Searchable PDF Format

Total Page:16

File Type:pdf, Size:1020Kb

Searchable PDF Format X(= *JfrRelscr)tl c*.**"-* 'l'beodore )izerman DIALECTI CAL MATERIATI$M alrdtheHIST0RY 0f Ptllt0s0PHY ESSAYS ON THE HISTORY OF PHITOSOPHY EE Progrex PrfiI i t he rc N ucou Trrnrlrtod lrom tho f,urtlan by Dmltrt Eeltavskg col{tEtvls Dodgnod bY Vadlm Kulethou ' Page T. Oftaepuar Inl,roduction t5 E M AT JII43 M AI4AJI ttTI4rIECIt[fi !]PI,IA ,t IA IICT OPI4fr @IIJIOCOOI4I4 I'IIOI]LEMS OF METHOD IN THE HISTORY OF PHILOSOPHY Ha aruanufrcnot a,aufre t7 Ihe.History oI ?hilosophy-the Development of philo- sollrcal tlrowledge . l9 Ilialectical Materillism and Hegel's phiiosoply' oi in.' Histo_ryof Philosophy. .... 4t A Contribution to the Critique of the Latest pluralistic Concept of the History of Philosoohv 62 'l'ho Dialectical-Materialist View of " ttre philosophical !yqlom 83 l.'}hilosophy and Everyday Consoiousness . 100 2 I)IALIJ.CTICAL MATERIALISM AND DIALECTICAL IDEAL IgM ttg lmrnrnuoltmnrnnuol Kaut and l?th-Century philojophicalphilosophical Ration_ tlhtrr t2t I(ant'r Dootrlno o[ "Thlnge ti thenjetvos;' and ilou-;o; 136 I'ho l)lalootloal trtoailrmif Johann Gb*iiel-ricnte l-.-l 154 I,lrlloroplry of tho powei of neas-on . 'l'holLofot'; .- tgt Soolll Morinlhc of Hecel' 204 Dlaloctlcal Matoriafism anil' (Jnlvorsality tlthe Hegeliin-Concept of ihd of Practice . 'of' 22!. Lonin.on ihe .Hegelian ioncept the'Coiutia'enie'oi ulalocttcs,_ Logic and Epistemology-Dialectic.il- . - 242 Dialoctical Miterialism,'Oiat.oticifMaterialism. IaeaUsm'ldcrti"- andonrt Conrem_nan+aa porary Coutem- @ I,Iagatelrcrno <Mncur,l, 1979 Bourgeois Consciousness (In Lieu of a Conctirii6ul 26t IIII]LIOGRAPHY . 276 English translation @ Progress Publishers 1982 NAMD INDEX. 2fi SIIBJECT INDEX Prtnted in the Unton ol Souiet Socialist Republi,cs 283 ouffffi38-82 0302000000 INTRODUCTION 'l'Itese essays on the history of philosophy deal, above nll with methodology. They also examine world outlook, Irocause a Marxist study of the history of philosophy must lnalyze the relation of dialectical materialism to the phi- losophy that preceded it. The Marxist approach to the development of pre-Marx- inn philosophy first of all singles out classical German plrilosophy, one of the theoretical sources of Marxism. 'l'herefore, this book poses a number of important although rrot yot sufficiently analyzed issues, related to the historical lspoct of the emergence and development of dialectical irlonlism, whose outstanding role as the precursor of dia- locl,ical materialism was repeatedly stressed by the found- lrs of Mnrxism. 'l'ltis book supplements my monographs Problems ol the lllatory ol Philosophy (Moscow, 1969; English translation prrbllxhorl in l{)73, German in 1962 and 1979, and French Irr 1tl7;l) nnd Malor Trends in Philosophy (Moscow, lll7l), rrnd dlflcusses issuos that wore not sufficiently lxnmlnorl ln tlrom. Oorrsoquontly, this book omits the top- icn wlrlch, nlt,hough very important, were discussed at Irrngth in thosc monographs. 'l'lro principal objective of this book is to use the study of cortain aspects of methodology and of dialectical ideal- ism to outline the fundamental role the dialectical-mate- rinlist theory of the history of philosophy plays in shap- ing the world outlook. A comprehensive analysis of that t,lroory is certainly relevant, and its importance transcends l,lrc bounds of a purely historical study of philosophy. As Frederick Engels emphasized, the history of theo- rt'tical thinking, and consequently the history of science, lrc inseparable from the history of philosophy. According l,o Ilngels, the rejection of philosophy as "the science of scicnces" that is opposed to specifig soiences is inseparable lrom r orlttorl cveluatlon ol the legacy of philosophy, process boo-auls I nocessary logical expression of the historical "the art ol worklng wlth coicoits is not iniorn deueloprnent knowledge-only because I am and ako h not givon witti ordinary overyday rrf tlrc of conscious- lrying to define the role of the history 9l philosophy in the .nets but req-uires roal thought,-iristory, and . ttrii ttiought simi- kngw larly haa ompirical ng,, old development of theoretical thinking. We a long not more andl not less pre-Marxian philosophers saw thal ompjrical natural l,liirt even the greatest of the scip,ncs. Only by learning to as- rro between the development of knowledge and the similate the results of the development of philosoffry arr- link past -it rlovclopment of the ability to think in concepts. For exam- ing- -the two and a half thousand years wiit rid ability exercise judgment (to itself on the one hand natural phiiosophy lrlr', Kant said that the to of any standing data the more general concepts and cat: apart from it, outside and above irrnke empirical fit it it, and bn- the othei ogories) was an inborn quality, and that no or hand also of its own limited method' of thought, which _education was inheritance tinining could make up for the absence of that essential its from English empiricism."-(8; 20) perfectly way his systeir Theoretical thinking essdntialty l,r'uit. frant's view fitted in the is firi"t<in! irr'"Lr".f,ts, rrnderestimated role of the history of science, partic'u- and it develops by perfecting conceptual-scientific the the sys- lnrly the history of philosophy. Had Kantian criticism been tem, creating new concepts caiegories. Theoreti- -by and capable of grasping the heuristic importance of the_ history cal thinLing operates with concepts greatly in -knowledge, that vary of would probably have concluded that quality. Some concepts register special qualities Kant iharalter- not exercise judgment but also the pro- istic of certain group objecls, qualities only the ability to a of the that are rluctive power imagination (whose role in cogqi- gJryped by sense perception and singled -emphasized)of the out by abstract l,ion he could be consciously developed only thinkin-g. Others-generalize processes and relationj perceived t,lrrough a critical and systematic study of the history of only through theoretical thinking. Stil1 others'have a strictly heuristic value-that science. is, they express operations While admitting that inborn intellectual abilities do by the perceiving subjoct and not the qrGhties of things or the general qualities oxist, Engels, unlike Kant, accords priority, to, the study of objective ieality. Such, for o[ it e history of culture, and particularly to example, is the concept of the infinitesimal in mathemat- hit--the ics. Another, conscious and scientifically sound study of the even more graphic example of a heuristic of the concept-that is, l,ory of cognitive thinking, especially the results one discharging an operational function- two and half thousand years of philosophy. Devel- is the identification abstraction l6gic. of i in This listing rrping concept his Dialectics ol Natare, Engels {,ypes of concepts from complete. this in - is far However, il is of" history philosophy-t-he enough to demonstrate conceptuai stresies that the stwd,y the of the nature of theoretical experience accumulated in the thinking and inevitable runderstanding of th; its links with the history of philos- philosophy's development-is truly a school of ophy and with the creative conceptual course of effort. itrint<ing. The lattei, as he put it, is an "innate Theoretical thinking is not confined ready-made l,heoretical to con- quality only as regards natural capacity. This natural oa- cepts. The actual study process d,euelops concepts:-limits it dif- pacity must be developed, improved, and for its imp_rove- ferentiates between them, binds them iogether, and than study of enriches them, unites them incnt there is as yet no other means the into definite systems, coordi- 42-43) Naturally, one must not nates, subordinates, extrapolates, generalizes lrrovious philosophy". (9; and develops iose sight of the fact that Engels wrote this when natural them, _etc. Nor_ does cognitive theoretical thinking stop Hence his Irere. Research discovers phenomena, seiencJ was still poorly developed theoretically. new laws and oblects century elapsed since the appear- of cognition, therefore presupposes "ns yet". The that has and it the formulation Nature has- wit- of new categorics even rrtrcc of Anti-Diihrireg and Dialectics ol and new systems of categories great advancei field, and they have played (within a specific field of study). n(lsscd in this nn important part in the development of philosophy, and I am speaking here about the d,euelopment ol concepts o[ [heoretical thinking in general, 0 (;' j" E- ir, ;; ,, . ',: l Engels described the great discoveries of natural science objective: that of revealing the laws that govern the_ d-evel- in the mid-l9th century (the discovery of the cell and its opment of the given sum-total of phenomena in a definite formation, the law of energy transformation, Darwin's lristorical frame,work laid down in the study. The latter theory of evolution) as revolutionary turning points in the case is thus a logical reconstruction of the process in ques- historical shaping of theoretical natural science and as l,ion. KarI Marx's Capital is a classic example. the scientiflc foundation of dialectical materialism. In this According to Engels, the logical method "is indeed noth- connection Engels formulated the law of the creative de- ing but thJhistoricil method, only stripped of the historical velopment of materialist philosophy: "With each epoch- torm and diverting chance occurrences. The point whe-re making discovery even in the sphere of natural science it this history beginJ must also be the starting point of the [materialism] has to change its form; and after history also l,rain of thought, and its further progress will be simply was subjected to materialistic treatment, a new avenue of the reflection, . in alstract and theoretically consistent development was opened here too." (3; 3, 349) In the [orm, of the historical course. Though the reflection is early 20th century V. L Lenin in his Materialism and.
Recommended publications
  • Dietrich Tiedemann: La Psicología Del Niño Hace Doscientos Arios
    Dietrich Tiedemann: la psicología del niño hace doscientos arios JUAN DELVAL y JUAN CARLOS GÓMEZ Universidad Autónoma de Madrid ___........-"\ n..." Resumen Hace doscientos años que el filósofo alemán Dietrich Tiedemann publicó la primera descripción del desarrollo psicológico de un niño. En este trabajo se examinan los antecedentes de las observa- ciones de Tiedemann, así como el contexto en que se producen y los presupuestos filosóficos que las orientan. Se sugiere que en el trabajó de Tiedernann aparecen por vez primera importantes observaciones que se han convertido en temas centrales de la actual psicología del desarrollo. Se termina analizando la influencia posterior de esa obra y las razones que explican el impacto reduci- do que tuvo en los años siguientes a su publicación. Palabras clave: Diehich Tiedenzann, Psicología infantil, Historia de la Psicología del Desarrollo. Dietrich Tiedemann: Child Psychology two hundred years ago Abstract The German philosopher Dietrich Tiedemann published two hundred years ago Me first known description of Me psychological development of a child. In the present paper, Me antecedents of Me observations made by Tiedemann are examined as well as the context and philosophical pre- suppositions which guide the study. It is suggested that Tiedemann's record offers fir Me first time important observations which later became a central part of present-day developmental psychoj logy. Finally it is analyzed Me repercusion of thilz work in the science of its time and the reasons for its lirnited impact. Key words: Diehich Tiedemann, Chad Psychology, History of Developmental Psychology. Dirección de los autores: Universidad Autónoma de Madrid. Facultad de Psicología.
    [Show full text]
  • The Empiricist Critique of the Theoretical Philosophy Edited by Brigitte Sassen Table of Contents More Information
    Cambridge University Press 978-0-521-03764-8 - Kant’s Early Critics: The Empiricist Critique of the Theoretical Philosophy Edited by Brigitte Sassen Table of Contents More information Contents Acknowledgments page vii Frequently Cited Texts and Abbreviations ix Introduction: Major Trends in the Early Empiricist Reception of Kant’s Critical Philosophy 1 I. Feder/Garve and Garve The Go¨ttingen Review [Anonymous], Zugabe zu den Go¨ttingischen Anzeigen von gelehrten Sachen (January 19, 1782): 40–8 53 The Garve Review Christian Garve, ‘‘Critique of Pure Reason by Immanuel Kant’’ AdB supplements to vols. 37–52 (1783): 838–62. 59 II. The Transcendental Aesthetic Dietrich Tiedemann, ‘‘On the Nature of Metaphysics: An Examination of Professor Kant’s Principles – Against the Aesthetic’’ Hessische Beytra¨ge zur Gelehrsamkeit und Kunst 1 (1785), 113–30. 81 [Hermann Andreas Pistorius], ‘‘Elucidations of Professor Kant’s ‘Critique of Pure Reason,’ by Johann Schultze’’ AdB 66/1 (1786): 92–123. 93 Johann Georg Heinrich Feder, On Space and Causality: An Examination of the Kantian Philosophy, 1–64, 84*–91* 106 [Anonymous], ‘‘On Space and Causality: An Examination of the Kantian Philosophy by Johann Georg Heinrich Feder’’ ALZ (28 January 1788): 249–54. 127 Friedrich Gottlob Born, Investigation into the First Grounds of the Doctrine of the Senses, 87–92 133 III. Idealism Johann Georg Heinrich Feder, On Space and Causality: An Examination of the Kantian Philosophy, 61–83*, 114–18 139 J. C. G. Schaumann, On the Transcendental Aesthetic: A Critical Attempt, 131–75 155 Friedrich Heinrich Jacobi, ‘‘On Transcendental Idealism’’ David Hume u¨ber den Glauben oder Idealismus und Realismus, 209–30 169 v © Cambridge University Press www.cambridge.org Cambridge University Press 978-0-521-03764-8 - Kant’s Early Critics: The Empiricist Critique of the Theoretical Philosophy Edited by Brigitte Sassen Table of Contents More information Contents [Hermann Andreas Pistorius], ‘‘Critique of Pure Reason by Immanuel Kant’’ AdB 81/2 (1788): 343–54.
    [Show full text]
  • Kant’S EARLY CRITICS: the Empiricist Critique of The
    Cambridge University Press 978-0-521-03764-8 - Kant’s Early Critics: The Empiricist Critique of the Theoretical Philosophy Edited by Brigitte Sassen Frontmatter More information © Cambridge University Press www.cambridge.org Cambridge University Press 978-0-521-03764-8 - Kant’s Early Critics: The Empiricist Critique of the Theoretical Philosophy Edited by Brigitte Sassen Frontmatter More information KANT’S EARLY CRITICS The Empiricist Critique of the Theoretical Philosophy translated and edited by BRIGITTE SASSEN McMaster University © Cambridge University Press www.cambridge.org Cambridge University Press 978-0-521-03764-8 - Kant’s Early Critics: The Empiricist Critique of the Theoretical Philosophy Edited by Brigitte Sassen Frontmatter More information CAMBRIDGE UNIVERSITY PRESS Cambridge, New York, Melbourne, Madrid, Cape Town, Singapore, São Paulo Cambridge University Press The Edinburgh Building, Cambridge CB2 8RU, UK Published in the United States of America by Cambridge University Press, New York www.cambridge.org Information on this title: www.cambridge.org/9780521781671 © Brigitte Sassen 2000 This publication is in copyright. Subject to statutory exception and to the provisions of relevant collective licensing agreements, no reproduction of any part may take place without the written permission of Cambridge University Press. First published 2000 This digitally printed version 2007 A catalogue record for this publication is available from the British Library Library of Congress Cataloguing in Publication data Sassen, Brigitte, 1960– Kant’s early critics : the empiricist critique of the theoretical philosophy / Brigitte Sassen. p. cm. Companion volume to: Cambridge edition of the works of Immanuel Kant. Includes bibliographical references and index. ISBN 0-521-78167-1 1.
    [Show full text]
  • Notes for a Romantic Encyclopaedia Das Allgemeine Brouillon
    Novalis Notes for a Romantic Encyclopaedia Das Allgemeine Brouillon Translated, Edited, and with an Introduction by David W. Wood Notes for a Romantic Encyclopaedia SUNY series, Intersections: Philosophy and Critical Theory Rodolphe Gasché, editor Notes for a Romantic Encyclopaedia Das Allgemeine Brouillon Novalis Translated, Edited, and with an Introduction by David W. Wood State University of New York Press Published by State University of New York Press, Albany © 2007 State University of New York All rights reserved Printed in the United States of America No part of this book may be used or reproduced in any manner whatsoever without written permission. No part of this book may be stored in a retrieval system or transmitted in any form or by any means including electronic, electrostatic, magnetic tape, mechanical, photocopying, recording, or otherwise without the prior permission in writing of the publisher. For information, address State University of New York Press, 194 Washington Avenue, Suite 305, Albany, NY 12210-2384 Production by Judith Block Marketing by Michael Campochiaro Library of Congress Cataloging-in-Publication Data Novalis, 1772–1801. [Allgemeine Brouillon. English] Notes for a Romantic Encyclopaedia : Das Allgemeine Brouillon / Novalis ; translated, edited, and with an introduction by David W. Wood. p. cm. — (SUNY series, intersections: philosophy and critical theory) Includes bibliographical references and index. Translation of: Das Allgemeine Brouillon : Materialien zur Enzyklopäedistik 1798/99. ISBN-13: 978-0-7914-6973-6
    [Show full text]
  • Psychology As Natural Science
    University of Pennsylvania ScholarlyCommons IRCS Technical Reports Series Institute for Research in Cognitive Science September 1994 Remaking the Science of Mind: Psychology as Natural Science Gary Hatfield University of Pennsylvania, [email protected] Follow this and additional works at: https://repository.upenn.edu/ircs_reports Hatfield, Gary, "Remaking the Science of Mind: Psychology as Natural Science" (1994). IRCS Technical Reports Series. 159. https://repository.upenn.edu/ircs_reports/159 University of Pennsylvania Institute for Research in Cognitive Science Technical Report No. IRCS-94-13. This paper is posted at ScholarlyCommons. https://repository.upenn.edu/ircs_reports/159 For more information, please contact [email protected]. Remaking the Science of Mind: Psychology as Natural Science Abstract Psychology considered as a natural science began as Aristotelian “physics” or “natural philosophy” of the soul. C. Wolff placed psychology under metaphysics, coordinate with cosmology. Near the middle of the eighteenth century, Krueger, Godart, and Bonnet proposed approaching the mind with the techniques of the new natural science. At nearly the same time, Scottish thinkers placed psychology within moral philosophy, but distinguished its “physical” laws from properly moral laws (for guiding conduct). British and French visual theorists developed mathematically precise theories of size and distance perception; they created instruments to test these theories and to measure visual phenomena such as the duration of visual impressions. By the end of the century there was a flourishing discipline of empirical psychology in Germany, with professorships, textbooks, and journals. The practitioners of empirical psychology at this time typically were dualists who included mental phenomena within nature. Comments University of Pennsylvania Institute for Research in Cognitive Science Technical Report No.
    [Show full text]
  • John Locke in the German Enlightenment: an Interpretation Klaus P
    View metadata, citation and similar papers at core.ac.uk brought to you by CORE provided by Chapman University Digital Commons Chapman University Chapman University Digital Commons Philosophy Faculty Articles and Research Philosophy 1975 John Locke in the German Enlightenment: An Interpretation Klaus P. Fischer Chapman University Follow this and additional works at: http://digitalcommons.chapman.edu/philosophy_articles Part of the Ethics and Political Philosophy Commons, History of Philosophy Commons, and the Philosophy of Mind Commons Recommended Citation Fischer, Klaus P. "John Locke in the German enlightenment: an interpretation." Journal of the History of Ideas (1975): 431-446. DOI:10.2307/2708655 This Article is brought to you for free and open access by the Philosophy at Chapman University Digital Commons. It has been accepted for inclusion in Philosophy Faculty Articles and Research by an authorized administrator of Chapman University Digital Commons. For more information, please contact [email protected]. John Locke in the German Enlightenment: An Interpretation Comments This article was originally published in Journal of the History of Ideas in 1975. DOI: 10.2307/2708655 Copyright University of Pennsylvania Press This article is available at Chapman University Digital Commons: http://digitalcommons.chapman.edu/philosophy_articles/1 JOHN LOCKE IN THE GERMAN ENLIGHTENMENT: AN INTERPRETATION BY KLAUSP. FISCHER I. A favorite assumptionof Anglo-Americanscholarship, endlessly repeated in textbooks and monographs,is that Locke's philosophy triumphed in every nook and cranny of Western Europe. By im- plication,it is also assumed that other philosophicsystems, especially those of Descartes and Leibniz, withered away without much op- position. The reigningphilosophy of the Enlightenment,we are told, was that of Locke and his disciples in Englandand on the Continent.
    [Show full text]
  • The Reception of French Materialism in Enlightenment Germany, 1739-1789
    The Reception of French Materialism in Enlightenment Germany, 1739-1789 A thesis submitted to the University of Manchester for the degree of Doctor of Philosophy in the Faculty of Humanities 2013 Nick Treuherz School of Arts, Languages and Cultures Contents Abstract…………………………………………..….5 Declaration…………………………………………..6 Acknowledgments…………………………………..7 Introduction………………………………….............8 1. Bibliographical dissemination……………..….....43 2. Thinking matter………………………..………...83 3. Matter and movement……………..……………119 4. Immortality…………………………...………...144 5. Morality……………………………..………….175 Conclusion…………………………………..…….218 Appendix …………………………………………222 Bibliography………………………………….…...252 Word Count: 79,967 2 Works frequently cited: Editions and Abbreviations Unless otherwise stated, the following editions are used, abbreviated as follows: Correspondance Diderot Correspondance de Diderot, ed. by Georges Roth and Jean Varloot, 16 vols (Paris: Minuit, 1955-70). DFS Heinrich Friedrich Diez, Heinrich Friedrich Diez: Frühe Schriften (1772-1784), ed. by Manfred Voigts (Würzburg: Königshausen & Neumann, 2010). DPV Denis Diderot, Œuvres complètes de Diderot, ed. by Herbert Dieckmann, Jacques Proust, Jean Varloot and others, 33 vols (Paris: Hermann, 1975-). De l’esprit Claude Adrien Helvétius, De l’esprit (Paris: Durand, 1758). Making of the Modern World. Gale Group. Encyclopédie Encyclopédie ou dictionnaire raisonné des sciences, des arts et des métiers, ed. by Denis Diderot and Jean le Rond d’Alembert, [28 vols] (1751-72, repr. New York: Pergamon, 1969, 5 vols). GGA Göttingische Zeitungen von gelehrten Sachen (1739-53) and the Göttingsche Anzeigen von gelehrten Sachen (1753-1801). De l’homme Helvétius, De l’homme (Londres [The Hague]: 1773). Eighteenth Century Collections Online. Gale Group. Jubiläumsausgabe Moses Mendelssohn, Gesammelte Schriften. Jubiläumsausgabe, ed. by Fritz Bamberger and others, 25 vols (Berlin: Akademie, 1929-; Stuttgart-Bad Canstatt: Frommann-Holzboog, 1971-).
    [Show full text]
  • Gods and Giants: Cudworth's Platonic Metaphysics and His Ancient Theology
    British Journal for the History of Philosophy ISSN: 0960-8788 (Print) 1469-3526 (Online) Journal homepage: http://www.tandfonline.com/loi/rbjh20 Gods and giants: Cudworth’s platonic metaphysics and his ancient theology Douglas Hedley To cite this article: Douglas Hedley (2017) Gods and giants: Cudworth’s platonic metaphysics and his ancient theology, British Journal for the History of Philosophy, 25:5, 932-953, DOI: 10.1080/09608788.2017.1336702 To link to this article: http://dx.doi.org/10.1080/09608788.2017.1336702 Published online: 17 Jul 2017. Submit your article to this journal Article views: 41 View related articles View Crossmark data Full Terms & Conditions of access and use can be found at http://www.tandfonline.com/action/journalInformation?journalCode=rbjh20 Download by: [University of Cambridge] Date: 02 October 2017, At: 07:42 BRITISH JOURNAL FOR THE HISTORY OF PHILOSOPHY, 2017 VOL. 25, NO. 5, 932–953 https://doi.org/10.1080/09608788.2017.1336702 ARTICLE Gods and giants: Cudworth’s platonic metaphysics and his ancient theology Douglas Hedley Clare College, Cambridge, UK ABSTRACT The Cambridge Platonists are modern thinkers and the context of seventeenth- century Cambridge science is an inalienable and decisive part of their thought. Cudworth’s interest in ancient theology, however, seems to conflict with the progressive aspect of his philosophy. The problem of the nature, however, of this ‘Platonism’ is unavoidable. Even in his complex and recondite ancient theology Cudworth is motivated by philosophical considerations, and his legacy among philosophers in the eighteenth and nineteenth centuries should not be overlooked. In particular we will draw on the scholarship of the German Egyptologist Jan Assmann in order to reassess the significance of Cudworth’s theory of religion for later philosophical developments.
    [Show full text]
  • Introduction
    Cambridge University Press 978-0-521-03764-8 - Kant’s Early Critics: The Empiricist Critique of the Theoretical Philosophy Edited by Brigitte Sassen Excerpt More information Introduction Major Trends in the Early Empiricist Reception of Kant’s Critical Philosophy There can be no doubt that the initial reception of the Critique of Pure Reason was quite different from what Kant had expected and hoped for. His correspondence from 1781 and 1782 clearly demonstrates that he had hoped, perhaps expected, that certain of his contemporaries, par- ticularly Mendelssohn and Tetens, would subject the work to serious study and that they would ultimately endorse it.1 Nothing, however, was to be heard from Johann Tetens, and Moses Mendelssohn soon ‘‘put the book aside,’’ citing age and ill health.2 Even worse, not only was there no word from Mendelssohn and Tetens, in 1781 there was no word from anyone, aside, that is, from the obligatory announce- ments and short summaries gleaned mostly from the Table of Con- tents, certainly not from serious study.3 And although 1782 did bring the first review, this was, as is well known, the Go¨ttingen or Feder/ Garve review,4 hardly the sort of assessment that Kant had hoped for. His bitter disappointment is evident in his efforts to involve others, notably Johann Schultz5 and even Mendelssohn,6 in the review and evaluation of the work, as it is evident also in his very public reaction to the Go¨ttingen review in the Prolegomena Appendix. But Kant’s disappointment was premature. For after the initial, per- haps stunned, silence, reviews of and even commentaries on the critical philosophy began to appear in ever increasing numbers, so much so that by the mid 1780s Kant criticism had become a striving concern.
    [Show full text]
  • John Locke in the German Enlightenment: an Interpretation Klaus P
    Chapman University Chapman University Digital Commons Philosophy Faculty Articles and Research Philosophy 1975 John Locke in the German Enlightenment: An Interpretation Klaus P. Fischer Chapman University Follow this and additional works at: http://digitalcommons.chapman.edu/philosophy_articles Part of the Ethics and Political Philosophy Commons, History of Philosophy Commons, and the Philosophy of Mind Commons Recommended Citation Fischer, Klaus P. "John Locke in the German enlightenment: an interpretation." Journal of the History of Ideas (1975): 431-446. DOI:10.2307/2708655 This Article is brought to you for free and open access by the Philosophy at Chapman University Digital Commons. It has been accepted for inclusion in Philosophy Faculty Articles and Research by an authorized administrator of Chapman University Digital Commons. For more information, please contact [email protected]. John Locke in the German Enlightenment: An Interpretation Comments This article was originally published in Journal of the History of Ideas in 1975. DOI: 10.2307/2708655 Copyright University of Pennsylvania Press This article is available at Chapman University Digital Commons: http://digitalcommons.chapman.edu/philosophy_articles/1 JOHN LOCKE IN THE GERMAN ENLIGHTENMENT: AN INTERPRETATION BY KLAUSP. FISCHER I. A favorite assumptionof Anglo-Americanscholarship, endlessly repeated in textbooks and monographs,is that Locke's philosophy triumphed in every nook and cranny of Western Europe. By im- plication,it is also assumed that other philosophicsystems, especially those of Descartes and Leibniz, withered away without much op- position. The reigningphilosophy of the Enlightenment,we are told, was that of Locke and his disciples in Englandand on the Continent. Some have gone so far as to claim that Locke's "influencepervades the eighteenthcentury with an almost scripturalauthority."' Examining the philosophic traditions of individual nations in eighteenth-centuryEurope, one encountersa slightlydifferent picture.
    [Show full text]
  • Chapter 3 Reinhold’S Way to Kant
    VU Research Portal The Usefulness of the Kantian Philosophy Marx, K.J. 2010 document version Publisher's PDF, also known as Version of record Link to publication in VU Research Portal citation for published version (APA) Marx, K. J. (2010). The Usefulness of the Kantian Philosophy: How Karl Leonhard Reinhold's Commitment to Enlightenment Influenced His Reception of Kant. General rights Copyright and moral rights for the publications made accessible in the public portal are retained by the authors and/or other copyright owners and it is a condition of accessing publications that users recognise and abide by the legal requirements associated with these rights. • Users may download and print one copy of any publication from the public portal for the purpose of private study or research. • You may not further distribute the material or use it for any profit-making activity or commercial gain • You may freely distribute the URL identifying the publication in the public portal ? Take down policy If you believe that this document breaches copyright please contact us providing details, and we will remove access to the work immediately and investigate your claim. E-mail address: [email protected] Download date: 24. Sep. 2021 chapter 3 Reinhold’s way to Kant In the first and second chapters we have established that Reinhold’s early philosophical in- terests were closely connected to the life he led as a monk, and then as a Freemason and an Aufklärer. Although in this early period he did not put forward a systematic philosophical theory of his own, his reviews, articles and speeches are by no means a random collec- tion of opinions.
    [Show full text]
  • Kant and Tetens on Transcendental Philosophy
    Western University Scholarship@Western Electronic Thesis and Dissertation Repository 10-10-2018 9:30 AM Kant and Tetens on Transcendental Philosophy Richard D. Creek The University of Western Ontario Supervisor Dyck, Corey W. The University of Western Ontario Graduate Program in Philosophy A thesis submitted in partial fulfillment of the equirr ements for the degree in Doctor of Philosophy © Richard D. Creek 2018 Follow this and additional works at: https://ir.lib.uwo.ca/etd Part of the History of Philosophy Commons Recommended Citation Creek, Richard D., "Kant and Tetens on Transcendental Philosophy" (2018). Electronic Thesis and Dissertation Repository. 5818. https://ir.lib.uwo.ca/etd/5818 This Dissertation/Thesis is brought to you for free and open access by Scholarship@Western. It has been accepted for inclusion in Electronic Thesis and Dissertation Repository by an authorized administrator of Scholarship@Western. For more information, please contact [email protected]. Abstract This dissertation examines the significance of Johann Nikolas Tetens, a German em- piricist philosopher working in the 1770’s, to the theoretical philosophy of Immanuel Kant. I begin by examining Tetens’ discussion of philosophical methodology in his 1775 essay Uber¨ die allgemeine speculativische Philosophie. I make the case that Tetens’ criticism of the methodology of the Scottish common sense philosophers and his subsequent attempt to incorporate what he takes to be their valuable insights into the approach of the broadly Wolffian philosophical tradition provides important context for interpreting Kant’s method- ology in the Critique of Pure Reason. I then examine two different cases of Tetens’ apply- ing this methodology in his 1777 text Philosophische Versuche ¨uberdie menschliche Natur und ihre Entwickelung.
    [Show full text]