Nonclassical First Order Logics: Semantics and Proof Theory

Total Page:16

File Type:pdf, Size:1020Kb

Nonclassical First Order Logics: Semantics and Proof Theory Nonclassical first order logics: Semantics and proof theory Apostolos Tzimoulis joint work with G. Greco, P. Jipsen, A. Kurz, M. A. Moshier, A. Palmigiano TACL Nice, 20 June 2019 Starting point Question How can we define general relational semantics for arbitrary non-classical first-order logics? I What are the models? I What do quantifiers mean in those models? I What does completeness mean? 2 / 29 Methodology: dual characterizations q Non − classical algebraic Non − classical proof th: semantics first order models Classical algebraic Classical proof th: semantics first order models i 3 / 29 A brief recap on classical first-order logic: Language I Set of relation symbols (Ri)i2I each of finite arity ni. I Set of function symbols ( f j) j2J each of finite arity n j. I Set of constant symbols (ck)k2K (0-ary functions). I Set of variables Var = fv1;:::; vn;:::g. The first-order language L = ((Ri)i2I; ( f j) j2J; (ck)k2K) over Var is built up from terms defined recursively as follows: Trm 3 t ::= vm j ck j f j(t;:::; t): The formulas of first-order logic are defined recursively as follows: L 3 A ::= Ri(t) j t1 = t2 j > j ? j A ^ A j A _ A j :A j 8vmA j 9vmA 4 / 29 A brief recap on classical first-order logic: Meaning The models of a first-order logic L are tuples D D D M = (D; (Ri )i2I; ( f j ) j2J; (ck )k2K) D D D where D is a non-empty set and Ri ; f j ; ck are concrete ni-ary relations over D, n j-ary functions on D and elements of D resp. interpreting the symbols of the language in the model M. M j= > Always M j= ? Never M j= A ^ B () M j= A and M j= B M j= A _ B () M j= A or M j= A M j= :A () M 2 A M j= 8xA(x) () M j= A(d) for all d 2 D M j= 9xA(x) () M j= A(d) for some d 2 D. For a set of sentences Σ, we write Σ j= A if M j= A for every model M such that M j= B for all B 2 Σ. 5 / 29 Display Calculi I Natural generalization of Gentzen’s sequent calculi; I sequents X ` Y, where X and Y are structures: - formulas are atomic structures - built-up: structural connectives (generalizing meta-linguistic comma in sequents φ1; : : : ; φn ` 1; : : : ; m) - generation trees (generalizing sets, multisets, sequences) I Display property: Y ` X > Z X ; Y ` Z Y ; X ` Z X ` Y > Z display rules semantically justified by adjunction/residuation I Canonical proof of cut elimination (via metatheorem) 6 / 29 Quantifiers as adjoints Consider 8x : }(D × Dn) ! }(Dn), 9x : }(D × Dn) ! }(Dn) and π−1 : }(Dn) ! }(D × Dn) defined as: I 8 T f 2 j 2 g x(A) = d02D d D (d0; d) A I 9 S f 2 n j 2 g x(A) = d02D d D (d0; d) A −1 I πx (B) = D × B We have: −1 πx (B) ⊆ A () B ⊆ 8x(A) −1 9x(A) ⊆ B () A ⊆ πx (B) I Existential and universal quantification are the left and right adjoints respectively of the inverse projection map (Lawvere). 7 / 29 Algebraic properties of inverse projection maps Let M be a model of L. For every finite set F ( Var such that x < F we define maps (x)F; 9xF; 8xF such that (x)F is the inverse projection map, 8xF > # F[fxg F }(D ) o (x)F }(D ) > < 9xF then the following properties hold: (x)(A \ B) = (x)(A) \ (x)(B)(x)(A [ B) = (x)(A) [ (x)(B) (x)(DF n A) = DF[fxg n (x)(A)(x)(y)(A) = (y)(x)(A) (x)8y(A) = 8y(x)(A)(x)9y(A) = 9y(x)(A) 8 / 29 Algebraic semantics for first-order logic An heterogeneous L-algebra is a tuple H = (A; Q), such that I A = fAF j F 2 P!(Var)g; I Q = f(x)F; 9xF; 8xF; j x < F ( Varg; where for every F 2 P!(Var), AF is a complete Boolean algebra 8xF[fxg > AF[fxg o (x)F o AF > > 9xF[fxg such that (x)F is an order embedding and the following hold: (x)(a ^ b) = (x)(a) ^ (x)(b)(x)(a _ b) = (x)(a) _ (x)(b) (x)(−a) = −(x)(a)(x)(y)(a) = (y)(x)(a) (x)8y(a) = 8y(x)(a)(x)9y(a) = 9y(x)(a) 9 / 29 Logical connectives and types I Types will be named after the elements F 2 }!(Var). I A type LF contains a formula A iff FV(') = F. I A 2 LF[fyg () 8yA 2 LF I A 2 LFnfxg () (x)A 2 LF I Symbols for quantifiers and cylindrification for each x 2 Var: Structural symbols Qx ((x)) Operational symbols 9x 8x (x) (x) 10 / 29 Display Calculus Introduction rules for quantifiers and their adjoint: QxA ` F X X ` F A 9L 9R 9xA ` F X QxX ` Fnfxg9xA A ` F X X ` FQxA 8L 8R 8xA ` FnfxgQxA X ` F8xA X ` FnfxgY ◦M ((x))X ` F[fxg((x))Y ((x))A ` F X X ` F((x))A ·L ·R (x)A ` F X X ` F(x)A 11 / 29 Display Calculus Display postulates for quantifiers and cylindrification: QxX ` FnfxgY Y ` FnfxgQxX X ` F[fxg((x))Y ((x))Y ` F[fxgX Further adjunction rules: ((x))QxX ` FY X ` F((x))QxY X ` FY X ` FY Interaction rules: ((x))X; ((x))Y ` Z Z ` ((x))X; ((x))Y ((x))(X; Y) ` Z Z ` ((x))(X; Y) ((x))QyX ` Y Y ` ((x))QyX Qy((x))X ` Y Y ` Qy((x))X 12 / 29 Completeness (Canonical model) If Σ is consistent then it has a model. 13 / 29 Σ can be extended to a set Σ0 such that I Σ0 is a maximal consistent theory (an ultrafilter) I If 9xA 2 Σ0 then A(t) 2 Σ0 for some term t Define t ≡ s if and only if t = s 2 Σ0: I Let D = Trm= ≡ I Let RD(t) iff R(t) 2 Σ0 I Let M = (D; RD; f D; cD) Then M j= A if and only if A 2 Σ0. 14 / 29 Witnesses Problem f9xP(x); :P(t1; );:::; :P(tn);:::g. Solution(s) I Add infinite constants in the language, and construct the ultrafilter by “carefully” using the constants for witnesses. I Rename the variables in your set so that you have enough (infinite) variables unused. 15 / 29 Algebraic predicate semantics A heterogeneous L-algebra is a tuple H = (A; Q) where for every F 2 P!(Var), AF is a complete Heyting algebra/ distributive lattice/DLE/LE/etc::: 8xF[fxg > AF[fxg o (x)F o AF > > 9xF[fxg such that (x)F is an order embedding and a Heyting algebra/distributive lattice/etc::: homomorphism and the following hold: (x)(y)(a) = (y)(x)(a) (x)8y(a) = 8y(x)(a)(x)9y(a) = 9y(x)(a) 16 / 29 Completeness revisited Classical completeness If Σ is consistent then it is satisfiable. Completeness in weaker logics I If Σ is consistent then it is satisfiable I If ∆ is not provable then it is falsifiable I If Σ does not imply ∆ then there is a model that satisfies Σ and falsifies ∆. Filter-ideal pairs DL: Every disjoint filter ideal pair can be extended to a prime filter-ideal pair. Lattices: Every disjoint filter ideal pair can be extended to a maximal one. 17 / 29 A case in point: Intuitionistic logic I We let M := (W; ≤), where each element of W is a classical first-order model I u ≤ w implies that f : Dw ! Du is a homomorphism of models. I w j= 9xA(x) if and only if there is some d 2 Dw, w j= A(d) I w j= 8xA(x) if and only if for all w 2 W such that u ≤ w and for all d 2 Du, u j= A(d). Categorically A model is a functor from a poset W to the category of f.o. models and homomorphisms. The meaning of a formula (with one free variable) is a subobject of the model in this category of functors. 18 / 29 Canonical model: A story in multi-type I A is the algebra of the logic excluding infinite free variables I F is a prime filter of A I If 9xA 2 F then A(t) 2 F for some term t Define t ≡ s if and only if t = s 2 F : I Let D = Trm= ≡ I Let RD(t) iff R(t) 2 Σ0 D D D I Let MF = (D; R ; f ; c ) Define M = (W; ≤) I W = fMF j F is a prime filter of some Ag I MF ≤ MG if and only if G ⊆ F 19 / 29 A curiosity? (x)(A ! B) = (x)A ! (x)B if and only if (9xA(x))^B = 9x(A(x)^B) (x)(A n B) = (x)A n (x)B if and only if 8x(A(x) _ B) = (8xA(x)) _ B 20 / 29 Witnesses, counterexamples and completeness Question Why witnesses and not counterexamples? Why not require that if 8xA(x) is falsified then A(t) is falsified for some t? Lemma 1. Assume that (9xA(x)) ^ B = 9x(A(x) ^ B) and let (F; I) be a disjoint filter-ideal pair. Then (F; I) can be expanded to a filter ideal pair (F ; I) such that for all 9xA(x) < I there exists some A(xn) < I for some n.
Recommended publications
  • The Corcoran-Smiley Interpretation of Aristotle's Syllogistic As
    November 11, 2013 15:31 History and Philosophy of Logic Aristotelian_syllogisms_HPL_house_style_color HISTORY AND PHILOSOPHY OF LOGIC, 00 (Month 200x), 1{27 Aristotle's Syllogistic and Core Logic by Neil Tennant Department of Philosophy The Ohio State University Columbus, Ohio 43210 email [email protected] Received 00 Month 200x; final version received 00 Month 200x I use the Corcoran-Smiley interpretation of Aristotle's syllogistic as my starting point for an examination of the syllogistic from the vantage point of modern proof theory. I aim to show that fresh logical insights are afforded by a proof-theoretically more systematic account of all four figures. First I regiment the syllogisms in the Gentzen{Prawitz system of natural deduction, using the universal and existential quantifiers of standard first- order logic, and the usual formalizations of Aristotle's sentence-forms. I explain how the syllogistic is a fragment of my (constructive and relevant) system of Core Logic. Then I introduce my main innovation: the use of binary quantifiers, governed by introduction and elimination rules. The syllogisms in all four figures are re-proved in the binary system, and are thereby revealed as all on a par with each other. I conclude with some comments and results about grammatical generativity, ecthesis, perfect validity, skeletal validity and Aristotle's chain principle. 1. Introduction: the Corcoran-Smiley interpretation of Aristotle's syllogistic as concerned with deductions Two influential articles, Corcoran 1972 and Smiley 1973, convincingly argued that Aristotle's syllogistic logic anticipated the twentieth century's systematizations of logic in terms of natural deductions. They also showed how Aristotle in effect advanced a completeness proof for his deductive system.
    [Show full text]
  • Does Reductive Proof Theory Have a Viable Rationale?
    DOES REDUCTIVE PROOF THEORY HAVE A VIABLE RATIONALE? Solomon Feferman Abstract The goals of reduction and reductionism in the natural sciences are mainly explanatory in character, while those in mathematics are primarily foundational. In contrast to global reductionist programs which aim to reduce all of mathematics to one supposedly “univer- sal” system or foundational scheme, reductive proof theory pursues local reductions of one formal system to another which is more jus- tified in some sense. In this direction, two specific rationales have been proposed as aims for reductive proof theory, the constructive consistency-proof rationale and the foundational reduction rationale. However, recent advances in proof theory force one to consider the viability of these rationales. Despite the genuine problems of foun- dational significance raised by that work, the paper concludes with a defense of reductive proof theory at a minimum as one of the principal means to lay out what rests on what in mathematics. In an extensive appendix to the paper, various reduction relations between systems are explained and compared, and arguments against proof-theoretic reduction as a “good” reducibility relation are taken up and rebutted. 1 1 Reduction and reductionism in the natural sciencesandinmathematics. The purposes of reduction in the natural sciences and in mathematics are quite different. In the natural sciences, one main purpose is to explain cer- tain phenomena in terms of more basic phenomena, such as the nature of the chemical bond in terms of quantum mechanics, and of macroscopic ge- netics in terms of molecular biology. In mathematics, the main purpose is foundational. This is not to be understood univocally; as I have argued in (Feferman 1984), there are a number of foundational ways that are pursued in practice.
    [Show full text]
  • Notes on Proof Theory
    Notes on Proof Theory Master 1 “Informatique”, Univ. Paris 13 Master 2 “Logique Mathématique et Fondements de l’Informatique”, Univ. Paris 7 Damiano Mazza November 2016 1Last edit: March 29, 2021 Contents 1 Propositional Classical Logic 5 1.1 Formulas and truth semantics . 5 1.2 Atomic negation . 8 2 Sequent Calculus 10 2.1 Two-sided formulation . 10 2.2 One-sided formulation . 13 3 First-order Quantification 16 3.1 Formulas and truth semantics . 16 3.2 Sequent calculus . 19 3.3 Ultrafilters . 21 4 Completeness 24 4.1 Exhaustive search . 25 4.2 The completeness proof . 30 5 Undecidability and Incompleteness 33 5.1 Informal computability . 33 5.2 Incompleteness: a road map . 35 5.3 Logical theories . 38 5.4 Arithmetical theories . 40 5.5 The incompleteness theorems . 44 6 Cut Elimination 47 7 Intuitionistic Logic 53 7.1 Sequent calculus . 55 7.2 The relationship between intuitionistic and classical logic . 60 7.3 Minimal logic . 65 8 Natural Deduction 67 8.1 Sequent presentation . 68 8.2 Natural deduction and sequent calculus . 70 8.3 Proof tree presentation . 73 8.3.1 Minimal natural deduction . 73 8.3.2 Intuitionistic natural deduction . 75 1 8.3.3 Classical natural deduction . 75 8.4 Normalization (cut-elimination in natural deduction) . 76 9 The Curry-Howard Correspondence 80 9.1 The simply typed l-calculus . 80 9.2 Product and sum types . 81 10 System F 83 10.1 Intuitionistic second-order propositional logic . 83 10.2 Polymorphic types . 84 10.3 Programming in system F ...................... 85 10.3.1 Free structures .
    [Show full text]
  • Proof Theory of Constructive Systems: Inductive Types and Univalence
    Proof Theory of Constructive Systems: Inductive Types and Univalence Michael Rathjen Department of Pure Mathematics University of Leeds Leeds LS2 9JT, England [email protected] Abstract In Feferman’s work, explicit mathematics and theories of generalized inductive definitions play a cen- tral role. One objective of this article is to describe the connections with Martin-L¨of type theory and constructive Zermelo-Fraenkel set theory. Proof theory has contributed to a deeper grasp of the rela- tionship between different frameworks for constructive mathematics. Some of the reductions are known only through ordinal-theoretic characterizations. The paper also addresses the strength of Voevodsky’s univalence axiom. A further goal is to investigate the strength of intuitionistic theories of generalized inductive definitions in the framework of intuitionistic explicit mathematics that lie beyond the reach of Martin-L¨of type theory. Key words: Explicit mathematics, constructive Zermelo-Fraenkel set theory, Martin-L¨of type theory, univalence axiom, proof-theoretic strength MSC 03F30 03F50 03C62 1 Introduction Intuitionistic systems of inductive definitions have figured prominently in Solomon Feferman’s program of reducing classical subsystems of analysis and theories of iterated inductive definitions to constructive theories of various kinds. In the special case of classical theories of finitely as well as transfinitely iterated inductive definitions, where the iteration occurs along a computable well-ordering, the program was mainly completed by Buchholz, Pohlers, and Sieg more than 30 years ago (see [13, 19]). For stronger theories of inductive 1 i definitions such as those based on Feferman’s intutitionic Explicit Mathematics (T0) some answers have been provided in the last 10 years while some questions are still open.
    [Show full text]
  • Proof Theory for Modal Logic
    Proof theory for modal logic Sara Negri Department of Philosophy 00014 University of Helsinki, Finland e-mail: sara.negri@helsinki.fi Abstract The axiomatic presentation of modal systems and the standard formula- tions of natural deduction and sequent calculus for modal logic are reviewed, together with the difficulties that emerge with these approaches. Generaliza- tions of standard proof systems are then presented. These include, among others, display calculi, hypersequents, and labelled systems, with the latter surveyed from a closer perspective. 1 Introduction In the literature on modal logic, an overall skepticism on the possibility of developing a satisfactory proof theory was widespread until recently. This attitude was often accompanied by a belief in the superiority of model-theoretic methods over proof- theoretic ones. Standard proof systems have been shown insufficient for modal logic: Natural deduction presentations of even the most basic modal logics present difficulties that have been resolved only partially, and the same has happened with sequent calculus. These traditional proof system have failed to meet in a satisfactory way such basic requirements as analyticity and normalizability of formal derivations. Therefore alternative proof systems have been developed in recent years, with a lot of emphasis on their relative merits and on applications. We review first the axiomatic presentations of modal systems and the standard formulations of natural deduction and sequent calculus for modal logic, and the difficulties that emerge with
    [Show full text]
  • The Relative Consistency of the Axiom of Choice — Mechanized Using Isabelle/ZF (Extended Abstract)
    The Relative Consistency of the Axiom of Choice | Mechanized Using Isabelle/ZF (Extended Abstract) Lawrence C. Paulson Computer Laboratory, University of Cambridge, England [email protected] G¨odel[3] published a monograph in 1940 proving a highly significant the- orem, namely that the axiom of choice (AC) and the generalized continuum hypothesis (GCH) are consistent with respect to the other axioms of set theory. This theorem addresses the first of Hilbert's famous list of unsolved problems in mathematics. I have mechanized this work [8] using Isabelle/ZF [5, 6]. Obvi- ously, the theorem's significance makes it a tempting challenge; the proof also has numerous interesting features. It is not a single formal assertion, as most theorems are. G¨odel[3, p. 33] states it as follows, using Σ to denote the axioms for set theory: What we shall prove is that, if a contradiction from the axiom of choice and the generalized continuum hypothesis were derived in Σ, it could be transformed into a contradiction obtained from the axioms of Σ alone. G¨odelpresents no other statement of this theorem. Neither does he introduce a theory of syntax suitable for reasoning about transformations on proofs, surely because he considers it to be unnecessary. G¨odel'swork consists of several different results which, taken collectively, express the relative consistency of the axiom the choice. The concluding inference takes place at the meta-level and is not formalized. Standard proofs use meta- level reasoning extensively. G¨odelwrites [3, p. 34], However, the only purpose of these general metamathematical consid- erations is to show how the proofs for theorems of a certain kind can be accomplished by a general method.
    [Show full text]
  • Combinatorial Proofs and Decomposition Theorems for First
    Combinatorial Proofs and Decomposition Theorems for First-order Logic Dominic J. D. Hughes Lutz Straßburger Jui-Hsuan Wu Logic Group Inria, Equipe Partout Ecole Normale Sup´erieure U.C. Berkeley Ecole Polytechnique, LIX France USA France Abstract—We uncover a close relationship between combinato- rial and syntactic proofs for first-order logic (without equality). ax ⊢ pz, pz Whereas syntactic proofs are formalized in a deductive proof wk system based on inference rules, a combinatorial proof is a ax ⊢ pw, pz, pz ⊢ p,p wk syntax-free presentation of a proof that is independent from any wk ⊢ pw, pz, pz, ∀y.py set of inference rules. We show that the two proof representations ⊢ p,q,p ∨ ∨ ax ⊢ pw, pz, pz ∨ (∀y.py) are related via a deep inference decomposition theorem that ⊢ p ∨ q,p ⊢ p,p ∃ ∧ ⊢ pw, pz, ∃x.(px ∨ (∀y.py)) establishes a new kind of normal form for syntactic proofs. This ⊢ (p ∨ q) ∧ p,p,p ∀ yields (a) a simple proof of soundness and completeness for first- ctr ⊢ pw, ∀y.py, ∃x.(px ∨ (∀y.py)) ⊢ (p ∨ q) ∧ p,p ∨ order combinatorial proofs, and (b) a full completeness theorem: ∨ ⊢ pw ∨ (∀y.py), ∃x.(px ∨ (∀y.py)) ⊢ ((p ∨ q) ∧ p) ∨ p ∃ every combinatorial proof is the image of a syntactic proof. ⊢ ∃x.(px ∨ (∀y.py)), ∃x.(px ∨ (∀y.py)) ctr ⊢ ∃x.(px ∨ (∀y.py)) I. INTRODUCTION First-order predicate logic is a cornerstone of modern logic. ↓ ↓ Since its formalisation by Frege [1] it has seen a growing usage in many fields of mathematics and computer science. Upon the development of proof theory by Hilbert [2], proofs became first-class citizens as mathematical objects that could be studied on their own.
    [Show full text]
  • Topics in the Theory of Recursive Functions
    SETS, MODELS, AND PROOFS: TOPICS IN THE THEORY OF RECURSIVE FUNCTIONS A Dissertation Presented to the Faculty of the Graduate School of Cornell University in Partial Fulfillment of the Requirements for the Degree of Doctor of Philosophy by David R. Belanger August 2015 This document is in the public domain. SETS, MODELS, AND PROOFS: TOPICS IN THE THEORY OF RECURSIVE FUNCTIONS David R. Belanger, Ph.D. Cornell University We prove results in various areas of recursion theory. First, in joint work with Richard Shore, we prove a new jump-inversion result for ideals of recursively enu- merable (r.e.) degrees; this defeats what had seemed to be a promising tack on the automorphism problem for the semilattice R of r.e. degrees. Second, in work spanning two chapters, we calibrate the reverse-mathematical strength of a number of theorems of basic model theory, such as the Ryll-Nardzewski atomic-model theorem, Vaught's no-two-model theorem, Ehrenfeucht's three-model theorem, and the existence theorems for homogeneous and saturated models. Whereas most of these are equivalent over RCA0 to one of RCA0, WKL0, ACA0, as usual, we also uncover model-theoretic statements with exotic complexities such as :WKL0 _ 0 ACA0 and WKL0 _ IΣ2. Third, we examine the possible weak truth table (wtt) degree spectra of count- able first-order structures. We find several points at which the wtt- and Turing- degree cases differ, notably that the most direct wtt analogue of Knight's di- chotomy theorem does not hold. Yet we find weaker analogies between the two, including a new trichotomy theorem for wtt degree spectra in the spirit of Knight's.
    [Show full text]
  • What Is Mathematical Logic? a Survey
    What is mathematical logic? A survey John N. Crossley1 School of Computer Science and Software Engineering, Monash University, Clayton, Victoria, Australia 3800 [email protected] 1 Introduction What is mathematical logic? Mathematical logic is the application of mathemat- ical techniques to logic. What is logic? I believe I am following the ancient Greek philosopher Aristotle when I say that logic is the (correct) rearranging of facts to find the information that we want. Logic has two aspects: formal and informal. In a sense logic belongs to ev- eryone although we often accuse others of being illogical. Informal logic exists whenever we have a language. In particular Indian Logic has been known for a very long time. Formal (often called, ‘mathematical’) logic has its origins in ancient Greece in the West with Aristotle. Mathematical logic has two sides: syntax and semantics. Syntax is how we say things; semantics is what we mean. By looking at the way that we behave and the way the world behaves, Aris- totle was able to elicit some basic laws. His style of categorizing logic led to the notion of the syllogism. The most famous example of a syllogism is All men are mortal Socrates is a man [Therefore] Socrates is mortal Nowadays we mathematicians would write this as ∀x(Man(x) → Mortal (x)) Man(S) (1) Mortal (S) One very general form of the above rule is A (A → B) (2) B otherwise know as modus ponens or detachment: the A is ‘detached’ from the formula (A → B) leaving B. This is just one example of a logical rule.
    [Show full text]
  • Constructive Zermelo-Fraenkel Set Theory, Power Set, and the Calculus of Constructions
    This is a repository copy of Constructive zermelo-fraenkel set theory, power set, and the calculus of constructions. White Rose Research Online URL for this paper: http://eprints.whiterose.ac.uk/75182/ Book Section: Rathjen, M (2012) Constructive zermelo-fraenkel set theory, power set, and the calculus of constructions. In: Dybjer, P, Lindström, S, Palmgren, E and Sundholm, G, (eds.) Epistemology versus ontology: Essays on the philosophy and foundations of mathematics in honour of Per Martin-Löf. Logic, Epistemology, and the Unity of Science, 27 . Springer , Dordrecht, Netherlands , 313 - 349. ISBN 9789400744356 https://doi.org/10.1007/978-94-007-4435-6 Reuse Unless indicated otherwise, fulltext items are protected by copyright with all rights reserved. The copyright exception in section 29 of the Copyright, Designs and Patents Act 1988 allows the making of a single copy solely for the purpose of non-commercial research or private study within the limits of fair dealing. The publisher or other rights-holder may allow further reproduction and re-use of this version - refer to the White Rose Research Online record for this item. Where records identify the publisher as the copyright holder, users can verify any specific terms of use on the publisher’s website. Takedown If you consider content in White Rose Research Online to be in breach of UK law, please notify us by emailing [email protected] including the URL of the record and the reason for the withdrawal request. [email protected] https://eprints.whiterose.ac.uk/ Constructive Zermelo-Fraenkel Set Theory, Power Set, and the Calculus of Constructions Michael Rathjen∗ Department of Pure Mathematics, University of Leeds Leeds LS2 9JT, United Kingdom [email protected] May 4, 2012 Abstract Full intuitionistic Zermelo-Fraenkel set theory, IZF, is obtained from constructive Zermelo- Fraenkel set theory, CZF, by adding the full separation axiom scheme and the power set axiom.
    [Show full text]
  • Power Kripke–Platek Set Theory and the Axiom of Choice
    This is a repository copy of Power Kripke–Platek set theory and the axiom of choice. White Rose Research Online URL for this paper: http://eprints.whiterose.ac.uk/155300/ Version: Accepted Version Article: Rathjen, M (2020) Power Kripke–Platek set theory and the axiom of choice. Journal of Logic and Computation. ISSN 0955-792X https://doi.org/10.1093/logcom/exaa020 © the Author(s) 2020. Published by Oxford University Press. All rights reserved. This is an author produced version of a paper published in Journal of Logic and Computation. Uploaded in accordance with the publisher's self-archiving policy. Reuse Items deposited in White Rose Research Online are protected by copyright, with all rights reserved unless indicated otherwise. They may be downloaded and/or printed for private study, or other acts as permitted by national copyright laws. The publisher or other rights holders may allow further reproduction and re-use of the full text version. This is indicated by the licence information on the White Rose Research Online record for the item. Takedown If you consider content in White Rose Research Online to be in breach of UK law, please notify us by emailing [email protected] including the URL of the record and the reason for the withdrawal request. [email protected] https://eprints.whiterose.ac.uk/ Power Kripke-Platek set theory and the axiom of choice Michael Rathjen Department of Pure Mathematics, University of Leeds Leeds LS2 9JT, England, [email protected] Abstract Whilst Power Kripke-Platek set theory, KP(P), shares many prop- erties with ordinary Kripke-Platek set theory, KP, in several ways it behaves quite differently from KP.
    [Show full text]
  • Lectures on Proof Theory
    Lectures on Proof Theory W. W. Tait [x3. of these lecture notes, on Derivability of induction, is defective. I hope to revise it soon.] 1 Chapter 1 History Proof theory was created early in the 20th century by David Hilbert to prove the consistency of the ordinary methods of reasoning used in mathematics| in arithmetic (number theory), analysis and set theory. Already in his famous \Mathematical problems" of 1900 [Hilbert, 1900] he raised, as the second problem, that of proving the consistency of the arithmetic of the real num- bers. In 1904, in \On the foundations of logic and arithmetic" [Hilbert, 1905], he for the first time initiated his own program for proving consistency. 1.1 Consistency Whence his concern for consistency? The history of the concept of consis- tency in mathematics has yet to be written; but there are some things we can mention. There is of course a long tradition of skepticism. For example Descartes considered the idea we are deceived by a malicious god and that the simplest arithmetical truths might be inconsistent|but that was simply an empty skepticism. On the other hand, as we now know, in view of G¨odel'sincom- pleteness theorems, there is no relevant sense in which we can refute it. Surely, if we are to judge by how long it took for the various successive extensions of the number system|zero and the negative numbers, and the complex numbers|to be accepted throughout the mathematical community, we have to believe that they, each in their turn, raised concerns about con- sistency (though at least some of the resistance to them simply resulted from the lack of immediate empirical meaning).
    [Show full text]