Please Do Not Cite Or Circulate 1 Constitution And
Total Page:16
File Type:pdf, Size:1020Kb
Load more
Recommended publications
-
The Trial of the Arginousai Generals and the Dawn of «Judicial Review»
Edwin Carawan THE TRIAL OF THE ARGINOUSAI GENERALS AND THE DAWN OF «JUDICIAL REVIEW» After the victory at Arginousai in 406 BC the Athenian generals were accused of «betrayal» and condemned without trial, by a decree that the Athenians later repudiated as «unlawful» 1. What precisely made the proceedings paranomon is hard to define: What is the nomos that was violated? There was no constitutional document prescribing what we would call «due process», no general statute that expressly guaranteed to each citizen the right to trial by a properly constituted jury. And, as Xenophon describes it, the process was not altogether arbitrary. The assembly debated the matter at length and the defen- dants made a brief statement, presented witnesses, and nearly per- suaded the people to leave them free on bond. But as it was nearly dark and impossible to count hands in a close vote, it was decided that the council should draft a measure defining «the manner in which the men should be judged». One of the councilmen, Kallixenos, in- troduced a decree for the assembled demos to judge the defendants summarily and en masse: «… let the Athenians all decide, tribe by 1 Plato, Apologia, 32b: strathgoÝj toÝj oÙk ¢nelomšnouj toÝj ™k tÁj naumac…aj ™bouleÚsasqe ¡qrÒouj kr…nein, paranÒmwj, æj ™n tù ØstšrJ crÒnJ p©sin Øm‹n œdoxen. Cf. Xenophon, Hell. 1.7.25: … toÚtouj ¢pollÚntej ¢kr…touj par¦ tÕn nÒmon. Andrewes (1974) concludes from Diodoros (13.100-103) that it was the generals who began the recrimination. Nemeth (1984) gives a useful summary of prosopography; five of those condemned were associated with Alkibiades, a group on the ascendant, while Theramenes in eclipse had every reason to discredit them. -
Rethinking Athenian Democracy.Pdf
Rethinking Athenian Democracy A dissertation presented by Daniela Louise Cammack to The Department of Government in partial fulfillment of the requirements for the degree of Doctor of Philosophy in the subject of Political Science Harvard University Cambridge, Massachusetts January 2013 © 2013 Daniela Cammack All rights reserved. Professor Richard Tuck Daniela Cammack Abstract Conventional accounts of classical Athenian democracy represent the assembly as the primary democratic institution in the Athenian political system. This looks reasonable in the light of modern democracy, which has typically developed through the democratization of legislative assemblies. Yet it conflicts with the evidence at our disposal. Our ancient sources suggest that the most significant and distinctively democratic institution in Athens was the courts, where decisions were made by large panels of randomly selected ordinary citizens with no possibility of appeal. This dissertation reinterprets Athenian democracy as “dikastic democracy” (from the Greek dikastēs, “judge”), defined as a mode of government in which ordinary citizens rule principally through their control of the administration of justice. It begins by casting doubt on two major planks in the modern interpretation of Athenian democracy: first, that it rested on a conception of the “wisdom of the multitude” akin to that advanced by epistemic democrats today, and second that it was “deliberative,” meaning that mass discussion of political matters played a defining role. The first plank rests largely on an argument made by Aristotle in support of mass political participation, which I show has been comprehensively misunderstood. The second rests on the interpretation of the verb “bouleuomai” as indicating speech, but I suggest that it meant internal reflection in both the courts and the assembly. -
Socrates and Democratic Athens: the Story of the Trial in Its Historical and Legal Contexts
Princeton/Stanford Working Papers in Classics Socrates and democratic Athens: The story of the trial in its historical and legal contexts. Version 1.0 July 2006 Josiah Ober Princeton University Abstract: Socrates was both a loyal citizen (by his own lights) and a critic of the democratic community’s way of doing things. This led to a crisis in 339 B.C. In order to understand Socrates’ and the Athenian community’s actions (as reported by Plato and Xenophon) it is necessary to understand the historical and legal contexts, the democratic state’s commitment to the notion that citizens are resonsible for the effects of their actions, and Socrates’ reasons for preferring to live in Athens rather than in states that might (by his lights) have had substantively better legal systems. Written for the Cambridge Companion to Socrates. © Josiah Ober. [email protected] Socrates and democratic Athens: The story of the trial in its historical and legal contexts. (for Cambridge Companion to Socrates) Josiah Ober, Princeton University Draft of August 2004 In 399 B.C. the Athenian citizen Socrates, son of Sophroniscus of the deme (township) Alopece, was tried by an Athenian court on the charge of impiety (asebeia). He was found guilty by a narrow majority of the empanelled judges and executed in the public prison a few days later. The trial and execution constitute the best documented events in Socrates’ life and a defining moment in the relationship between Greek philosophy and Athenian democracy. Ever since, philosophers and historians have sought to -
La Délibération Démocratique À L'assemblée Athénienne
Edinburgh Research Explorer La délibération démocratique à l’Assemblée athénienne Citation for published version: Canevaro, M 2019, 'La délibération démocratique à l’Assemblée athénienne: Procédures et stratégies de légitimation', Annales. Histoire, Sciences Sociales, vol. 74, no. 2, pp. 339-381. https://doi.org/10.1017/ahss.2020.8 Digital Object Identifier (DOI): 10.1017/ahss.2020.8 Link: Link to publication record in Edinburgh Research Explorer Document Version: Peer reviewed version Published In: Annales. Histoire, Sciences Sociales Publisher Rights Statement: This article has been published in a revised form in Annales. Histoire, Sciences Sociales https://doi.org/10.1017/ahss.2020.8. This version is free to view and download for private research and study only. Not for re-distribution, re-sale or use in derivative works. © copyright holder. General rights Copyright for the publications made accessible via the Edinburgh Research Explorer is retained by the author(s) and / or other copyright owners and it is a condition of accessing these publications that users recognise and abide by the legal requirements associated with these rights. Take down policy The University of Edinburgh has made every reasonable effort to ensure that Edinburgh Research Explorer content complies with UK legislation. If you believe that the public display of this file breaches copyright please contact [email protected] providing details, and we will remove access to the work immediately and investigate your claim. Download date: 28. Sep. 2021 Democratic deliberation in the Athenian Assembly: procedures and behaviours towards legitimacy Mirko Canevaro (The University of Edinburgh) Abstract: The article examines the deliberative credentials of Athenian democracy. -
Huang He) Valley
A History of Knowledge Oldest Knowledge What the Jews knew What the Sumerians knew What the Christians knew What the Babylonians knew Tang & Sung China What the Hittites knew What the Japanese knew What the Persians knew What the Muslims knew What the Egyptians knew The Middle Ages What the Indians knew Ming & Manchu China What the Chinese knew The Renaissance What the Greeks knew The Industrial Age What the Phoenicians knew The Victorian Age What the Romans knew The Modern World What the Barbarians knew 1 What the Chinese knew Piero Scaruffi 2004 "shi shi shi shi shi shi shi shi shi shi shi shi shi" = "the master is fond of licking lion spittle" (Chinese tonguetwister) 2 What the Chinese knew • Bibliography: – Charles Hucker: “China’s Imperial Past” (1975) – Ian McGreal: Great Thinkers of the Eastern World (1995) – Alberto Siliotti: The Dwellings of Eternity (2000) – Sherman Lee: A History of Far Eastern Art (1973) – Wolfgang Bauer : China and the Search for Happiness (1976) – Joseph Needham: Science and Civilisation in China (1954) – John King Fairbank & Edwin Reischauer: East Asia Tradition and Transformation (1989) 3 Ancient Civilizations 4 Yellow River (Huang He) valley 5 http://www.artsmia.org/arts-of-asia/china/maps/index.cfm The Chinese Empire • 2500BC: ink, tea and silk are invented • 2205BC: the Xia dynasty is founded by Yu: Yellow River (Huang He) valley • 900BC: I Ching/Yi Jing • 700 BC: the Chinese invent gunpowder • 500BC: Confucius • 500BC: Daoism • 350BC: the period of the "warring states" is characterized by coins, iron -
Politics, Competition, and the Courts in Democratic Athens Susan Lape*
The State of Blame: Politics, Competition, and the Courts in Democratic Athens Susan Lape* Abstract Politics in democratic Athens routinely spilled over into the courts. From an Athenian perspective, this process was fundamentally democratic; it allowed the courts to provide a check on the power of individual political leaders and contributed to the view that the courts were the most democratic branch of Athenian government. That said, there were some downsides to transferring the scene of politics to the courts. When political issues and rivalries were brought into the courts, there was a tendency to render them into the court’s adversarial rhetoric. This translation of political issues into the polarizing language of judicial rhetoric in turn impoverished political reasoning and the political process. This study examines this broad process by first reviewing the culture of competitive honor that informed Athenian political and judicial practice, and then by examining how it operates in one famous and exceptionally competitive political trial in which politics and policy-making are center stage: Demosthenes’s prosecution of Aeschines for misconduct on the embassies leading to the Peace of Philocrates between Athens and Philip II of Macedon. The arguments and emotion strategies in this case indicate that intra-Athenian competition, both in and out of the courts, inflected the way foreign policy issues were conceptualized and understood, and was a factor in Athens’s inability to formulate a coherent policy and response to Philip of Macedon in the context of the Peace of Philocrates. * * * In the United States, the judicial system is supposed to be inoculated from political con- cerns, even though this is often more an ideal than reality. -
The Democratic Significance of the Athenian Courts
THE DEMOCRATIC SIGNIFICANCE! OF THE ATHENIAN COURTS 1,2 ! Daniela Cammack Abstract. Towards the end of the fifth century, the Athenians formally increased the political powers of their courts at the expense of those of the assembly. The significance of this move has been disputed, but it is agreed the aim was democratic self-restraint. This article questions that interpretation. There is no evidence the Athenians conceived judicial activity as a restraint on the dêmos. To the contrary, numerous sources cast the courts as the most demotic organ in the political system, and an examination of the respective compositions, procedures and functions of the assembly and courts finds several possible reasons why. The reconceptualisation of Athenian democracy this invites poses a considerable challenge to our !understanding of democracy both ancient and modern. Towards the end of the fifth century, the Athenians passed a series of reforms that formally increased the political powers of their courts at the expense of those of the assembly. Some thirty years ago these reforms occasioned considerable debate, one worth revisiting, not only for its intrinsic interest but because it suggests the limitations of an important assumption underlying many accounts of Athenian democracy. The reforms in question were three. First, between 410 and 399, came the reexamination and reinscription of existing laws and the establishment of a public legal archive.3 Next, in 403/2, came a new distinction between a law (nomos) and a decree (psêphisma) and a new legislative procedure (nomothesia). In the latter half of the fifth century the assembly had enacted all legislation, but now the power to make law, i.e. -
Rhetores and Strategoi in Fourth-Century Athens Mogens Herman Hansen
HANSEN, MOGENS HERMAN, "Rhetores" and "Strategoi" in Fourth-Century Athens , Greek, Roman and Byzantine Studies, 24:2 (1983:Summer) p.151 Rhetores and Strategoi in Fourth-Century Athens Mogens Herman Hansen ONCERNING POLITICAL LEADERSHIP in classical Athens histori C ans have posed a number of interesting questions: Were the Athenian 'politicians' recruited from the propertied families? Did they become rich in consequence of their political careers? Did they belong to the city demes or to the inland and coastal demes? Did they often serve as archai selected by lot? How often were they put on trial? But as a basis for their arguments historians tend either to draw up a random list of so-called politicians or to adduce five, ten, or fifteen examples of named political leaders, from which to draw conclusions. 1 In the absence of a list of political leaders, this is of course the only possible method, and doubtless the answers offered are often along the right lines. Nevertheless, given the very good sources available on fourth-century Athens, it is worth while to delimit the concept 'political leader' and accordingly draw up a list of persons meeting the criteria, so as to have a more rigorous basis for addressing questions of the sort mentioned above. In an earlier ar ticle 2 I argued that in fourth-century Athens the phrase PT,TOpf.~ Kat (TTpaT'Y'TrYOL is the nearest equivalent of what we, with a much vaguer and less formal term, call 'politicians' or 'political leaders'. Accor dingly, I present here the application of that principle, an inventory which is basically a list of rhetores and strategoi. -
The Living Constitution of Ancient Athens: a Comparative Perspective on the Originalism Debate
Cleveland State University EngagedScholarship@CSU Law Faculty Articles and Essays Faculty Scholarship 2009 The Living Constitution of Ancient Athens: A Comparative Perspective on the Originalism Debate Mark J. Sundahl Cleveland State University, [email protected] Follow this and additional works at: https://engagedscholarship.csuohio.edu/fac_articles Part of the Comparative and Foreign Law Commons, and the Constitutional Law Commons How does access to this work benefit ou?y Let us know! Original Citation Mark J. Sundahl, The Living Constitution of Ancient Athens: A Comparative Perspective on the Originalism Debate, 42 John Marshall Law Review 463 (2009) This Article is brought to you for free and open access by the Faculty Scholarship at EngagedScholarship@CSU. It has been accepted for inclusion in Law Faculty Articles and Essays by an authorized administrator of EngagedScholarship@CSU. For more information, please contact [email protected]. +(,121/,1( Citation: 42 J. Marshall L. Rev. 463 2008-2009 Content downloaded/printed from HeinOnline (http://heinonline.org) Thu Feb 14 13:38:25 2013 -- Your use of this HeinOnline PDF indicates your acceptance of HeinOnline's Terms and Conditions of the license agreement available at http://heinonline.org/HOL/License -- The search text of this PDF is generated from uncorrected OCR text. -- To obtain permission to use this article beyond the scope of your HeinOnline license, please use: https://www.copyright.com/ccc/basicSearch.do? &operation=go&searchType=0 &lastSearch=simple&all=on&titleOrStdNo=0270-854X THE LIVING CONSTITUTION OF ANCIENT ATHENS: A COMPARATIVE PERSPECTIVE ON THE ORIGINALISM DEBATE MARK J. SUNDAHL* I.Introduction ................................................................................. -
Graphe Paranomon" in Fourth-Century Athens , Greek, Roman and Byzantine Studies, 29:4 (1988:Winter) P.361
YUNIS, HARVEY, Law, Politics, and the "Graphe Paranomon" in Fourth-Century Athens , Greek, Roman and Byzantine Studies, 29:4 (1988:Winter) p.361 Law, Politics, and the Graphe Paranomon in Fourth-Century Athens Harvey Yunis N FOURTH-CENTURY Athens, when a dikasterion was convened to I hear a graphe paranomon, the jurors naturally heard the prosecu tor argue that the defendant's decree ("'~«j>Lup.a) was 7rapavop.ov or 7rapa TOUs voP.OV!;, that is, in conflict with some one or more statutes (VOP.OL) of the inscribed law code} The jurors were also likely to hear the plea that the decree under indictment was inexpedient (o.UVIJ. «j>opov) for the Athenian people, and the defendant ought to be con victed for that reason too, in addition to the conflict with statute law. If the decree under indictment was a grant of honors or citizenship, the jurors were likely to hear the further plea that the person named in the decree as the beneficiary of the grant was unworthy (o.va,to!;) of the honors or citizenship. This plea too would be advanced as reason to convict the original mover of the decree. For the sake of convenience, I will call the plea of paranomon the 'legal plea', and the latter two pleas, concerning inexpediency and unworthiness, 'political pleas'. In this paper I wish to consider the status of these two types of pleas. Are the political pleas to be counted among those numerous irrelevant ' arguments and considerations, such as the opponent's family back ground, that Athenian orators commonly introduced in an attempt to prejudice the jurors against the opponent? Or were the political pleas, as well as the legal plea, viewed by Athenian pleaders and jurors as I Throughout this paper the word 'decree' will be used to translate "'~tpHrp.a, and the word 'statute' to translate vop.os, in the senses these words bear in the statutes passed in 403/2 following the decree of Tisamenus (Andoc. -
John Hyland, the Aftermath of Aigospotamoi and the Decline of Spartan Naval Power
The Ancient History Bulletin VOLUME THIRTY-THREE: 2019 NUMBERS 1-2 Edited by: Edward Anson ò Michael Fronda òDavid Hollander Timothy Howe ò John Vanderspoel Pat Wheatley ò Sabine Müller òAlex McAuley Catalina Balmacedaò Charlotte Dunn ISSN 0835-3638 ANCIENT HISTORY BULLETIN Volume 33 (2019) Numbers 1-2 Edited by: Edward Anson, Catalina Balmaceda, Michael Fronda, David Hollander, Alex McAuley, Sabine Müller, John Vanderspoel, Pat Wheatley Senior Editor: Timothy Howe Assistant Editor: Charlotte Dunn Editorial correspondents Elizabeth Baynham, Hugh Bowden, Franca Landucci Gattinoni, Alexander Meeus, Kurt Raaflaub, P.J. Rhodes, Robert Rollinger, Victor Alonso Troncoso Contents of volume thirty-three Numbers 1-2 1 Kathryn Waterfield, Penteconters and the Fleet of Polycrates 19 John Hyland, The Aftermath of Aigospotamoi and the Decline of Spartan Naval Power 42 W. P. Richardson, Dual Leadership in the League of Corinth and Antipater’s Phantom Hegemony 60 Andrea F. Gatzke, Mithridates VI Eupator and Persian Kingship NOTES TO CONTRIBUTORS AND SUBSCRIBERS The Ancient History Bulletin was founded in 1987 by Waldemar Heckel, Brian Lavelle, and John Vanderspoel. The board of editorial correspondents consists of Elizabeth Baynham (University of Newcastle), Hugh Bowden (Kings College, London), Franca Landucci Gattinoni (Università Cattolica, Milan), Alexander Meeus (University of Mannhiem), Kurt Raaflaub (Brown University), P.J. Rhodes (Durham University), Robert Rollinger (Universität Innsbruck), Victor Alonso Troncoso (Universidade da Coruña) AHB is currently edited by: Timothy Howe (Senior Editor: [email protected]), Edward Anson, Catalina Balmaceda, Michael Fronda, David Hollander, Alex McAuley, Sabine Müller, John Vanderspoel, Pat Wheatley and Charlotte Dunn. AHB promotes scholarly discussion in Ancient History and ancillary fields (such as epigraphy, papyrology, and numismatics) by publishing articles and notes on any aspect of the ancient world from the Near East to Late Antiquity. -
Making Direct Democracy Work: a Rational-Actor Perspective on The
Const Polit Econ https://doi.org/10.1007/s10602-018-9263-4 ORIGINAL PAPER Making direct democracy work: a rational‑actor perspective on the graphe paranomon in ancient Athens Carl Hampus Lyttkens1,2 · George Tridimas3 · Anna Lindgren4 © The Author(s) 2018 Abstract The specifc way the Athenians set up their democracy presents both theoretical and empirical challenges. Decisions were taken by majority vote in the Assembly. To keep politicians in line, the Athenians frst used ostracism, which however was replaced by the graphe paranomon around 415 BCE. The latter pro- vided that anybody who had made a proposal in the Assembly could be accused of having made an unconstitutional suggestion, bringing a potentially severe pen- alty if found guilty. We know of 35 such cases between 403 and 322. During the fourth century the notion of illegality was extended to a mere question of political undesirability. Henceforth any decision by the Assembly could be overturned by the courts, but if the accuser failed to get at least 20% of the jury votes, he was punished instead. While these rules can be seen as a safeguard against bad decisions, they also provided the Athenian politicians with important information about the relative strength of their political support. This efect has not been analysed before, and it may help explain the relative stability of political life in classical Athens. Further- more this analysis also contributes to our understanding of a curious but often over- looked fact, namely that the decrees of the Athenian Assembly to a great extent con- cerned honorary rewards, and the use of the graphe paranomon in turn was largely focussed on the honorary decrees.