Establishing a Taxonomy of Natural Kinds Martin Carrier*

Total Page:16

File Type:pdf, Size:1020Kb

Establishing a Taxonomy of Natural Kinds Martin Carrier* What is Right with the Miracle Argument: Establishing a Taxonomy of Natural Kinds Martin Carrier* IT CERTAINLY strikes us as one of the most remarkable types of scientific achievement when apparently disparate phenomena are unified theoretically. What appeared to be disparate to the untutored eye turns out to arise from the same underlying mechanism and thus to be identical in kind. When a door slams because the windows are open and it is windy outside, this happens due to the same cause and according to the same mechanism that makes a plane lift off the ground. The prima facie conclusion is that science succeeds in going beyond the specious distinctions of the senses. It teaches us what things are truly alike. My aim in this paper is to examine the viability of this popular view. And the result will be that the view is basically correct. More precisely, I will try to show, first, that in some distinguished cases science arguably manages to induce the right classification or taxonomy among the phenomena, and that, second, this is the only access to reality that science is justifiably able to gain. Accordingly, what I am aiming to do is to support a particular and compara- tively weak form of scientific realism. Scientific realism contends that claims about certain unobservable ‘items’ which emerge from the theoretical or experimental activity of scientists are literally true; these claims faithfully refer to what is, as it were, going on behind the scenes. There is some quarrel, however, about what these ‘items’ are legitimately supposed to be. The leading brand of this doctrine is theory- realism. According to this position, the successful theories of mature science are approximately true. That is, these theories correctly portray the not- directly-observable processes and mechanisms that make the phenomena occur the way they do. A more attenuated version of scientific realism is entity-realism. On the one hand, entity-realism is an immediate consequence of theory-realism. The truth of a theory implies the existence of its theoretical entities. On the other hand, there is also a more autonomous type of entity-realism which is advanced on the basis of experiment-centered arguments. In this version, entity-realism says that the capacity to manipulate certain unobservable entities, and, in parti- cular, to manipulate them in order to experiment on something else, gives *Center for Philosophy of Science, University of Konstanz, 78434 Konstanz, Germany. Received 29 October 1992; in revised form 10 February 1993. Stud. His. Phil. Sci., Vol. 24, No. 3, pp. 391-409, 1993. 0039-368 l/93 S6.00 + 0.00 Printed in Great Britain 0 1993. Pergamon Press Ltd 391 392 Studies in History and Philosophy of Science strong evidence for the real existence of these entities. Entity-realism is thus non-committal as to the (near) truth of the accepted scientific account of these entities. It is no theory’s entity but the experimenter’s entity to which actual existence is attributed. Belief in these entities does not imply belief in any one of the theories involved. An even more attenuated variant of realism, and the one I set out to support, is a realism of kinds. The claim is that science, at least on some rare and distinguished occasions, manages truthfully to forge links among the phenomena. Science sometimes succeeds in collecting phenomena into equiva- lence classes that reflect truly existing similarity relations among these pheno- mena. Whereas entity-realism implies a kind-realism, the reverse does not hold. It will be seen that commitment to the experimentally established entities entails commitment to the kind-structures they introduce. By contrast, the assumption that science is sometimes able to unveil true relations of similarity does not imply that the mechanisms employed to establish these relations and the entities they invoke reflect anything in nature. The argument comes in three steps. The first one is introductory. I sketch the notion of ‘natural kinds’ and show, using some examples from the history of science, that the structure of natural kinds is theory-dependent and indeed changes in the course of scientific progress. This finding implies that a naive form of a realism of kinds is untenable empirically. In the second step I consider the experimental route to natural kinds. The prima facie advantage of this alternative is that it seems to be exempt from the uncertainties and vicissitudes of theoretical reasoning. It turns out, however, that this position is likewise beset with a historical counter-example. Next comes, finally, the constructive step. I take up some earlier results of mine about the actual impact of the so-called ‘Miracle Argument’ in favor of scientific realism. The argument says that scientific realism is a necessary precondition for any explanation of scientific progress; it is the only choice for divesting progress of its miraculous aspects. I will argue that the Miracle Argument is insufficient for achieving its proper objective, namely, theory-realism, and that its real accom- plishment consists in showing that there are instances in which science provides us with a veridical portrait of relations of similarity as they prevail in nature. 1. Changing Patterns of Natural Kinds Every theory determines a classification among the objects or events it deals with; it induces a taxonomy into its universe of discourse. The laws of the theory are framed using certain descriptive predicates, and the relevant objects obey the laws in virtue of satisfying these predicates. A law thus serves to bind several objects together. It establishes a link of similarity among them by What is Right with the Miracle Argument 393 regarding them as instances of the same law. A so-created equivalence class of like objects is called a natural kind (cf. Fodor 1974, 101-102). Take, for example, the law: All electrons possess the elementary charge e. This law generates the natural kind ‘electron’ by quantifying over electrons. Electrons constitute a natural kind because there is a law that applies to them in virtue of their property of being electrons. Different laws may well pick the same natural kind. All further laws about electrons (such as: All electrons have a spin-value of )) obviously specify the same kind, namely, the class of electrons. This implies immediately that a theoretical change need not involve a change in the concomitant kind-structure. Different bodies of laws may select the same objects as being alike.’ The concept of natural kinds, as just circumscribed, is entirely non- committal as to the issue of scientific realism. Natural kinds are created by a corpus of laws irrespective of whether these laws are interpreted merely as useful but fictitious unifiers or are thought to refer to a theory-independent reality. Accordingly, natural kinds need not be truly natural, and the attribute ‘natural’ is, strictly speaking, a misnomer. In order to avoid the realist overtones the expression ‘scientific kinds’ has been proposed, but this proposal seems not to have gained acceptance. Thus I stick to the usual term, taking its non-committal sense to be understood. The reality of natural kinds constitutes the topic of the present investigation. The first response to this problem presumably is that we are surely entitled to interpret the taxonomy specified by present-day science realistically. After all, its laws have undergone a large number of severe tests; they are well- confirmed and thus deserve our confidence. And this confidence quite naturally extends to the taxonomy induced by these laws. Most of us would thus be inclined to reason as follows. Since present-day knowledge includes laws about electrons, electrons form a natural kind. For this reason, electrons are in reality of the same kind. Let’s examine the tenability of this assessment. A condition familiar from the discussion of scientific realism in general is the following retention requirement. For a theory component to be interpreted realistically, it is necessary that it be retained across scientific change. In particular, if earlier successful theories in the mature sciences are approxi- mately true, then the later even more successful theories in the same discipline ‘Note that ‘natural kind’ is used here as a technical term which does not wholly coincide with everyday usage. Biological species, for instance, though they are natural kinds in a rough and ready sense, hardly qualify as natural kinds in the present understanding. Kinds are derived from laws, and it is a matter of dispute in current philosophy of biology whether there are any specifically biological laws. In any event, a regularity of the sort ‘All ravens are black’ certainly does not count as a law of nature and thus does not give rise to the natural kind ‘raven’. 394 Studies in History and Philosophy of Science will preserve the earlier laws as limiting cases (cf. Putnam 1978, 2&24; Laudan 1981, 234240). Applied to natural kinds this means that the kind-structure of earlier well-confirmed theories should be reproduced ‘in the limit’ by the kind- structure of their respective successor theories. The intuition behind the retention condition is as follows. Once-successful but now-rejected theories in the mature sciences were in their lifetimes well- confirmed according to our present methodological criteria. If such theories turn out to be wrong on all counts, nothing prevents us from the meta- inductive inference that our present most cherished accounts are likewise doomed to complete failure and that nothing will remain from them in the end. If scientific realism is supposed to be a viable position, this meta-inductive move has to be blocked; and it can only be blocked by assuming that these earlier accounts indeed got something right (cf.
Recommended publications
  • Queries About Pragmatic Realism
    Queries about Pragmatic Realism ILKKA NIINILUOTO Sami Pihlström (2003, 351) has proposed pragmatism as a promising philosophy for dedicated “middle-ground-thinkers” who attempt to find reconciliatory standpoints between extreme and even incompatible positions. I have been fascinated by pragmatism as an inspiring movement which is able to interact with all other major philosophical schools. Therefore, we both have appreciated the dialogue between pragmatists and realists, with the hope that we could learn from our agreements and disagreements (see e.g. Pihlström, 2007; Niiniluoto, 2009). In this paper, both of these points are illustrated by the main problem of Pihlström’s doctoral thesis Structuring the World (1996): the possibility of pragmatic realism, taking seriously some of the key ideas of these two rival approaches. The topic is vast and deep, full of intricate philosophical and metaphilosophical issues, and in a single short article I can only take up some selected interesting examples: Pihlström’s own pragmatism with a Kantian turn, Rein Vihalemm’s practical realism, and Hasok Chang’s pluralist pragmatic realism. I cannot argue here who is right in these debates, but in the queries my own critical scientific realism (Niiniluoto, 1999) is used as a point of comparison. Pihlström: Pragmatic Realism with a Kantian turn Sami Pihlström’s 1996 doctoral thesis is a heroic attempt to reconcile neopragmatism (especially in the form developed by Hilary Putnam) and scientific realism (especially as defended by Ilkka Niiniluoto). Later he has become a leading expert in classical American pragmatism. With influences from the Wittgenstein scholar Heikki Kannisto’s lectures on Kant, Pihlström’s Naturalizing the Transcendental (2003) makes a Kantian turn in arguing that pragmatism offers a naturalized reconstruction of transcendental philosophy.
    [Show full text]
  • Realism for Realistic People
    Realism for Realistic People Author(s): Hasok Chang Source: Spontaneous Generations: A Journal for the History and Philosophy of Science, Vol. 9, No. 1 (2018) 31-34. Published by: The University of Toronto DOI: 10.4245/sponge.v9i1.27002 EDITORIALOFFICES Institute for the History and Philosophy of Science and Technology Room 316 Victoria College, 91 Charles Street West Toronto, Ontario, Canada M5S 1K7 [email protected] Published online at jps.library.utoronto.ca/index.php/SpontaneousGenerations ISSN 1913 0465 Founded in 2006, Spontaneous Generations is an online academic journal published by graduate students at the Institute for the History and Philosophy of Science and Technology, University of Toronto. There is no subscription or membership fee. Spontaneous Generations provides immediate open access to its content on the principle that making research freely available to the public supports a greater global exchange of knowledge. Focused Discussion Invited Paper Realism for Realistic People* Hasok Chang† Why should anyone care about the seemingly interminable philosophical debate concerning scientific realism? Shouldn’t we simply let go of it,in the spirit of Arthur Fine’s “natural ontological attitude” (NOA) (Fine 1986, chs. 7-8)? To a large extent I follow Fine, especially in relation to the endless arguments surrounding realist attempts to show that the impossible is somehow possible, that empirical science can really attain assured knowledge about what goes beyond experience. It is time to face the fact that we cannot know whether we have got the objective Truth about the World (even if such a formulation is meaningful). Realists go astray by persisting in trying to find a way around this fact, as do anti-realists in engaging with that obsession.
    [Show full text]
  • Philsoc Student Essay Prize, Trinity Term, 2020 – 1St Equal Prize
    Philsoc Student Essay Prize, Trinity term, 2020 – 1st Equal Prize Is Entity Realism the right way to think about Scientific Realism? By Jason Mahr Introduction Ian Hacking’s entity realism is influential in the scientific realism debate and maintains realism concerning manipulatable unobservable entities while retreating to an anti-realist position regarding the scientific theories and structures (Hacking 1982). It is an alternative compromise position to John Worrall’s structural realism, which makes the opposite concession. Entity realism improves the realist’s position in light of some anti-realist arguments but faces additional issues of its own. David Resnik criticises entity realism as entailing the same epistemological burdens as standard scientific realism. He argues Hacking must rely on a traditional success-of-science argument, entities depend on theories after all, and experimentation is not as theory-free as Hacking claims (Resnik 1994). Resnik’s concerns are legitimate, but he leaves out significant nuances. Martin Carrier instead cites past purported entities that have since been rejected while arguing for kind-realism (Carrier 1993). I cast Hacking’s arguments as better suited to a limited structural realism, which I then defend against Carrier’s claims. The result is a limited structural realism that can be supported by both Hacking and Carrier’s arguments. No-Miracles and Reliance on Theory Resnik’s first criticism is that entity realism, like standard scientific realism (SSR), relies on inference to the best explanation (IBE). It is useful to consider how the two arguments are different. A common response to the no-miracles argument (NMA) for SSR is that false theories can yield approximately true consequences.
    [Show full text]
  • Realism, Empiricism, and Causal Inquiry in International Relations: What's at Stake?
    CORE Metadata, citation and similar papers at core.ac.uk Provided by Central Archive at the University of Reading Realism, empiricism, and causal inquiry in International Relations: what©s at stake? Article Accepted Version Humphreys, A. (2018) Realism, empiricism, and causal inquiry in International Relations: what©s at stake? European Journal of International Relations. ISSN 1460-3713 doi: https://doi.org/10.1177/1354066118759179 Available at http://centaur.reading.ac.uk/74724/ It is advisable to refer to the publisher's version if you intend to cite from the work. To link to this article DOI: http://dx.doi.org/10.1177/1354066118759179 Publisher: Sage All outputs in CentAUR are protected by Intellectual Property Rights law, including copyright law. Copyright and IPR is retained by the creators or other copyright holders. Terms and conditions for use of this material are defined in the End User Agreement . www.reading.ac.uk/centaur CentAUR Central Archive at the University of Reading Reading's research outputs online Realism, empiricism, and causal inquiry in International Relations – what’s at stake? Adam R. C. Humphreys (University of Reading) European Journal of International Relations (forthcoming – accepted Jan 2018) AUTHOR FINAL VERSION Alexander Wendt argued thirty years ago that a commitment to the reality of ‘unobservable generative structures’ would open up new avenues of causal inquiry in International Relations [IR] (1987: 350). This view has since been further elaborated (see Wendt 1999; Patomäki and Wight 2000; Patomäki
    [Show full text]
  • Reference, Success and Entity Realism
    Reference, Success and Entity Realism Howard Sankey (School of Historical and Philosophical Studies, University of Melbourne) [email protected] 1. Introduction According to scientific realism, the aim of scientific inquiry is to discover the truth about observable and unobservable aspects of a mind-independent, objective reality. We may be confident that science has made considerable progress toward this aim because of the success of science. For the best explanation of the success of science is that the theories proposed by scientists increasingly approximate to the truth, and that contemporary theories are closer to the truth than the earlier theories which they have replaced. Absent a better explanation of the success of science, we should adopt the realist explanation of success as the correct interpretation of science. But scientific realism is not uncontroversial. A number of anti-realists have criticized scientific realism in respect of the role played by truth in the realist’s account of science. Larry Laudan and Bas van Fraassen provide two well-known examples of such anti-realist critics. Laudan (1981) objects to the realist’s abductive argument that the best explanation of the success of science is that its theories are true or approximately true, and that the terms used by the theories genuinely refer. For his part, Fraassen (1980) argues that empirical adequacy rather than truth should be seen as the aim of science. Scientific realists respond to the anti-realist attack in various ways. One reaction is to emphasize reality rather than truth. A number of philosophers suggest that scientific realism is open to anti-realist attack because it places undue emphasis on the truth of theories and on the correspondence theory of truth.
    [Show full text]
  • Pragmatic Realism†
    Revista de Humanidades de Valparaíso Año 4 / 2016 / 2do semestre / N° 8 Págs. 107 - 122 ISSN 0719-4234 / eISSN 0719-4242 Pragmatic Realism† Hasok Chang* Abstract In this paper I seek to articulate and develop Roberto Torretti’s advocacy of pragmatic realism. At the core of Torrietti’s view is a rejection of the notion that the truth of scientific theories consists in their correspondence to the world. I propose to understand correspondence in that sense as a metaphorical notion. I articulate a notion of pragmatist coherence, on the basis of which I make new coherence theories of truth and reality. Then it becomes possible to say that pragmatic realism consists in the pursuit of true knowledge of reality, in a way that is also consonant with Torretti’s pluralism. Keywords: pragmatism, realism, pluralism, coherence, truth, reality Realismo Pragmático Resumen En este trabajo intento articular y desarrollar la defensa que Roberto Torretti hace del realismo pragmático. En el núcleo de la visión de Torretti existe un rechazo a la idea de que la verdad de las teorías científicas consista en su correspondencia con el mundo. Propongo entonces entender la correspondencia como una noción metafórica. Articularé una noción de coherencia pragmática sobre la cual establezco una nueva teoría de la coherencia entre verdad y realidad. __________________En consecuencia, resultará posible afirmar que el realismo pragmático † Recibido: octubre 2016. This paper is partly based on a presentation entitled “Pragmatist Coherence as the Source of Truth and Reality,” given at the sixth biennial conference of the Society for Philosophy of Science in Practice (SPSP) on 17 June 2016 at Rowan University.
    [Show full text]
  • Axiological Scientific Realism and Methodological Prescription
    Axiological Scientific Realism and Methodological Prescription Timothy D. Lyons Indiana University–Purdue University Indianapolis I: Meta-Hypotheses in the Scientific Realism Debate The contemporary scientific realism debate centers on two general kinds of meta-hypotheses, i.e., hypotheses about science, both of which are purported to be empirical. The first kind of meta- hypotheses are descriptive hypotheses regarding the nature of scientific inquiry. I will call these “Type-D meta-hypotheses.” The second kind of meta-hypotheses are epistemological theories about what individuals (scientists or non-scientists) should / can justifiably believe about (successful) scientific theories. I will call the latter, “Type-E meta-hypotheses.” I will first identify three Type-Ds. The realist’s most explicit and fundamental Type-D is axiological, a meta-hypothesis that purports to describe the aim of science: science seeks truth, including truth about unobservables. This meta-hypothesis is opposed by non-realists who favor an alternative. Van Fraassen, for instance, argues that science seeks empirical adequacy—and that truth about unobservables, though possibly attained on occasion, is not of concern to the scientific enterprise. Larry Laudan argues that, if a general aim is needed, it is that science seeks, not truth, but solutions to problems. Hence, central to the scientific realism debate are competing empirical descriptions, Type-D axiological meta-hypotheses, regarding the aim of science. A second kind of Type-D meta-hypothesis of importance in the realism debate pertains more specifically to the nature and structure of scientific inference itself. In light of well-known descriptive concerns regarding the classical Type-D meta-hypotheses— e.g., enumerative-inductivism, hypothetico-deductivism—realists tend to favor an alternative that we can dub descriptive 1 explanationism.
    [Show full text]
  • Scientific Realism
    eophil_S1 10/25/05 8:44 AM Page 688 SCIENTIFIC REALISM Kepler, J. The Secret of the Universe (1596). Translated by A.M. scientific realism Duncan. New York: Abaris Books, 1981. Kuhn, T. S. The Structure of Scientific Revolutions. Chicago: Scientific realism is a philosophical view about science University of Chicago Press, 1962. that consists of three theses: Kyburg,H.E.Science & Reason. New York: Oxford University Press, 1990. The metaphysical thesis: The world has a definite and Myrvold, W. C. “A Bayesian Account of The Virtue of mind-independent structure. Unification.” Philosophy of Science 70 (2003): 399–423. Myrvold, W. C., and W. Harper. “Model Selection, Simplicity, The semantic thesis: Scientific theories should be and Scientific Inference.” Philosophy of Science 69 (2002): taken at face value. They are truth-conditioned 135–149. Newton, I. Mathematical Principles of Natural Philosophy.3rd descriptions of their intended domain, both observ- ed. (1726). Translated by I. B. Cohen and A. Whitman. Los able and unobservable. Hence, they are capable of Angeles: University of California Press, 1999. being true or false. The theoretical terms featured in Pearl, J. Causality. San Mateo, CA: Morgan Kaufmann, 2000. theories have putative factual reference. Pearl, J. Probabilistic Reasoning in Intelligent Systems: Networks of Plausible Inference. San Mateo, CA: Morgan Kaufmann, The epistemic thesis: Mature and predictively success- 1988. ful scientific theories are well confirmed and Popper,K.R.Conjectures and Refutations: The Growth of (approximately) true of the world. So the entities Scientific Knowledge (1962). New York: Harper & Row, 1963. Popper,K.R.The Logic of Scientific Discovery (1959).
    [Show full text]
  • Realist and Anti-Realist Approaches in Philosophy of Science: Perspective and Representational Pluralism in Scientific Discovery
    Realist and Anti-Realist Approaches in Philosophy of Science: Perspective and Representational Pluralism in Scientific Discovery Mark Coleman Department of Philosophy School of Humanities, Faculty of Arts The University of Adelaide Submitted for the degree of Master of Philosophy August 2016 Scientific Realism versus Anti-realism Mark Coleman 1 Table of Contents Table of Contents 2 Abstract 4 Thesis Declaration 5 Acknowledgements 6 Chapter 1 7 Scientific Realism versus Anti-Realism, an Introduction 7 Preamble 7 1.1 An overview of scientific realism 10 1.2 Anti-realism 12 1.3 Some realist responses 16 1.4 Variations and preliminary conclusions 18 Chapter 2 21 Anti-Realism: van Fraassen and His Critics 21 2.1 van Fraassen’s ‘arguments concerning scientific realism’ 21 2.1.1 van Fraassen’s account of realism 22 2.1.2 Constructive empiricism 23 2.1.3 van Fraassen on “The Theory/Observation ‘Dichotomy’” and the observable/unobservable distinction 26 2.1.4 van Fraassen on inference to the best explanation 28 2.2 Responses to van Fraassen 31 2.2.1 Observable versus unobservable 33 2.2.2 Churchland on observation, empirical adequacy and ontological commitment 36 2.2.3 van Fraassen, the microscope, and ‘public hallucinations’ 41 2.2.4 Underdetermination 43 2.2.5 Boyd’s defence of realism: underdetermination and the importance of theoretical induction 46 2.2.6 Ladyman and Ross, and Ellis on underdetermination 50 2.2.7 Epistemic virtues and theory evaluation: Churchland on beliefworthiness and the super-empirical virtues 52 2.3 Giere’s ‘modest’
    [Show full text]
  • Chapter 4 Reading Nature Realist, Instrumentalist, and Quietist
    Chapter 4 raji ! 3/24/14 8:45 PM Reading Nature Deleted: : Realist, Instrumentalist, and Quietist Interpretations of Scientific jfk ! 4/21/14 7:29 PM Theories Comment: au: Notes are not allowed in titles or heads. The callout has been moved to the first sentence in the text. OK? The TOC gives the subtitle as “The Interpretation of Scientific Theories.” Please P. Kyle Stanford indicate the correct subtitle. Title as here is correct. PKS: moving callout to first sentence is fine (though moving it to the end of the last sentence 1. Preliminary Reconnaissance: Realism, Instrumentalism, and might be even better); subtitle as it is here (“Realist, Instrumentalist, and Quietist Interpretations of Scientific Theories”) is correct Interpretation jfk ! 3/16/14 6:29 AM Formatted: Font:Bold jfk ! 3/16/14 6:37 AM Questions concerning how we are to interpret our best scientific theories, make sense of Formatted: Font:Not Italic what they are telling us, or even just connect them systematically to the world around us jfk ! 3/16/14 6:43 AM Deleted: , have a remarkably long intellectual pedigree.1 And they have most often been motivated not by the sorts of rarified puzzles we encounter in the course of trying to decide how we could even possibly understand claims about, say, superpositions or complementarity in quantum mechanics, but instead by concerns about whether we are really entitled to Preston Stanford ! 4/17/14 3:07 PM Deleted: , believe what our theories say if we interpret them in what otherwise strikes us as the most 1 My thanks to Aldo Antonelli; Jeff Barrett; Ludwig Fahrbach; Arthur Fine; Yoichi Ishida; Pen Maddy; David Malament; Mark Newman; Michael Poulin; Jim Weatherall;[au: OK to alphabetize the names? OK] students in graduate seminars at the University of Pittsburgh Department of History and Philosophy of Science and the University of California, Irvine, Department of Logic and Philosophy of Science;[au: correct?PKS: yes] and many others I have inexcusably forgotten for useful discussion and suggestions regarding the material in this chapter.
    [Show full text]
  • Elixir Journal
    53737 Stella S. Makpu and Christian C. Emedolu/ Elixir Biosciences 135 (2019) 53737-53744 Available online at www.elixirpublishers.com (Elixir International Journal) Biosciences Elixir Biosciences 135 (2019) 53539-53545 Bas C. Van Fraassen‟s Objection to Unobservable Entities: A Studied Rebuttal with the Case of Mycobacterium Tuberculosis Stella S. Makpu1 and Christian C. Emedolu2 1Department of Microbiology, University of Port Harcourt, Nigeria 2Department of Philosophy, University of Port Harcourt, Nigeria ARTICLE INFO ABSTRACT Article history: Bas C. van Fraassen holds an anti-realist position that directs a damaging attack against Received: 22 June 2019; entity realism. As it stands, the question of limits of experience is crucial to van Received in revised form: Fraassen‟s constructive empiricism and has an intricate link with his negation of the 1 October 2019; ontological status of unobservable entities. This paper essentially rebuts van Fraassen‟s Accepted: 10 October 2019; position with the case of drug resistant Mycobacterium tuberculosis. It queries the sort of experiential limits placed on science by van Fraassen and argues that his epistemological Keywords or constructive empiricist dimension of discourse does not fit or tie-in properly with the Constructive Empiricism, question of existence of unobservable entities. Most of his critics somewhat fail to Experience, recognize differences in dimensions of discourse. To be sure, this un-appreciated Ontological Status, difference in discourse dimension is what brings a shimmering freshness to this paper. Entity Realism, Now, using the qualitative tool of critical analysis, the paper fronts the pragmatic and Mycoba Cteriumtuberculosis. ontological dimensions as much better thresholds of argumentation in the realm of existence of unobservable entities.
    [Show full text]
  • Spring 2018 Edition
    METEORITE THE UNDERGRADUATE JOURNAL OF PHILOSOPHY FROM THE UNIVERSITY OF MICHIGAN The University of Michigan Ann Arbor SPRING 2018 METEORITE 1 EDITOR-IN-CHIEF: Jesse Kozler EDITORS: Aaruran Chandrasekhar, Benjamin Chiang, Colton Karpman, Isabel Park, Joe Wisniewski, Scott Bouboulis FACULTY ADVISOR: David John Baker, Ph.D Meteorite gratefully acknowledges the support of Judith Beck and the staff of the Tanner Library, and the faculty and staff of the University of Michigan Department of Philosophy, without whom this publication would not be possible. All authors retain copyright on original work unless otherwise noted. Please direct copyright inquiries and requests for back issues to: Meteorite c/o Department of Philosophy 2215 Angell Hall 435 S. State St. Ann Arbor, MI 48109 USA METEORITE 2 Contents A Critique of Cartwright’s Entity Realism: Redundancy of Causal Ex- planations .........................................................................................................3 Nicholas M.G. Friedman Skidmore College Trust, Reliance and Normativity: Explaining the Normative Dimen- sion of Trust in Terms of Interpersonal Relationships .........................12 Johnny Hugill Sidney Sussex College, University of Cambridge The Gender of Consent ................................................................................24 Paula Keller University of Cambridge ”Beyond a Reasonable Doubt”: An Analytic Reconstruction .............33 Jared I. Mayer Johns Hopkins University When Some Speak Too Loudly: Reimagining the Relationship be-
    [Show full text]