St. Augustine's Epistemology and the Education Process | 139
Total Page:16
File Type:pdf, Size:1020Kb
St. Augustine's epistemology and the education process | 139 ST. AUGUSTINE'S EPISTEMOLOGY AND THE EDUCATION PROCESS Abstract St. Augustine's epistemology can be seen in his doctrine of divine illumination, where he distinguishes knowledge got through the senses, inferior reason, and superior reason. Augustine was interested in education and he was a teacher very interested in how learners get the best knowledge from the teaching and learning process. He held that love of God, expressed through love of neighbour was to be the bedrock of the teacher-pupil relationship, but he did not clearly state the bridge or connecting link between the teaching and learning process. So, through critical analysis. This essay intends to explore Augustine's divine illumination theory as the missing link between teaching and learning. It employs the method of exposition and critical analysis. Keywords: St. Augustine, Epistemology, Basis, Teaching, Learning, Divine Illumination Introduction History has it that Aurelius Augustine, popularly known as Saint Augustine or Augustine, the Bishop of Hippo, was born in A.D. 354 at Thagaste, in North Africa. Thagaste was a town forty-five miles south of Hippo in the Roman province of Numidia, which is the current Algeria. Augustine's father was Patricius (a pagan), and his mother was Monica (a Christian). Through his mother's persistence in pressuring Augustine to become a Christian, Augustine ended up becoming a Christian, and through his writings a rich intellectual 140 | Ekpoma Review, Volume. 5 No. 1., 2019 foundation of Christianity was established in the West. Augustine became enthused about philosophy through his reading of Cicero's Hortensius, when he went to Carthage for further studies in his late teens. Then he taught rhetoric in Carthage and later in Rome and Milan. As a thinker, Augustine was more of a restless seeker than a systematic thinker. He restlessly sought to unravel the problem of evil, which may be said to have characterized his intellectual and moral struggle in life. This restless search brought Augustine to romance briefly with the dualistic philosophy of Manichaeanism, and then dived headlong into the Neoplatonic philosophy of Plotinus. To bring a solution to his struggle with the problem of evil, Augustine synthesized the ideas of Neoplatonists with Christianity; upholding the teachings of the Bible but equally realizing that broad education was needed to maintain these teachings in the intellectual and political climate of his time.1 For Augustine, the ultimate purpose for education is turning towards God, because in his analysis for the presence of evil, Augustine notes that evil is not a being but human exercise of the free will in rejecting God Who is the Ultimate Good.2 Augustine believes that education helps save humans from the self destructive path of rejecting God in human's exercise of the free will, and he dedicated himself to delivering a good number of teaching and learning aid to facilitate the education of humans. This point is presented by Raymond Canning thus: Augustine of Hippo offers a rich resource for philosophical, theological and pastoral reflection on teaching and learning. Already in December 386, four months or more before his baptism, he had proposed, in On Order 2,7,24-19,51, a program for education in the liberal arts, the object of which was the vision of beauty, the vision of God. Shortly afterwards, in his Soliloquies, he had explored the epistemological foundations of such a program, focusing on the highest of the liberal arts, i.e., philosophy, the subject matter of which for him was God and the soul. Then, in the late 380s, in the St. Augustine's epistemology and the education process | 141 dialogue with his son, Adeodatus, called The Teacher, he developed an accompanying theory of language and interpretation, a theory that would be further worked out and applied in his classic treatment of the interpretation of Scripture in On Christian Doctrine dating from the mid to late 390s. It is not surprising, therefore, that in 415-418 as he explores different mental analogies in his work, On the Trinity, he should draw attention also to the amor studentium, i.e., “the sort of love... that the studious have, that is people who do not yet know but still desire to know some branch of learning.... The more... the thing is known without being fully known, the more does the intelligence desire to know what remains.... The object of our inquiry is what it is that [someone] loves in that which he is studious to know.”3 Augustine placed education within the realm of the search for love, and indicates that education comes through the instrumentality of teaching and learning. Through teaching, the phenomenon to be known is exposed, while through learning, the exposed phenomenon is grasped. But a close consideration of the elements of teaching and learning in Augustine's philosophy of education may leave one asking: “Are the elements of teaching and learning in Augustine's philosophy of education parallel to themselves or do they have a point of convergence?” This paper argues that there is a point of convergence for the elements: teaching and learning, in Augustine's philosophy of education, and that point of convergence lies in Augustine's epistemology. But before digging deep into this, let us consider two philosophical trends that influenced Augustine. Platonic and Aristotelian Influence on Augustine Augustine is ordinarily considered to be a Platonist, and he even made allusion to the strong influence of Neoplatonism on him thus: “In the regular course of study I came upon the book of a certain 142 | Ekpoma Review, Volume. 5 No. 1., 2019 Cicero... that book of his contained an exhortation to philosophy. It was called Hortensius. In fact that book changed my mental attitude, and changed the character of my prayers to Thyself, O Lord.”4 Augustine held firmly to Neoplatonism and was pleasantly surprised by its unexpected agreement with Christian doctrine: Therein I read, not, indeed, in these very words, but quite the same thing, supported by means of many and manifold reasons, that: In the beginning was the Word and the Word was with God and the Word was God. Furthermore, I read that the soul of man, though it gives testimony of the light, is not itself the light, but the Word, God Himself, is the true light, that enlightens every man who comes into the world.... Again, I read there that the Word, God, was born not of the flesh, nor of blood, nor of the will of man, nor of the will of flesh, but of God.5 Neoplatonism offered Augustine the soft landing he needed to accept the Christian faith, yet retain his pagan literary culture. So Augustine belongs to the Platonic school of thought, but Robert C. Trundle notes that “Augustine is normally associated with Plato's essentialism rather than Aristotle's 'organismic' empiricism. But... both Aristotle and Plato presented paradigm metaphysical options. And an open-minded reading of Augustine's philosophical theology belies some mediation between them.”6 The metaphysics of Plato was attractive, especially to a thinker like Augustine, for the fact that it made a distinction between two realities together with a soul that knew eternal ideas, just as the Scripture made a distinction between unchanging spiritual reality and a changing corporeal reality. Yet, Plato's metaphysics loses its attractiveness in the face of the claim in the New Testament that all things will pass away, and that includes knowledge, leaving only Love (agape) that will endure forever. Also, the New Testament teaching of the resurrection of the body, which is ultimately connected to Love, cannot find a place in Platonism which regards the body as a 'dark' receptacle, obscuring St. Augustine's epistemology and the education process | 143 the cognitive 'light' of the soul. For these difficulties with Plato's metaphysics, an alternative is found in Aristotle's metaphysics, based on the fact that: ...it is easier for the later Greeks as well as for Augustine to embrace an Aristotelian paradigm in which the mind, without recourse to a pre-existing soul, distinguished immutable universal ideas from mutable objects. For one thing, this was a simpler thesis. For another, this thesis would give an omniscient God some possible role in illuminating such objects. Further, these objects qua unities of form and matter implied a unity of body and soul. Though the later implied the death of soul and body alike, it rendered a personal resurrection viable and significant. [But].... the significance of the resurrection was tainted by an Aristotelian view of a single reality that, while involving a cosmological principle of causation, proceeded ad infinitium into the past. Besides an infinite past conflicting with creatio ex nihilo, it further anchored in otherwise transcendent God in a single reality.7 Having pin-pointed the attractive and unattractive metaphysical options of Platonism and Aristotelianism, Tundle submits that “it is reasonable to suppose that Augustine limitedly embraced both. The Platonic ontology of two realities explained the transcendence of God as well as both an inferiority of corporeal reality and sin-laden human condition;”8 which reveals the inherent fault in human knowledge and self deception in wanting to use just only human knowledge to solve moral and political problems, while doing away with God. The Aristotelian epistemology explained the merciful immanence of God, despite its fruitless pursuits of godless utopias. It acknowledges the ordered and rationality at play in the world, and these tended towards empiricism, yet the medium of articulating them cannot solely be limited to bodily senses. This is in close 144 | Ekpoma Review, Volume. 5 No. 1., 2019 association with Augustine's claim in the On Free Choice of the Will, that persons “are forced to admit that the order and truth of numbers have nothing to do with the bodily senses;”9 a claim that is not meant to mean that the real mathematical ideas are to be found in another 'real world of ideas' but that mathematical ideas cannot just be merely explained out on the base of a materialist account of perception.