Logical Constants: a Modalist Approach 11 Respect to the Producible Theorems, One System Is No Better Than Another, Save for Reasons of Efficiency Or Aesthetic Values

Total Page:16

File Type:pdf, Size:1020Kb

Logical Constants: a Modalist Approach 11 Respect to the Producible Theorems, One System Is No Better Than Another, Save for Reasons of Efficiency Or Aesthetic Values NOUSˆ 47:1 (2013) 1–24 Logical Constants: A Modalist Approach1 OTAVIO´ BUENO University of Miami SCOTT A. SHALKOWSKI University of Leeds 1. Introduction Philosophers sometimes take refuge in logic in a way befitting a domain free of controversy. Metaphysical claims are thought to be dubious in ways that logical claims are not.2 Metaphysical matters cannot be settled in any straightforward way, whereas logical issues typically can be. There is more than a little self-deception contained in this contrast, however. In this paper, we begin with a theoretical dis- agreement in logical theory. This disagreement carries over to the characterization of logical constants. After presenting Tarski’s very general account of the nature of the constants, and Gila Sher’s more detailed development of the Tarskian approach, we return to the subject of logical disagreement and show the deficiencies with the basic Tarskian framework. We argue that a modalist alternative should supplant it. Our goal in the paper is to offer a modalist account of the status of logical constants. We are not developing a full-fledged modalist account of logical conse- quence. We take only the first step in that direction by examining the ineliminable role that modality plays in shaping our understanding of logical constants. The modalist treatment of logical consequence is left for another occasion. 2. The Model-Theoretic Approach to Logical Constants: Some Features Logical theory is a partial theory of good argumentation. It is a partial theory be- cause it concerns only the formal or structural component of good argumentation, and good arguments are about more than structure. Good arguments are also about truth, warranted belief, the transmission of warrant, and the like. Disagreements regarding any aspect of good argumentation may well generate disagreements re- garding which arguments are valid and which are not. Intuitionist logicians have maintained that the Law of Excluded Middle is not a logical truth and that re- ductio ad absurdum is not a valid argument form. Paraconsistent logicians have maintained that logics codifying well-managed inference should not be explosive, i.e., they should not treat as valid the inference of an arbitrary conclusion from inconsistent premises. It is usual and agreed among the advocates of divergent treatments of logic that expressions for first-order quantification, negation, conjunction, disjunction, C 2012 Wiley Periodicals, Inc. 1 2 NOUSˆ and the material conditional are permitted only their own respective invariant interpretations. All parties agree that permitting all expressions to have variable interpretations makes formal treatments of validity impossible, since no argument form would preserve truth under all interpretations of the logical “constants”, and all agree that permitting no expressions to have variable interpretations does not allow for multiple instances of a given logical form, thus precluding the study of formal logic. Hence, all agree on the need for logically relevant constants. There is also widespread, even if not universal, agreement that the Tarskian model-theoretic framework is the proper framework for characterizing the various theories of logical truth and logical consequence. In his original account of logical consequence, Tarski saw the need for the interpretation of some expressions to remain fixed, but he provided only an implicit account of what those fixed expres- sions were by employing the constants as he did, and he provided no account of what makes an expression appropriate for only an invariant interpretation (Tarski [1935]). Tarski filled this gap in a posthumous paper on the notion of a logical con- stant (Tarski [1966]). There he provided a very general model-theoretic framework that, in principle, could be accepted by all participants in the debate regarding the proper characterization of logical consequence. The key idea behind eligibility for invariant interpretation is that an expression has an invariant interpretation when its interpretation is unaffected by all permutations of the objects in the domain. Tarski’s own development of his approach was extremely general and abstract. Gila Sher provided a much more detailed presentation of a model-theoretic account of the logical constants (Sher [1991], Chapter 3, and Sher [2003]). Her account can be accepted entirely by classical logicians. For our purposes, the key features of her account are that logical constants are: (1) extensional in character, (2) defined over all models, and (3) defined by functions that are invariant over isomorphic structures. More specifically (see Sher [1991], pp. 54–56, and Sher [2003], pp. 189– 190): C is a logical constant iff C is a truth-functional connective or C satisfies the following conditions: (A) A logical constant C is syntactically an n-place predicate or functor (functional expression) of level 1 or 2, n being a positive integer. (B) A logical constant C is defined by a single extensional function and is identified with its extension.3 (C) A logical constant C is defined over models. In each model A over which it is defined, C is assigned a construct of elements of A corresponding to its syntactic category. Specifically, C should be defined by a function fC such that given a model A (with universe A) in its domain: n (a) If C is a first-level n-place predicate, then fC (A)isasubsetofA . n (b) If C is a first-level n-place functor, then fC (A) is a function from A into A. (c) If C is a second-level n-place predicate, then fC (A)isasubsetofB1 x ...x Bn, m where for n ≥ i ≥ 1, Bi = A if i(C) is an individual, and Bi = P(A )ifi(C) is an m-place predicate (i(C)beingtheith argument of C). Logical Constants: A Modalist Approach 3 (d) If C is a second-level n-place functor, then fC (A) is a function from B1 x ...x Bn into Bn +1,whereforn+1 ≥ i ≥ 1, Bi is as defined in (c). (D) A logical constant C is defined over all models (for the logic). (E) A logical constant C is defined by a function fC which is invariant over isomorphic structures. That is, the following conditions hold: (a) If C is a first-level n-place predicate, A and A are models with universes A and n n A respectively, b1, ...,bn∈A , b 1, ...,b n∈A , and the structures A, b1, ...,bn and A ,b 1, ...,b n are isomorphic, then b1, ...,bn∈fC (A)iff b 1, ...,b n∈fC (A ). (b) If C is a second-level n-place predicate, A and A are models with universes A and A respectively, D1, ...,Dn∈B1 x ...x Bn, D 1, ...,D n∈B 1 x ...x B n (where for n ≥ i ≥ 1, Bi and B i are as in (C.c)), and the structures A, D1, ...,Dn and A , D 1, ...,D n are isomorphic, then D1, ...,Dn∈ fC (A)iffD 1, ...,D n∈fC (A ). (c) Analogously for functors. Sher’s is a disjunctive account, according to which, given the first disjunct, any truth-functional connective is automatically a logical constant. To avoid exclud- ing non-truth-functional connectives by fiat, the second disjunct is offered. First, syntactically logical constants are functional expressions (condition (A)) associated with a single extensional function (condition (B)) defined over all models for the logic (conditions (C) and (D)). Finally, the crucial condition is that a logical con- stant is a function that is invariant over isomorphic structures (condition (E)), i.e., the extension of the function does not change across isomorphic structures. In other words, if we permute the objects of the domains of these structures, the extension of that function will remain invariant. This is the core of the Tarskian model-theoretic approach, and Sher develops it carefully. 3. The Model-Theoretic Approach to Logical Constants: Some Troubles The model-theoretic account faces several difficulties. The most significant lies in the model-theoretic framework itself. Models are useful and informative only to the extent that they model something and fail to model other things. In the context of logic, models serve primarily as invalidators of inferences. If there is a model in which the premises of an argument are jointly true and yet the conclusion is false, the argument is invalid. So far, we have said nothing about what models are, and not just any old models will do. Not all of the Lego models in the world will do what the logician requires. The reason for this, of course, is that all of the Lego models in the world fail to model all that there is. The world itself manages what the Lego models do not; it manages to model all that there is because it is all that there is. If the world and an argument conspire so that the premises are true and the conclusion false, that is sufficient for the invalidity of the argument. The logician, however, is still not satisfied with the world as the (domain of) models. Even if all inferences of “At no time is Mars inhabited” from “At some 4 NOUSˆ time Earth is inhabited” begin and end in truth, the connection between the truths in those inferences is insufficiently tight. Intuitively, we have contingency where we require necessity. The model-theoretician maintains that ‘the world’ was inter- preted too narrowly. The world is not merely the concrete world of plums, planets, princesses, and peas. It contains all the wonders of the abstract. While there is no concrete model in which the premise is true while the conclusion is false, there is an abstract model invalidating that inference. There are two ways of interpreting the model-theoretic account: one is platonist, the other is nominalist.
Recommended publications
  • Which Quantifiers Are Logical? a Combined Semantical and Inferential Criterion Solomon Feferman1
    Which Quantifiers are Logical? A combined semantical and inferential criterion Solomon Feferman1 Abstract. The aim of logic is to characterize the forms of reasoning that lead invariably from true sentences to true sentences, independently of the subject matter; thus its concerns combine semantical and inferential notions in an essential way. Up to now most proposed characterizations of logicality of sentence generating operations have been given either in semantical or inferential terms. This paper offers a combined semantical and inferential criterion for logicality (improving one originally proposed by Jeffery Zucker) and shows that any quantifier that is to be counted as logical according to that criterion is definable in first order logic. The aim of logic is to characterize the forms of reasoning that lead invariably from true sentences to true sentences, independently of the subject matter. The sentences involved are analyzed according to their logical (as opposed to grammatical) structure, i.e. how they are compounded from their parts by means of certain operations on propositions and predicates, of which the familiar ones are the connectives and quantifiers of first order logic. To spell this out in general, one must explain how the truth of compounds under given operations is determined by the truth of the parts, and characterize those forms of rules of inference for the given operations that insure preservation of truth. The so-called problem of “logical constants” (Gomez-Torrente 2002) is to determine all such operations.
    [Show full text]
  • The Nature of Logical Constants
    Aporia vol. 27 no. 1—2017 The Nature of Logical Constants LAUREN RICHARDSON haracterizing the distinction between the “logical” and “non-logical” expressions of a language proves a challenging task, and one Cwith significant implications for the nature and scope of logic itself. It is often claimed that logical truths are statements that are “true by virtue of form,” and, likewise, that arguments are logically valid because of their respective “forms,” not because of their contents (Sider 2).1 Take, for example, a straightforward piece of reasoning: (P1) Maria is in Berlin or she is in Vienna. (P2) Maria is not in Berlin. (C) Maria is in Vienna. If this argument is valid—which, of course, in classical logic, it is—then it is typically held to be valid because of the structure of the argument and not because of certain material facts about the world. So it seems as if we should 1 Contrast the idea of truth preservation by virtue of form with the idea of an argument that is truth- preserving by virtue of the meaning of certain terms: (P1*):Nick is a bachelor. (C*): Nick is an unmarried man. We might think that the truth of (P1*) guarantees the truth of (C*), but it is not by virtue of the form of the argument; it is by virtue of the meaning of the expressions “bachelor” and “unmarried man.” Lauren Richardson is studying philosophy at the University of Chicago and will graduate in 2018. Her philosophical interests include philosophy of language, logic, metaethics, and feminism. After graduation, Lauren intends to pursue a graduate degree in philosophy.
    [Show full text]
  • Plurals and Mereology
    Journal of Philosophical Logic (2021) 50:415–445 https://doi.org/10.1007/s10992-020-09570-9 Plurals and Mereology Salvatore Florio1 · David Nicolas2 Received: 2 August 2019 / Accepted: 5 August 2020 / Published online: 26 October 2020 © The Author(s) 2020 Abstract In linguistics, the dominant approach to the semantics of plurals appeals to mere- ology. However, this approach has received strong criticisms from philosophical logicians who subscribe to an alternative framework based on plural logic. In the first part of the article, we offer a precise characterization of the mereological approach and the semantic background in which the debate can be meaningfully reconstructed. In the second part, we deal with the criticisms and assess their logical, linguistic, and philosophical significance. We identify four main objections and show how each can be addressed. Finally, we compare the strengths and shortcomings of the mereologi- cal approach and plural logic. Our conclusion is that the former remains a viable and well-motivated framework for the analysis of plurals. Keywords Mass nouns · Mereology · Model theory · Natural language semantics · Ontological commitment · Plural logic · Plurals · Russell’s paradox · Truth theory 1 Introduction A prominent tradition in linguistic semantics analyzes plurals by appealing to mere- ology (e.g. Link [40, 41], Landman [32, 34], Gillon [20], Moltmann [50], Krifka [30], Bale and Barner [2], Chierchia [12], Sutton and Filip [76], and Champollion [9]).1 1The historical roots of this tradition include Leonard and Goodman [38], Goodman and Quine [22], Massey [46], and Sharvy [74]. Salvatore Florio [email protected] David Nicolas [email protected] 1 Department of Philosophy, University of Birmingham, Birmingham, United Kingdom 2 Institut Jean Nicod, Departement´ d’etudes´ cognitives, ENS, EHESS, CNRS, PSL University, Paris, France 416 S.
    [Show full text]
  • Understanding the Logical Constants and Dispositions
    Baltic International Yearbook of Cognition, Logic and Communication Volume 5 MEANING, UNDERSTANDING AND KNOWLEDGE Article 2 2009 Understanding the Logical Constants and Dispositions Corine Besson St Hugh's College, Oxford Follow this and additional works at: https://newprairiepress.org/biyclc This work is licensed under a Creative Commons Attribution-Noncommercial-No Derivative Works 4.0 License. Recommended Citation Besson, Corine (2009) "Understanding the Logical Constants and Dispositions," Baltic International Yearbook of Cognition, Logic and Communication: Vol. 5. https://doi.org/10.4148/biyclc.v5i0.279 This Proceeding of the Symposium for Cognition, Logic and Communication is brought to you for free and open access by the Conferences at New Prairie Press. It has been accepted for inclusion in Baltic International Yearbook of Cognition, Logic and Communication by an authorized administrator of New Prairie Press. For more information, please contact [email protected]. Understanding the Logical Constants and Dispositions 2 The Baltic International Yearbook of not explore here how that explanatory connection might be accounted Cognition, Logic and Communication for. But however it is accounted for, it seems that the following min- imal constraint should be met by any account of competence with an October 2010 Volume 5: Meaning, Understanding and Knowledge expression: pages 1-24 DOI: 10.4148/biyclc.v5i0.279 (CT) An account of speakers’ understanding of an expres- sion should be consistent with their correct performances CORINE BESSON with that expression. St Hugh’s College, Oxford This is a weak constraint, since the connection between competence and performance is much tighter. But this will suffice for the purposes UNDERSTANDING THE LOGICAL CONSTANTS AND of this paper.
    [Show full text]
  • The Constituents of the Propositions of Logic Kevin C
    10 The Constituents of the Propositions of Logic Kevin C. Klement 1 Introduction Many founders of modern logic—Frege and Russell among them—bemoan- ed the tendency, still found in most textbook treatments, to define the subject matter of logic as “the laws of thought” or “the principles of inference”. Such descriptions fail to capture logic’s objective nature; they make it too dependent on human psychology or linguistic practices. It is one thing to identify what logic is not about. It is another to say what it is about. I tell my students that logic studies relationships between the truth-values of propositions that hold in virtue of their form. But even this characterization leaves me uneasy. I don’t really know what a “form” is, and even worse perhaps, I don’t really know what these “propositions” are that have these forms. If propositions are considered merely as sentences or linguistic assertions, the definition does not seem like much of an improvement over the psychological definitions. Language is a human invention, but logic is more than that, or so it seems. It is perhaps forgiveable then that at certain times Russell would not have been prepared to give a very good answer to the question “What is Logic?”, such as when he attempted, but failed, to compose a paper with that title in October 1912. Given that Russell had recently completed Principia Mathematica, a work alleging to establish the reducibility of mathematics to logic, one might think this overly generous. What does the claim that mathematics reduces to logic come to if we cannot independently speci- Published in Acquaintance, Knowledge and Logic: New Essays on Bertrand Russell’s Problems of Philosophy, edited by Donovan Wishon and Bernard Linsky.
    [Show full text]
  • Handbook of Mereology Total
    Simons, P., 1987. Part I is a standard The notion of structure is of central im- reference for extensional mereology. portance to mereology (for the following Parts II and III treat further topics and see also Koslicki 2008, ch. IX). Histori- question some assumptions of extension- cal contributions had this clearly in view; ality. Has an extensive bibliography. for example, as is brought out in Harte 2002, Plato in numerous dialogues grap- ples with the question of how a whole References and further readings which has many parts can nevertheless be a single unified object and ultimately Cartwright, R., 1975, “Scattered Ob- endorses a structure-based response to jects”, as reprinted in his Philosophical this question (see Plato). Wholes, ac- Essays, 1987, Cambridge, MIT Press: cording to Plato’s mature views (as de- 171-86. veloped primarily in the Sophist, Par- Lewis, D., 1991, Parts of Classes, Ox- menides, Philebus and Timaeus), have a ford: Blackwell. dichotomous nature, consisting of both material as well as structural compo- Sanford, D. H., 2003, “Fusion Confu- nents; it is the job of structure to unify sion”, Analysis 63: 1-4. and organize the plurality of material Sanford, D. H., 2011, “Can a sum change parts that are present in a unified whole. its parts?”, Analysis 71: 235-9. A similar conception is taken up and worked out further by Aristotle who Simons, P., 1987, Parts: A Study in On- famously believed that ordinary material tology, Oxford: Clarendon Press. objects, such as houses, are compounds Tarski, A., 1929, “Foundations of the of matter (viz., the bricks, wood, etc.) Geometry of Solids” as reprinted in his and form (viz., the arrangement exhibited Logic, Semantics, Metamathematics, by the material components for the pur- Oxford: Oxford University Press, 1959: pose of providing shelter).
    [Show full text]
  • The Bounds of Logic Part 2
    To Ik a Logical Term 37 Chapter 3 To Be a Logical Ternl logic; at the same time, the principles developed by Tarski in the 1930s are still the principles underlying logic in the early 1990s. My interest in Tarski is, Ileedless to say, not historical. I am interested in the modern conception of logic as it evolved out of Tarski's early work in semantics. The Task of Logic and the Origins of Semantics In "The Concept of Truth in Formalized Languages" (1933). "On the Concept of Logical Consequence" (1936a), and "The Establishment of Scientific Semantics" (1936b), Tarski describes the semantic project as comprising two tasks: Since the discovery ofgeneralized quantifiers by A. Mostowski (1957), the I. Definition of the gelleral concept of truth for formalized languages question "What is a logical term?" has taken on a significance it did not 2. Dclinition of the logical concepts of truth, consequence, consistency. have before. Are Mostowski's quantifiers Hlogical" quantifiers'! Do they etc. , differ in any significant way from the standard existential and universal The main purpose of (I) is to secure meta logic against semantic para­ I quantifiers? What logical operators, if any, has he left out? What. ill doxes. Tarski worried lest the ullcritical usc of semantic concepts prior to I all, are the first- and second-level predicates and rcla tions that can be his work concealed an inconsistency: a hidden fallacy would undermine construed as logical? the cntire venturc. Be therefore sought precise, materially, as well as One way in which I do not want to ask the question is, "What, ill Ihe formally, correct definitions of "truth" and related notions to serve as a I nature ofthings, makes a property or a relation logical'!" On this road lie hedge against paradox.
    [Show full text]
  • Redalyc.Logical Consequence for Nominalists
    THEORIA. Revista de Teoría, Historia y Fundamentos de la Ciencia ISSN: 0495-4548 [email protected] Universidad del País Vasco/Euskal Herriko Unibertsitatea España ROSSBERG, Marcus; COHNITZ, Daniel Logical Consequence for Nominalists THEORIA. Revista de Teoría, Historia y Fundamentos de la Ciencia, vol. 24, núm. 2, 2009, pp. 147- 168 Universidad del País Vasco/Euskal Herriko Unibertsitatea Donostia-San Sebastián, España Available in: http://www.redalyc.org/articulo.oa?id=339730809003 How to cite Complete issue Scientific Information System More information about this article Network of Scientific Journals from Latin America, the Caribbean, Spain and Portugal Journal's homepage in redalyc.org Non-profit academic project, developed under the open access initiative Logical Consequence for Nominalists Marcus ROSSBERG and Daniel COHNITZ BIBLID [0495-4548 (2009) 24: 65; pp. 147-168] ABSTRACT: It has repeatedly been argued that nominalistic programmes in the philosophy of mathematics fail, since they will at some point or other involve the notion of logical consequence which is unavailable to the nominalist. In this paper we will argue that this is not the case. Using an idea of Nelson Goodman and W.V.Quine's which they developed in Goodman and Quine (1947) and supplementing it with means that should be nominalistically acceptable, we present a way to explicate logical consequence in a nominalistically acceptable way. Keywords: Philosophy of mathematics, nominalism, logical consequence, inferentialism, Nelson Goodman, W.V. Quine. 1. The Argument from Logical Consequence We do not have any strong convictions concerning the question of the existence or non- existence of abstract objects. We do, however, believe that ontological fastidiousness is prima facie a good attitude to adopt.
    [Show full text]
  • Introduction
    i i OUP CORRECTED PROOF – FINAL, //, SPi i i PART I Introduction i i i i i i OUP CORRECTED PROOF – FINAL, //, SPi i i i i i i i i OUP CORRECTED PROOF – FINAL, //, SPi i i Logical Consequence Its Nature, Structure, and Application Colin R. Caret and Ole T. Hjortland . Introduction Recent work in philosophical logic has taken interesting and unexpected turns. It has seen not only a proliferation of logical systems, but new applications of a wide range of different formal theories to philosophical questions. As a result, philosophers have been forced to revisit the nature and foundation of core logical concepts, chief amongst which is the concept of logical consequence. This volume collects together some of the most important recent scholarship in the area by drawing on a wealth of contributions that were made over the lifetime of the AHRC-funded Foundations of Logical Consequence project. In the following introductory essay we set these contributions in context and identify how they advance important debates within the philosophy of logic. Logical consequence is the relation that obtains between premises and conclu- sion(s) in a valid argument. Validity, most will agree, is a virtue of an argument, butwhatsortofvirtue?Orthodoxyhasitthatanargumentisvalidifitmustbethe case that when the premises are true, the conclusion is true. Alternatively, that it is impossible for the premises to be true and the conclusion false simultaneously. In short, the argument is necessarily truth preserving. These platitudes, however, leave us with a number
    [Show full text]
  • Logic, the a Priori, and the Empirical
    Logic, the A Priori, and the Empirical William H. HANSON ABSTRACT: The time-honored view that logic is a non-empirical enterprise is still widely accepted, but it is not always recognized that there are (at least) two distinct ways in which this view can be made precise. One way fo- cuses on the knowledge we can have of logical matters, the other on the nature of the logical consequence relation itself. More specifically, the first way embodies the claim that knowledge of whether the logical consequence relation holds in a particular case is knowledge that can be had a priori (if at all). The second way presupposes a distinction between structural and non-structural properties and relations, and it holds that logical consequence is to be defined exclusively in terms of the former. It is shown that the two ways are not coextensive by giving an example of a logic that is non-empirical in the second way but not in the first. Keywords: logic, a priori, structure, logical consequence In “Logical Consequence and Logical Expressions” (2003) Mario Gómez-Torrente discusses many central issues in the philosophy of logic in an elegant, knowledgeable, and sensible manner. At the beginning of his paper Gómez-Torrente notes the impor- tance of form and modality for the notion of logical consequence, and he asserts that a necessary condition for the conclusion of an argument to follow from the premises is that it “follows by logical necessity from those premises”. He further asserts that this notion of following by logical necessity is “associated (in ways which are themselves unclear and vague) to unclear and vague notions like analytical implication, a priori implication and implication by necessity (tout court)”.
    [Show full text]
  • What Does It Mean to Say That Logic Is Formal?
    WHAT DOES IT MEAN TO SAY THAT LOGIC IS FORMAL? by John Gordon MacFarlane A.B., Philosophy, Harvard College, 1991 M.A., Philosophy, University of Pittsburgh, 1994 M.A., Classics, University of Pittsburgh, 1997 Submitted to the Graduate Faculty of Arts and Sciences in partial fulfillment of the requirements for the degree of Doctor of Philosophy University of Pittsburgh 2000 i Robert Brandom, Distinguished Service Professor of Philosophy (Director) Nuel Belnap, Alan Ross Anderson Distinguished Professor of Philosophy (Second Reader) Joseph Camp, Professor of Philosophy Danielle Macbeth, Associate Professor of Philosophy, Haverford College (Outside Reader) Kenneth Manders, Associate Professor of Philosophy Gerald Massey, Distinguished Service Professor of Philosophy ii WHAT DOES IT MEAN TO SAY THAT LOGIC IS FORMAL? John Gordon MacFarlane, PhD University of Pittsburgh, 2000 Much philosophy of logic is shaped, explicitly or implicitly, by the thought that logic is distinctively formal and abstracts from material content. The distinction between formal and material does not appear to coincide with the more familiar contrasts between a pri- ori and empirical, necessary and contingent, analytic and synthetic—indeed, it is often invoked to explain these. Nor, it turns out, can it be explained by appeal to schematic inference patterns, syntactic rules, or grammar. What does it mean, then, to say that logic is distinctively formal? Three things: logic is said to be formal (or “topic-neutral”) (1) in the sense that it provides constitutive norms for thought as such, (2) in the sense that it is indifferent to the particular identities of objects, and (3) in the sense that it abstracts entirely from the semantic content of thought.
    [Show full text]
  • In Search of the Intuitive Notion of Logical Consequence
    1 In search of the intuitive notion of logical consequence Catarina Dutilh Novaes Faculty of Philosophy – Leiden University I. Introduction After decades of predominant focus on the notion of logical truth, the debate on the concept of logical consequence among philosophers and logicians was re-ignited by J. Etchemendy’s book The Concept of Logical Consequence (1990). His main tenet was that the model-theoretic notion of logical consequence did not capture adequately the corresponding intuitive notion. One of Etchemendy’s central claims was that the intuitive notion could be understood essentially from two different perspectives, one representational and one interpretational – and that the model-theoretic notion failed to match either. Some years ago, S. Shapiro (1998) sought to vindicate the model-theoretic notion of logical consequence; one of his arguments was that the dichotomy representational/interpretational notion of logical consequence was in a certain way infelicitous, since, according to him, a faithful rendering of the intuitive concept would have to have elements of both notions. Clearly, the resolution of issue as to whether the model-theoretic notion correctly captures the intuitive notion presupposes an at least minimally adequate characterization of this intuitive notion. Shapiro claimed that Etchemendy hadn’t really provided such a characterization1, and attempted to formulate one himself. He further claimed that, thus characterized, the intuitive notion was indeed correctly captured by the model-theoretic notion (albeit with some adjustements).2 In this paper, I do not discuss Shapiro’s defense of the model-theoretic notion; rather I examine his contention that the best rendering of the intuitive notion of logical consequence is what he called the ‘conglomeration’ notion, that is, the hybrid notion that combines both the representational and the interpretational view on consequence.
    [Show full text]