Ling 98A: the Meaning of Negation (Week 2)

Total Page:16

File Type:pdf, Size:1020Kb

Ling 98A: the Meaning of Negation (Week 2) Ling 98a: The Meaning of Negation (Week 2) Yimei Xiang [email protected] 24 September 2013 1 Review 1.1 Negation in propositional logic • Truth table of negation; propositional logic • Some tautologies in propositional logic are not valid in natural languages 1.2 Oppositions • Contrary opposition vs. contradictory opposition • Defining oppositions with laws: – Law of Non-Contradiction (LNC): :(f ^ :f) – Law of Excluded Middle (LEM): f _:f • Three tricky issues: – Non-existent subjects – Scope ambiguity of negation – Metalinguistic negation • Categorical term-based logic of Aristotle – S(ubject)-P(redicate) form, a given P can be either affirmed or denied of a given S. – Two negations (neither of the following two is a propositional operator) ∗ Predicate denial: S is not (not-)P ∗ Term negation: S is not-P – When the given subject doesn’t exist, any affirmation about this subject is False and any denial is True. – Square of opposition ∗ Four corners: A, E, O, I ∗ Three types of oppositions: contradictories, contraries and subcontraries 1 Ling 98a: The Meaning of Negation (Week 2) 1.3 Presuppositions • Presuppositions – Presupposition triggers – Presuppositions vs. entailments/ implicatures – Presupposition projection ∗ Negation ∗ Conditionals ∗ Epistemic modals ∗ Interrogatives 2 Presuppositions (cont.) 2.1 Presupposition accommodation • A presupposition of a sentence must normally be part of the common ground of the utterance context (the shared knowledge of the interlocutors) in order for the sentence to be felicitous. This process of an addressee assuming that a presupposition is true (even in the absence of explicit information that it is), is called presupposition accommodation. • If the presupposition is not properly accommodated (namely, the truth of the presupposition is not satisfied in the CG), then we say there is a presupposition failure. (1) a. # John’s daughter is coming, and John doesn’t have a daughter. b. # If John’s daughter is coming, then we will have a party tonight. Although John doesn’t have a daughter. • A pragmatic approach (Heim 1983, a.o.) • A semantic approach (three-valued logic): If one of a sentence’s presuppositions is not True, then the sentence is neither True nor False, but has a third truth value ‘#’. (Strawson) (2) p is a presupposition of f (viz. fp) iff whenever p is not True, f is #. p fp 1 1 or 0 0 # Appendix: representative three-valued logical systems (Gamut 1 section 5.5.2) 2 Ling 98a: The Meaning of Negation (Week 2) 2.2 Presuppositions and negation • Presuppositions project under negation fp :fp 1 0 0 1 # # • However, in the following sentence, the presuppositions from the negative clause isn’t true. Why this sentence is still felicitous? (3) John’s daughter is not coming, since John doesn’t have a daughter. In other words, we need to address the dilemma between the following two observations: – The presupposition of f is projected in the negation of f. – The presupposition of f is defeasible in the negation of f. • Option 1: There are two kinds of negation in the extended Bochvar’s system: i. Internal/ presupposition-preserving negation: : ii. External/ presupposition-canceling negation: ∼ f :f ∼ f 1 0 0 0 1 1 # # 1 With internal negation, presuppositions are preserved and truth-value gaps arise when one or more of the presuppositions fail; with external negation, presuppositions are potentially re- moved or transformed into simple entailments and the sentence is bivalent. Selective Reading: Gamut 1 pp 188-189. • Option 2: Negation applies to an operator (assertion operator A) that has a meaning akin to “it is the case that/ it is true that ...”. (4) a. Not that John’s daughter is coming, (since John doesn’t have a daughter). b. Not that John has a daughter and his daughter is coming, (since he doesn’t have a daughter). fp Afp :Afp 1 1 0 0 0 1 # 0 1 Some characteristic properties of A (Beaver and Krahmer 2001): (5) a. If f presupposes p, then Afp is equivalent with Af ^ Ap. b. Af is equivalent with f, if f is defined. 3 Ling 98a: The Meaning of Negation (Week 2) • Global accommodation vs. local accommodation John’s daughter is not coming. – Global accommodation: John has a daughter and she is not coming. – Local accommodation: Not that [John has a daughter and she is coming] In-class Exercise 1: 1. Translate the sentences in (4) into propositional formulas and identify their truth conditions. (Omit the bracketed parts.) 2. Use truth tables to show the distinctions between fp, :Afp and A:fp. 3. The meta-assertion operator A and ∼ are interdefinable via :. Use truth tables to show the equivalent relations below. (6) a. ∼ f is equivalent to :Af. b. Af is equivalent to : ∼ f. 4 Ling 98a: The Meaning of Negation (Week 2) • Back to the original question: give an answer that differs from both Mary’s and John’s. Make sure that your answer cannot be simultaneously true with either of their answers. (15) Case 3 in Handout 1: – Mary: “Harry’s daughter is coming.” – John: “Harry’s daughter is not coming.” – You: “Harry doesn’t have a daughter.” In a three-valued logic, “not True” can be either False (0) or Neither (#); – a proposition with a presupposition can be either True, False or Neither; – a proposition without any presupposition is either True or False; When the presupposition “Harry has a daughter” is False (0), Mary’s answer will be Neither (#), while John’s answer is ambiguous. Can you tell what are the possible truth values of John’s answer? • In-class Exercise 2: There are many kinds of three-valued logical systems in the literature. Consider the Bochvar’s system below, for each of the following formulas, identify whether it is a tautology or not. Table 1: Truth table of the Bochvar’s system f y :f ∼ f f ^ y f _ y f ! y 1 1 0 0 1 1 1 1 0 0 0 0 1 0 1 # 0 0 # # # 0 1 1 1 0 1 1 0 0 1 1 0 0 1 0 # 1 1 # # # # 1 # 0 # # # # 0 # 0 # # # # # # 0 # # # (17) a. :(f ^ :f) b. ∼ (f^ ∼ f) c. ∼ (f ^ :f) d. :(f^ ∼ f) (18) a. f _:f b. f_ ∼ f (19) a. ::f $ f b. ∼∼ f $ f c. ∼ :f $ f d. : ∼ f $ f 5 Ling 98a: The Meaning of Negation (Week 2) 2.3 Another case of scope ambiguity: Neg-raising • “Neg-raising” (NR) is a phenomenon that the clause-mate negation of some sentence-embedding verb is intuitively interpreted as taking scope in the complement clause. (7) a. John doesn’t believe that it is raining. b. John believes that it isn’t raining. • Bartsch (1973): an NRP gives rise to an excluded middle (EM) homogeneity inference, sug- gesting that the subject is opinionated about the truth or falsity of the complement clause. (8) a. John believes that it is raining. belf b. John has a opinion as to whether it is raining. belf _ bel:f In a negative context, an NR reading (9c) is derived as a logical consequence of the negative assertion (9a) and the EM presupposition (9b). (9) a. John doesn’t believe that it’s raining. :belf b. John has an opinion as to if it’s raining. belf _ bel:f c. John believes that it isn’t raining. bel:f • Gajewski (2005, 2007): EMs are soft presuppositions that are lexically specified for NRPs. • A non-NR reading arises if there is a stress on the negative auxiliary. Gajewski (2007): negation takes scope over the A-operator. (10) a. John DOESN’T think that it is raining. b. 6! John thinks it isn’t raining. c. : A [John believes that it is raining] 6 Ling 98a: The Meaning of Negation (Week 2) 3 Implicatures 3.1 Conventional implicatures • Conventional implicatures are implications that are triggered by linguistic meaning. • Conventional implicatures are different from ordinary entailments in two ways: (i) the exact content of what is implied is not readily made explicit; (ii) the content of the implication does not seem at issue in the way that truth-conditional content standardly is. In-class Exercise 3: Only one of the first two sentences implies (11c), which one it is? Does it also entail (11c)? (11) a. Johni is an English man, but hei is cowardly. b. Johni is an English man, and hei is cowardly. c. John’si being cowardly is somehow unexpected or surprising in light of hisi being English. • Karttunee, Peters a.o. argue that conventional implicatures are conventionally presupposed. 7 Ling 98a: The Meaning of Negation (Week 2) 3.2 Conversational implicatures • Conversational implicatures are implications relying on more than the linguistic meaning. They are derived on the basis of conversational principles and assumptions. • Conversational principles: – Principle of cooperation (Grice [1967]1989: 26) Make your conversational contribution such as is required, at the stage at which it occurs, by the accepted purpose or direction of the talk in which you are engaged. – Conversational maxims: (12) a. QUALITY: Try to make your contribution one that is true. i. Do not say what you believe to be false. ii. Do not say that for which you lack evidence. b. QUANTITY: i. Make your contribution as informative as is required (for the current pur- poses of the exchange). ii. Do not make your contribution more informative than is required. c. RELATION: Be relevant. d. MANNER: Be perspicuous. i. Avoid obscurity of expression. ii. Avoid ambiguity. iii. Be brief. (Avoid unnecessary prolixity.) iv. Be orderly. A conversational implicature is NOT a logical consequence of a sentence, but it is logical consequence of the assumption that the speaker in uttering the sentence is conforming to the conversational maxims.
Recommended publications
  • Plurals and Mereology
    Journal of Philosophical Logic (2021) 50:415–445 https://doi.org/10.1007/s10992-020-09570-9 Plurals and Mereology Salvatore Florio1 · David Nicolas2 Received: 2 August 2019 / Accepted: 5 August 2020 / Published online: 26 October 2020 © The Author(s) 2020 Abstract In linguistics, the dominant approach to the semantics of plurals appeals to mere- ology. However, this approach has received strong criticisms from philosophical logicians who subscribe to an alternative framework based on plural logic. In the first part of the article, we offer a precise characterization of the mereological approach and the semantic background in which the debate can be meaningfully reconstructed. In the second part, we deal with the criticisms and assess their logical, linguistic, and philosophical significance. We identify four main objections and show how each can be addressed. Finally, we compare the strengths and shortcomings of the mereologi- cal approach and plural logic. Our conclusion is that the former remains a viable and well-motivated framework for the analysis of plurals. Keywords Mass nouns · Mereology · Model theory · Natural language semantics · Ontological commitment · Plural logic · Plurals · Russell’s paradox · Truth theory 1 Introduction A prominent tradition in linguistic semantics analyzes plurals by appealing to mere- ology (e.g. Link [40, 41], Landman [32, 34], Gillon [20], Moltmann [50], Krifka [30], Bale and Barner [2], Chierchia [12], Sutton and Filip [76], and Champollion [9]).1 1The historical roots of this tradition include Leonard and Goodman [38], Goodman and Quine [22], Massey [46], and Sharvy [74]. Salvatore Florio [email protected] David Nicolas [email protected] 1 Department of Philosophy, University of Birmingham, Birmingham, United Kingdom 2 Institut Jean Nicod, Departement´ d’etudes´ cognitives, ENS, EHESS, CNRS, PSL University, Paris, France 416 S.
    [Show full text]
  • Handbook of Mereology Total
    Simons, P., 1987. Part I is a standard The notion of structure is of central im- reference for extensional mereology. portance to mereology (for the following Parts II and III treat further topics and see also Koslicki 2008, ch. IX). Histori- question some assumptions of extension- cal contributions had this clearly in view; ality. Has an extensive bibliography. for example, as is brought out in Harte 2002, Plato in numerous dialogues grap- ples with the question of how a whole References and further readings which has many parts can nevertheless be a single unified object and ultimately Cartwright, R., 1975, “Scattered Ob- endorses a structure-based response to jects”, as reprinted in his Philosophical this question (see Plato). Wholes, ac- Essays, 1987, Cambridge, MIT Press: cording to Plato’s mature views (as de- 171-86. veloped primarily in the Sophist, Par- Lewis, D., 1991, Parts of Classes, Ox- menides, Philebus and Timaeus), have a ford: Blackwell. dichotomous nature, consisting of both material as well as structural compo- Sanford, D. H., 2003, “Fusion Confu- nents; it is the job of structure to unify sion”, Analysis 63: 1-4. and organize the plurality of material Sanford, D. H., 2011, “Can a sum change parts that are present in a unified whole. its parts?”, Analysis 71: 235-9. A similar conception is taken up and worked out further by Aristotle who Simons, P., 1987, Parts: A Study in On- famously believed that ordinary material tology, Oxford: Clarendon Press. objects, such as houses, are compounds Tarski, A., 1929, “Foundations of the of matter (viz., the bricks, wood, etc.) Geometry of Solids” as reprinted in his and form (viz., the arrangement exhibited Logic, Semantics, Metamathematics, by the material components for the pur- Oxford: Oxford University Press, 1959: pose of providing shelter).
    [Show full text]
  • Redalyc.Logical Consequence for Nominalists
    THEORIA. Revista de Teoría, Historia y Fundamentos de la Ciencia ISSN: 0495-4548 [email protected] Universidad del País Vasco/Euskal Herriko Unibertsitatea España ROSSBERG, Marcus; COHNITZ, Daniel Logical Consequence for Nominalists THEORIA. Revista de Teoría, Historia y Fundamentos de la Ciencia, vol. 24, núm. 2, 2009, pp. 147- 168 Universidad del País Vasco/Euskal Herriko Unibertsitatea Donostia-San Sebastián, España Available in: http://www.redalyc.org/articulo.oa?id=339730809003 How to cite Complete issue Scientific Information System More information about this article Network of Scientific Journals from Latin America, the Caribbean, Spain and Portugal Journal's homepage in redalyc.org Non-profit academic project, developed under the open access initiative Logical Consequence for Nominalists Marcus ROSSBERG and Daniel COHNITZ BIBLID [0495-4548 (2009) 24: 65; pp. 147-168] ABSTRACT: It has repeatedly been argued that nominalistic programmes in the philosophy of mathematics fail, since they will at some point or other involve the notion of logical consequence which is unavailable to the nominalist. In this paper we will argue that this is not the case. Using an idea of Nelson Goodman and W.V.Quine's which they developed in Goodman and Quine (1947) and supplementing it with means that should be nominalistically acceptable, we present a way to explicate logical consequence in a nominalistically acceptable way. Keywords: Philosophy of mathematics, nominalism, logical consequence, inferentialism, Nelson Goodman, W.V. Quine. 1. The Argument from Logical Consequence We do not have any strong convictions concerning the question of the existence or non- existence of abstract objects. We do, however, believe that ontological fastidiousness is prima facie a good attitude to adopt.
    [Show full text]
  • Introduction
    i i OUP CORRECTED PROOF – FINAL, //, SPi i i PART I Introduction i i i i i i OUP CORRECTED PROOF – FINAL, //, SPi i i i i i i i i OUP CORRECTED PROOF – FINAL, //, SPi i i Logical Consequence Its Nature, Structure, and Application Colin R. Caret and Ole T. Hjortland . Introduction Recent work in philosophical logic has taken interesting and unexpected turns. It has seen not only a proliferation of logical systems, but new applications of a wide range of different formal theories to philosophical questions. As a result, philosophers have been forced to revisit the nature and foundation of core logical concepts, chief amongst which is the concept of logical consequence. This volume collects together some of the most important recent scholarship in the area by drawing on a wealth of contributions that were made over the lifetime of the AHRC-funded Foundations of Logical Consequence project. In the following introductory essay we set these contributions in context and identify how they advance important debates within the philosophy of logic. Logical consequence is the relation that obtains between premises and conclu- sion(s) in a valid argument. Validity, most will agree, is a virtue of an argument, butwhatsortofvirtue?Orthodoxyhasitthatanargumentisvalidifitmustbethe case that when the premises are true, the conclusion is true. Alternatively, that it is impossible for the premises to be true and the conclusion false simultaneously. In short, the argument is necessarily truth preserving. These platitudes, however, leave us with a number
    [Show full text]
  • Logic, the a Priori, and the Empirical
    Logic, the A Priori, and the Empirical William H. HANSON ABSTRACT: The time-honored view that logic is a non-empirical enterprise is still widely accepted, but it is not always recognized that there are (at least) two distinct ways in which this view can be made precise. One way fo- cuses on the knowledge we can have of logical matters, the other on the nature of the logical consequence relation itself. More specifically, the first way embodies the claim that knowledge of whether the logical consequence relation holds in a particular case is knowledge that can be had a priori (if at all). The second way presupposes a distinction between structural and non-structural properties and relations, and it holds that logical consequence is to be defined exclusively in terms of the former. It is shown that the two ways are not coextensive by giving an example of a logic that is non-empirical in the second way but not in the first. Keywords: logic, a priori, structure, logical consequence In “Logical Consequence and Logical Expressions” (2003) Mario Gómez-Torrente discusses many central issues in the philosophy of logic in an elegant, knowledgeable, and sensible manner. At the beginning of his paper Gómez-Torrente notes the impor- tance of form and modality for the notion of logical consequence, and he asserts that a necessary condition for the conclusion of an argument to follow from the premises is that it “follows by logical necessity from those premises”. He further asserts that this notion of following by logical necessity is “associated (in ways which are themselves unclear and vague) to unclear and vague notions like analytical implication, a priori implication and implication by necessity (tout court)”.
    [Show full text]
  • In Search of the Intuitive Notion of Logical Consequence
    1 In search of the intuitive notion of logical consequence Catarina Dutilh Novaes Faculty of Philosophy – Leiden University I. Introduction After decades of predominant focus on the notion of logical truth, the debate on the concept of logical consequence among philosophers and logicians was re-ignited by J. Etchemendy’s book The Concept of Logical Consequence (1990). His main tenet was that the model-theoretic notion of logical consequence did not capture adequately the corresponding intuitive notion. One of Etchemendy’s central claims was that the intuitive notion could be understood essentially from two different perspectives, one representational and one interpretational – and that the model-theoretic notion failed to match either. Some years ago, S. Shapiro (1998) sought to vindicate the model-theoretic notion of logical consequence; one of his arguments was that the dichotomy representational/interpretational notion of logical consequence was in a certain way infelicitous, since, according to him, a faithful rendering of the intuitive concept would have to have elements of both notions. Clearly, the resolution of issue as to whether the model-theoretic notion correctly captures the intuitive notion presupposes an at least minimally adequate characterization of this intuitive notion. Shapiro claimed that Etchemendy hadn’t really provided such a characterization1, and attempted to formulate one himself. He further claimed that, thus characterized, the intuitive notion was indeed correctly captured by the model-theoretic notion (albeit with some adjustements).2 In this paper, I do not discuss Shapiro’s defense of the model-theoretic notion; rather I examine his contention that the best rendering of the intuitive notion of logical consequence is what he called the ‘conglomeration’ notion, that is, the hybrid notion that combines both the representational and the interpretational view on consequence.
    [Show full text]
  • Ambiguity and the Representation Problem
    Ambiguity and the Representation Problem Paul Saka ([email protected]) Department of Philosophy, University of Houston 513 Agnes Arnold Hall, Houston, TX 77204 USA Abstract x is a bank ≡ x is a [certain kind of] financial institution or x is a bank ≡ x is a [certain kind of] slope. I canvass eight possible approaches to representing (2) NARROW-SCOPE DISJUNCTION ambiguity within truth-conditional semantics, and I x is a bank ≡ argue that all are unsatisfactory. For example, it would (x is a financial institution or x is a slope). be a mistake to hold that "x is a bank" is true iff x is a Disjunction (1) would be true even if "bank" univocally meant financial institution while "x is a bank" is true iff x is a slope, for then x would be a financial institution iff x is just 'financial institution', and it would be true even if "bank" a slope. It would also be a mistake to hold that some univocally meant 'slope'. Asserting (1) implicates that we as tokens of "x is a bank" are true iff x is a financial analysts don't know which meaning uniquely belongs to institution while other tokens are true iff x is a slope, "bank", which is different from saying that "bank" has two given the existence of punning and equivocation. My different meanings. Therefore wide-scope disjunction is not work may be taken either as a call for research on a the correct format for representing ambiguity. neglected topic in truth-conditional semantics, or as a The problem with (2) is that it does not really claim that the call for abandoning truth-conditional semantics.
    [Show full text]
  • Elementary Mathematical Logic: Introduction and Outline
    ELEMENTARY MATHEMATICAL LOGIC: INTRODUCTION AND OUTLINE DAVID W. KUEKER 1. Introduction: What is Logic? Logic is traditionally defined as the study of reasoning. Mathematical Logic is, in particular, the study of reasoning as used in mathematics. Math- ematical reasoning is deductive — that is, it consists of drawing (correct) conclusions from given hypotheses. Thus the basic concept is that of a statement being a logical consequence of some other statements. In ordinary mathematical English the use of “therefore” customarily indicates that the following statement is a consequence of what comes before. For example: Every integer is either odd or even. 7 is not even. Therefore 7 is odd. We need to give a precise, mathematical, definition of logical consequence in order to study mathematical reasoning mathematically. To be a logical consequence the conclusion should not only be true (supposing the hypothe- ses to be true) but this should depend only on the “logical structure” of the statements — in this example, only on the meanings of “every”, “or” and “not”, but not on the meanings of “integer” “even”, “odd”, or “7”. For example, consider the following: Some integers are odd. Some integers are prime. Therefore some integers are both odd and prime. Although the conclusion is true this is not a valid example of a logical con- sequence since the conclusion fails, although the hypotheses hold, if “prime” is replaced by “even”. To capture this essential aspect of logical consequence we will work in formal languages in which the “non-logical” symbols do not have a fixed meaning. A formal language determines a collection of sentences of the language and also a class of interpretations for the language.
    [Show full text]
  • Elementary Mathematical Logic: Introduction and Outline
    ELEMENTARY MATHEMATICAL LOGIC: INTRODUCTION AND OUTLINE DAVID W. KUEKER 1. Introduction: What is Logic? Mathematical Logic is, at least in its origins, the study of reasoning as used in mathematics. Mathematical reasoning is deductive — that is, it consists of drawing (correct) conclusions from given hypotheses. Thus the basic concept is that of a statement being a logical consequence of some other statements. In ordinary mathematical English the use of “therefore” customarily indicates that the following statement is a consequence of what comes before. For example: Every integer is either odd or even. 7 is not even. Therefore 7 is odd. To be a logical consequence the conclusion should not only be true (sup- posing the hypotheses to be true) but this should depend only on the “logical structure” of the statements — in this example, only on the meanings of “ev- ery”, “or” and “not”, but not on the meanings of “integer” “even”, “odd”, or “7”. For example, consider the following: Some integers are odd. Some integers are prime. Therefore some integers are both odd and prime. Although the conclusion is true this is not a valid example of a logical con- sequence since the conclusion fails, although the hypotheses hold, if “prime” is replaced by “even”. To capture this aspect of logical consequence we will work in formal lan- guages in which the “non-logical” symbols do not have a fixed meaning. A formal language determines a collection of sentences amd also a class of interpretations for the language. Each sentence of the formal langauge is ei- ther true or false in each interpretation, and we will define a sentence to be a logical consequence of a set of hypotheses if it is true in every interpretation which makes all of the hypotheses true.
    [Show full text]
  • HISTORY of LOGICAL CONSEQUENCE 1. Introduction
    HISTORY OF LOGICAL CONSEQUENCE CONRAD ASMUS AND GREG RESTALL 1. Introduction Consequence is a, if not the, core subject matter of logic. Aristotle's study of the syllogism instigated the task of categorising arguments into the logically good and the logically bad; the task remains an essential element of the study of logic. In a logically good argument, the conclusion follows validly from the premises; thus, the study of consequence and the study of validity are the same. In what follows, we will engage with a variety of approaches to consequence. The following neutral framework will enhance the discussion of this wide range of approaches. Consequences are conclusions of valid arguments. Arguments have two parts: a conclusion and a collection of premises. The conclusion and the premises are all entities of the same sort. We will call the conclusion and premises of an argument the argument's components and will refer to anything that can be an argument component as a proposition. The class of propositions is defined func- tionally (they are the entities which play the functional role of argument compo- nents); thus, the label should be interpreted as metaphysically neutral. Given the platonistic baggage often associated with the label \proposition", this may seem a strange choice but the label is already used for the argument components of many of the approaches below (discussions of Aristotlean and Medieval logic are two ex- amples). A consequence relation is a relation between collections of premises and conclusions; a collection of premises is related to a conclusion if and only if the latter is a consequence of the former.
    [Show full text]
  • The Language of Thought: No Syntax Without Semantics*
    Mind & Language ISSN 0268-1064 Vol. 5 No. 3 Autumn 1990 0Basil Blackwell Article The Language of Thought: No Syntax Without Semantics* TIM CRANE Many philosophers think that being in an intentional state is a matter of being related to a sentence in a mental language-a 'Language of Thought' (see especially Fodor 1975, 1987 Appendix; Field 1978). According to this view-which I shall call 'the LT hypothesis'-when anyone has a belief or a desire or a hope with a certain content, they have a sentence of this language, with that content, 'written' in their heads. The claim is meant quite literally: the mental representations that make up the items of this language have semantic and syntactic properties. This is why, according to this view, cognitive psychology does, and should, treat that part of the mind which deals with intentional states as a semantic and a syntactic 'engine'. Stephen Stich 1983 has argued at length that although there are good reasons for thinking of the mind as a syntactic engine, cognitive psy- chology should abandon the idea of a semantic engine. In particular, he argues that the 'folk' psychological notion of the semantic content of an intentional state should have no place in a mature science of the mind. He does think that there is a language of thought, but it is a purely syntactic language, a language without semantics. In this paper I will explain why he is wrong. Patricia and Paul Churchland have also attacked the scientific credentials of folk psychology (see P.M. Churchland 1981; P.S.
    [Show full text]
  • What Do We Mean by Logical Consequence? Jesse Endo Jenks University of Puget Sound, [email protected]
    University of Puget Sound Sound Ideas Summer Research Summer 2016 What Do We Mean by Logical Consequence? Jesse Endo Jenks University of Puget Sound, [email protected] Follow this and additional works at: http://soundideas.pugetsound.edu/summer_research Part of the Logic and Foundations of Mathematics Commons Recommended Citation Jenks, Jesse Endo, "What Do We Mean by Logical Consequence?" (2016). Summer Research. Paper 276. http://soundideas.pugetsound.edu/summer_research/276 This Article is brought to you for free and open access by Sound Ideas. It has been accepted for inclusion in Summer Research by an authorized administrator of Sound Ideas. For more information, please contact [email protected]. What Do We Mean by Logical Consequence? Jesse E. Jenks * September 2016 Abstract In the beginning of the 20th century, many prominent logicians and mathematicians, such as Frege, Russell, Hilbert, and many others, felt that mathematics needed a very rigorous foun- dation in logic. The standard approach in the early part of the 20th century was to use a syntactic or proof-theoretic definition of logical consequence. This says that “for one sentence to be a logical consequence of [a set of premises] is simply for that sentence to be derivable from [them] by means of some standard system of deduction”[3, pg. 65]. However, many famous results of the time, especially Gödel’s incompleteness theorems led to logicians such as Tarski to define logical consequence with what was eventually developed into the standard “model-theoretic” definition. This way of defining logical consequence says that a argument of a certain form is a logically valid argument if it is impossible for the premises to be true and the conclusion false[9, 1, pg.
    [Show full text]