork:Century. Lewis,David.1968.CounterpartTheoryandQuantifiedModalLogic. Journal of Philosophy 65:113–126. Lewis,David.1986. The Plurality of Worlds. Oxford:BasilBlackwell. Marcus, Ruth Barcan. 1961. Modalities and Intensional Languages. Synthese 13:303–322. Pagereferencestothereprintin Modalities. Oxford:OxfordUniversityPress,1993. Martí,Genoveva.1995.TheEssenceofGenuineReference. Journal of Philosophical Logic 24:275–89. McGinn, Colin. 1982. Rigid Designation and Semantic Value. Philosophical Quarterly 32:97–115. Neale,StephenR.2000.OnaMilestoneofEmpiricism.In Knowledge, Language and Logic: Questions for Quine ,eds.PetrKotatko&AlexOrenstein,237–346.Dordrecht:Kluwer. Plantinga,Alvin.1979.ActualismandPossibleWorlds .InThe Possible and the Actual ,eds. MichaelJ.Loux,146–65.Ithaca,NY:CornellUniversityPress,1991. Prior,Arthur.1970.TheNotionofthePresent. Stadium Generale 23:245–8. Quine,WillardV.1943.NotesonExistenceandNecessity.Journal of Philosophy 40:113– 127. Quine,WillardV.1947.TheProblemofInterpretingModalLogic. Journal of Symbolic Logic 12:43–48. Quine, Willard V. 1963 (1962). Reply to Professor Marcus. In Proceedings of the Boston Colloquium for the Philosophy of Science ,ed.MarxW.Wartofsky,97–104.Dordrecht: D.Reidel. Russell,Bertrand.(1905).OnDenoting. Mind 14:479–93. Russell, Bertrand. (1918). The Philosophy of Logical Atomism. In Logic and Knowledge: Essays 1901–1950 , ed.R.C.Marsh,175–282.London:Allen&Unwin,1956. Salmon,Nathan.1981. Reference and Essence. Princeton:PrincetonUniversityPress. Salmon,Nathan.2004.TheGood,theBad,andtheUgly. In Descriptions and Beyond: An Interdisciplinary Collection of Essays on Definite and Indefinite Descriptions , eds. MargaReimerandAnneBezuidenhout,230–60.Oxford:ClarendonPress. Smullyan,ArthurF.1947.ReviewofQuine’s“TheProblemofInterpretingModalLogic”. Journal of Symbolic Logic 12:139–41. Soames, Scott. 2002. Beyond Rigidity: The Unfinished Semantic Agenda of Naming and Necessity . Oxford:OxfordUniversityPress.

42 Soames,Scott.forthcoming.KripkeonEpistemicandMetaphysicalPossibility:TwoRoutes totheNecessaryAposteriori.In Saul Kripke , ed.AlanBerger.Cambridge:Cambridge UniversityPress. Stanley,JasonandZoltánSzabóGendler.2000.OnQuantifierDomainRestriction. Mind and Language:15,219–61. Zvolenszky,Zsófia.2002.IsaPossibleworldsSemanticsofModalityPossible?In Semantics and Linguistic Theory XII ,ed.BrendanJackson,339–58.Ithaca,NewYork:Cornell UniversityPress. Zvolenszky, Zsófia. 2006. A Semantic Constraint on the Logic of Modal Conditionals. In Proceedings of the Ninth Symposium on Logic and Language (LoLa 9) , eds. Beáta Gyuris,LászlóKálmán,ChrisPiñon,KárolyVarasdi,167–77.Budapest:RévaiDigital Press.

43