On the Psychological Foundations of the Skeptical Problem

Total Page:16

File Type:pdf, Size:1020Kb

On the Psychological Foundations of the Skeptical Problem SHADOWS OF DOUBT: ON THE PSYCHOLOGICAL FOUNDATIONS OF THE SKEPTICAL PROBLEM by John Waterman A dissertation submitted to Johns Hopkins University in conformity with the requirements for the degree of Doctor of Philosophy Baltimore, Maryland February, 2015 Abstract: Why is it that we can know so much about the world, but skeptical arguments seem so hard to resist? My dissertation offers a psychological diagnosis of the attraction of skeptical arguments. Just as vision scientists investigate illusion to better understand how perception is successful, I think that by investigating the causes of doubt we can better understand the nature of knowledge. Most contemporary accounts of the skeptical problem describe it as appealing to our ordinary intuitions about knowledge, and trace its origin to linguistic confusions. I argue that this diagnosis is mistaken on both counts. The received diagnosis assumes that skepticism is a byproduct of our ordinary epistemic practices. However, this diagnosis is overly reliant on armchair appeals to intuitions about cases by philosophers - individuals who are not ordinary epistemic agents by any means. To better understand the nature of skeptical arguments and their relation to our ordinary epistemic practices, I use the methods of the psychological sciences to empirically investigate how ordinary individuals reason about skeptical arguments, and the factors affect their evaluations. Using this empirical work as a foundation, I argue that the linguistic diagnosis of the skeptical paradox is inadequate because it does not do justice to skepticism’s intransigence: linguistic mistakes are easy to recognize, but skeptical doubts are hard to dislodge. I argue, instead, that the skeptical problem is a byproduct of a conflict between two separate components of our epistemic psychology. Specifically, I defend the idea that we deploy two different heuristic standards of evaluation towards potential beliefs. Toward favored sources, like perception and the testimony of friends, we apply the heuristic can I believe P?, and search for evidence that is consistent with P. Toward disfavored sources, like the arguments of rivals, we ask instead must I believe P?, and search for possibilities in which P might be false. These two standards, the first fallibilist and the second infallibilist, are inconsistent, and thus lead to the skeptical paradox. Dissertation Committee: Steven Gross (advisor), Michael Williams, Justin Halberda, Richard Bett, Howard Egeth ii SHADOWS OF DOUBT Acknowledgements No project like this is completed without a great deal of help, and I have many thanks to give. First, I owe an enormous debt of gratitude to Steven Gross for his support and guidance. This essay and my development as a philosopher have only been possible because of his generous insight. I also owe a special thanks to Justin Halberda for teaching me the ropes as I began to experiment with experimental philosophy. My thanks, too, to Michael Williams, whose work on skepticism inspired this project in many ways. I have also been fortunate to have met warm and fiercely intelligent friends in my time at Hopkins. Thank you to Brian Miller, Nick Tebben, Marianna Bergamaschi, and Karen Yan for all your insights and all your time. I owe a special thanks to the members of Language Lab, Derek Leben, Jeff Maynes, and Jon Hricko. You suffered through many of my half-baked ideas and still had the patience to help me improve them. Jon Hricko deserves a special thanks; I would not have started this project without his kick in the pants. I would also like to thank the administrative staff of the philosophy department for all their hard work and support. Without Alicia Burley, Leslie Bean, and Veronica Feldkircher-Reed nothing gets done, and this dissertation most certainly wouldn’t have. Many parts of this dissertation were delivered at various conferences over the last three years, and I have benefitted enormously from the insights of those audiences and from my commentators. Parts of Chapter 2 were presented at the 2012 meeting of the Southern Society for the Philosophy of Psychology, and I owe the audience there and my commentator David Rose thanks for all their input. Parts of Chapter 3 and 4 were presented at the 2013 meeting of the of the Pacific APA, the 2013 Northwestern Philosophy Conference, the 2013 meeting of the Society for Philosophy of Psychology, the 2013 Meeting of the Buffalo Experimental Philosophy Conference, the 2013 Mid-South Philosophy Conference, the 2014 Southern Society for Philosophy and Psychology, the 2014 meeting of the Central APA, and the 2014 meeting of the Society for Philosophy and Psychology. Many thanks to the audiences at those events and to Wesley Buckwalter, Joseph Schieber, Jeffrey Roland, Dan Korman, Edouard Machery, and Jonathan Weinberg for their incisive comments. iii SHADOWS OF DOUBT I owe a special thanks to Shaun Nichols and Ron Mallon for offering me an NEH fellowship at the University of Arizona to work on experimental philosophy, and for their generous support since that time. During my time in Arizona I made many friends who contributed to this project. Many thanks to Joshua Knobe, who always checks in to see how things are going, and who always has a helpful idea to offer. My thanks also to Jennifer Nagel, both for answering many questions about the psychology of knowledge attribution, and for offering an approach to philosophy I have emulated. Through my connection with Arizona I also met Joshua Alexander and Chad Gonnerman. We have now collaborated on a number of projects, and they deserve special credit for improving this project. I owe an enormous debt to my family. I have had the incredibly rare privilege of making my work something that I love. Very few people get that chance. I would never have had it without the love, support, and sacrifice of my parents and my sister. My family became larger in many ways during my time in graduate school, and so I have many thanks to give to Liz Bennett, Joanna Van Orden, Robert Knight, Margaret Chalmers, David Chalmers, John Van Orden, Jenny Van Orden and Jeff Lerman. Thank you all for everything over the years. An essay like this is made up of words but it is only made with time. Thank you to Ida, Hazel, and Noel for giving me a reason to finish. To Barb, who did the most to give me that time, as always, my love. iv SHADOWS OF DOUBT Contents 1. The Intuitive Foundations of the Skeptical Problem 1 1.1 Introduction………………………………………………….. 2 1.2 Past Attempts at Diagnosis…………………………………… 8 1.3 Empirical Diagnosis………………………………………….. 14 1.4 Psychological Foundations…………………………………… 21 1.5 A Sketch of the Argument……………………………………. 24 2. Experimental Philosophy and the Skeptical Problem 27 2.1 Introduction………………………………………………….. 28 2.2 The Method of Cases…………………………………………. 28 2.3 Intuition………………………………………………………. 31 2.4 Thought Experiments and Real Experiments…………………. 36 2.4.1 Gettier Cases………………………………………………….. 36 2.4.2 Gettier Experiments…………………………………………... 38 2.4.3 The Variation Argument………………………………………. 41 2.4.4 Experimental Control and Generality in Gettier Experiments…. 43 2.4.5 Recent Gettier Experiments…………………………………… 46 2.4.6 The Reformed General Variation Argument…………………… 49 2.4.7 Experimental Philosophy and the Skeptical Problem………….. 51 2.5 Responses to the Variation Argument…………………………. 57 2.6 Conclusion…………………………………………………….. 65 3. Contextualism and the Intuition of Conflict 67 3.1 Introduction…………………………………………………… 68 3.2 The Intuition of Conflict and Semantic Blindness…………….... 69 3.2.1 Tests For Context Sensitivity…………………………………… 71 3.2.2 Semantic Blindness…………………………………………….. 74 3.2.3 The Generality Response to Semantic Blindness……………….. 76 3.2.4 The Close Analogues and Partial Blindness Responses…………. 78 3.3 Testing the Intuition of Conflict and the Close Analogues Response 79 v SHADOWS OF DOUBT 3.3.1 Experiment 1: Empirically Describing the Intuition of Conflict… 81 3.3.2 Experiment 2: Testing the Close Analogues View………………. 87 3.4 Linguistic and Cognitive Accounts of the Intuition of Conflict….. 99 3.4.1 Dual Process Theory and Intransigence…………………………. 100 3.4.2 Heuristics, Biases, and Widespread Error……………………….. 104 3.5 Conclusion………………………………………………………. 110 4. Salience, Plausibility, and Skepticism 112 4.1 Introduction……………………………………………………... 113 4.2 Linguistic Contextualism………………………………………… 116 4.3 Testing Contextualism…………………………………………… 120 4.3.1 Null Results……………………………………………………… 120 4.3.2 Significant Results……………………………………………….. 124 4.3.3 Bad Methodology? ……………………………………………… 138 4.3.4 Experiments 1a - 1d ……………………………………………... 143 4.4 Salience and Plausibility………………………………………….. 147 4.4.1 Contextualism and Plausibility …………………………………... 150 4.4.2 Invariantism and Plausibility …………………………………….. 156 4.4.3 Plausibility and the Psychology of Law and Politics……………… 158 4.5 Testing Salience and Plausibility………………………………….. 164 4.5.1 Experiment 2a……………………………………………………. 164 4.5.2 Experiments 2b, 2c, and 2d………………………………………. 169 4.6 Repetition and Cartesian Priming………………………………… 181 4.6.1 Experiment 3a……………………………………………………. 182 4.6.2 Experiment 3b……………………………………………………. 190 4.7 Conclusion…………………………………………………….…. 195 5. The Psychological Foundations of the Skeptical Problem 208 5.1 Introduction……………………………………………………… 209 5.2 The Skeptical Problem……………………………………………. 210 5.3 Desiderata of a Diagnosis of the Skeptical Problem………………. 214 5.4 Psychological Contextualism……………………………………… 217 vi SHADOWS OF DOUBT 5.4.1 Confirmation Bias………………………………………………… 220 5.4.2 Confirmation Bias, Disconfirmation
Recommended publications
  • Putting Reasons in Their Place José Ángel Gascón
    Document generated on 09/29/2021 9:19 a.m. Informal Logic Putting Reasons in their Place José Ángel Gascón Volume 40, Number 4, 2020 Article abstract Hilary Kornblith has criticised reasons-based approaches to epistemic URI: https://id.erudit.org/iderudit/1075226ar justification on the basis of psychological research that shows that reflection is DOI: https://doi.org/10.22329/il.v40i4.6070 unreliable. Human beings, it seems, are not very good at identifying our own cognitive processes and the causes of our beliefs. In this article I defend a See table of contents conception of reasons that takes those empirical findings into account and can avoid Kornblith’s objections. Reasons, according to this account, are not to be identified with the causes of our beliefs and are useful first and foremost in Publisher(s) argumentation instead of reflection. Informal Logic ISSN 0824-2577 (print) 2293-734X (digital) Explore this journal Cite this article Gascón, J. (2020). Putting Reasons in their Place. Informal Logic, 40(4), 587–604. https://doi.org/10.22329/il.v40i4.6070 Copyright (c), 2020 José Ángel Gascón This document is protected by copyright law. Use of the services of Érudit (including reproduction) is subject to its terms and conditions, which can be viewed online. https://apropos.erudit.org/en/users/policy-on-use/ This article is disseminated and preserved by Érudit. Érudit is a non-profit inter-university consortium of the Université de Montréal, Université Laval, and the Université du Québec à Montréal. Its mission is to promote and disseminate research. https://www.erudit.org/en/ Putting Reasons in their Place JOSÉ ÁNGEL GASCÓN Department of Philosophy Universidad Católica del Maule Talca, Chile [email protected] Abstract: Hilary Kornblith has Résumé: Hilary Kornblith a critiqué criticised reasons-based approaches to les approches raisonnées de la justifi- epistemic justification on the basis of cation épistémique en se basant sur psychological research that shows that des recherches psychologiques qui reflection is unreliable.
    [Show full text]
  • Contrastivism Surveyed
    Contrastivism Surveyed (Forthcoming in Nous) Jonathan Schaffer Joshua Knobe ANU-RSSS Yale University Suppose that Ann says, “Keith knows that the bank will be open tomorrow.” Her audience may well agree. Her knowledge ascription may seem true. But now suppose that Ben—in a different context—also says “Keith knows that the bank will be open tomorrow.” His audience may well disagree. His knowledge ascription may seem false. Indeed, a number of philosophers have claimed that people’s intuitions about knowledge ascriptions are context sensitive, in the sense that the very same knowledge ascription can seem true in one conversational context but false in another. This purported fact about people’s intuitions serves as one of the main pieces of evidence for epistemic contextualism, which is (roughly speaking) the view that the truth conditions of a knowledge attribution can differ from one conversational context to another. Opponents of contextualism have replied by trying to explain these purported intuitions in other ways. For instance, they have proposed that these purported intuitions may be explained via shifts in what is at stake for the subject, pragmatic shifts in what is assertible, or performance shifts in our liability to error. Yet a recent series of empirical studies threatens to undermine this whole debate. These studies presented ordinary people with precisely the sorts of cases that have been discussed in the contextualism literature and gave them an opportunity to say whether they agreed or disagreed with the relevant knowledge attributions. Strikingly, the results suggest that people simply do not have the intuitions they were purported to have.
    [Show full text]
  • Veritism, Values, Epistemic Norms (Rysiew)
    late-stage version 1 Veritism, Values, Epistemic Norms PATRICK RYSIEW 1. Introduction Stephen Grimm observes that “[a]mong contemporary epistemologists, perhaps the most prominent way to make sense of our epistemic evaluations is in teleological terms” (Grimm 2009, 243). Specifically, many epistemologists take it that what has fundamental value in the epistemic domain is truth -- or, more properly, true belief. From this, the teleological account of epistemic appraisal to which Grimm refers naturally follows: other epistemic goods besides true belief -- justification, evidence, reasons, and so on -- have epistemic value because they are appropriately related to that telos.1 (There is, of course, significant disagreement as to what the appropriate such relation is, exactly.) Such a truth-oriented approach to understanding epistemic value and assessments is a core theme of Epistemology and Cognition, and indeed of Alvin Goldman’s epistemological writings as a whole. Thus, in the former work, we’re told that “[t]he central epistemological concepts of appraisal…invoke true belief as their ultimate aim” (1986, 3), that “true belief is a prime determinant of intellectual value” (ibid., 98), and that the appropriate criteria of epistemic rightness are all truth-linked (ibid., 116). In later works, the same underlying idea, now dubbed ‘veritism’, is defended: “the cardinal [epistemic] value, or underlying motif, is something like true, or accurate belief” (2012, 52); and various intellectual virtues (2002) and public institutions and practices
    [Show full text]
  • A Bibliography of Works on Reflexivity
    A bibliography of works on reflexivity The Harvard community has made this article openly available. Please share how this access benefits you. Your story matters Citation Peter Suber, A bibliography of works on reflexivity, in Self- Reference: Reflections on Reflexivity 259-362 (Peter Suber and Steven J. Bartlett 1987). Citable link http://nrs.harvard.edu/urn-3:HUL.InstRepos:4725021 Terms of Use This article was downloaded from Harvard University’s DASH repository, and is made available under the terms and conditions applicable to Other Posted Material, as set forth at http:// nrs.harvard.edu/urn-3:HUL.InstRepos:dash.current.terms-of- use#LAA Peter Suber A Bibliography of \ \'orks on Reflexivity "I don't have to quote anybody else to say what I could say for myself." --Anon. Section One: Introduction . ·:Reflexivity" is the generic name for all kinds and species of CJrcu~an.ty. It includes the self-reference of signs, the self-appplication of pnn~J_Ples and predicates. the self-justification and self-refutation of propositiOns and inferences the self-fulfillment and self-falsification of pre?!ctions, the self-creati~n and self-destruction of logical and legal Cntilie~, the self-augmentation and self-limitation of powers, circular reasonmg, circular causation. cvclic and spiral recurrence, feedback ?ste~s, mutu~li.ty, recipr~city: and organic. fonn. .It includes the sallaciOus, the VICious, the tnvial, and the quesuon beggmg, but also the ound, the benign, the useful and the inescapable. It ranges from the Pro. sa1c· to the numinous, from' the paradoxical to the self-evident, from ~Ience to religion.
    [Show full text]
  • The University of Chicago in Praise of Praise a Dissertation Submitted to the Faculty of the Division of the Humanities in Candi
    THE UNIVERSITY OF CHICAGO IN PRAISE OF PRAISE A DISSERTATION SUBMITTED TO THE FACULTY OF THE DIVISION OF THE HUMANITIES IN CANDIDACY FOR THE DEGREE OF DOCTOR OF PHILOSOPHY DEPARTMENT OF PHILOSOPHY BY DANIEL J. TELECH CHICAGO, ILLINOIS AUGUST 2018 ACKNOWLEDGMENTS I thank my dissertation committee. I am incredibly fortunate to have had Agnes Callard and Brian Leiter direct my dissertation project. Their support, wisdom, and generosity have meant a great deal to me—philosophically and personally—over the past several years. Joint dissertation meetings with Agnes and Brian unfailingly left me with a sense of urgency, demandingness, and encouragement that remains with me, at least on good days, when doing philosophy. Before they were my advisors, they were my teachers. Agnes’ seminar on deliberation, on the one hand, and Brian’s workshop on free will and responsibility, on the other, played significant roles in my becoming gripped by the questions animating this project. I hope to be able to live up to the ideals that working and studying with them has allowed me, however incipiently, to appreciate. I thank Paul Russell for being an excellent committee member. Paul has helped me stay attuned to the complexity and humanness of issues of agency and responsibility. This dissertation owes much to insightful conversations with him. I also thank Derk Pereboom. Derk supervised a valuable visit of mine to Cornell in the fall of 2016, and became something of an unofficial committee member, providing me with generous and instructive comments on the majority of the dissertation. There are many others to whom I am grateful for support with and valuable discussion on, parts of my project, and its earlier and attendant stages.
    [Show full text]
  • Contrast and Contrastivism: the Logic of Contrastive Knowledge
    University of Calgary PRISM: University of Calgary's Digital Repository Arts Arts Research & Publications 2010 Contrast and Contrastivism: The Logic of Contrastive Knowledge Scobbie, Taylor http://hdl.handle.net/1880/51000 Thesis Downloaded from PRISM: https://prism.ucalgary.ca Contrast and Contrastivism: The Logic of Contrastive Knowledge Taylor Scobbie - 0 - Table of Contents I. Introduction ........................................................................................................................ - 2 - II. Contrast ............................................................................................................................... - 5 - A. Contrastive Sentences ..................................................................................................... - 5 - B. Knowledge of Contrastive Sentences .............................................................................. - 9 - III. Contrastivism .................................................................................................................... - 11 - A. Historical Context ........................................................................................................... - 11 - B. Contrastivism ................................................................................................................. - 13 - C. Contrastivism and Epistemic Logic ................................................................................ - 22 - D. Compatibility .............................................................................................................
    [Show full text]
  • Herman Cappelen
    CSMN & IFIKK GEORG MORGENSTIERNES HUS HERMAN UNIVERSITY OF OSLO [email protected] CAPPELEN PRIMARY POSITIONS CHAIR PROFESSORSHIP, PHILOSOPHY 2020- University of Hong Kong PROFESSOR OF PHILOSOPHY 2015-2020 University of Oslo PROFESSOR AND ARCHÉ CHAIR 2007 – 2015 University of St Andrews CUF LECTURER, FELLOW AND TUTOR IN PHILOSOPHY 2006-2007 Somerville College and University of Oxford ASSOCIATE PROFESSOR OF PHILOSOPHY 2003 – 2005 Vassar College, New York ASSISTANT PROFESSOR OF PHILOSOPHY 1996 – 2003 Vassar College, New York LONG-TERM AFFILIATED POSITIONS PROFESSOR OF PHILOSOPHY (0.2 TIME) 2015-2020 University of St Andrews RESEARCH DIRECTOR, CSMN AT OSLO 2007 – 2017 University of Oslo 1 QUALIFICATIONS PhD In Philosophy. 1996 University of California, Berkeley Dissertation: “The Metaphysics of Words and the Semantics of Quotation”. Advisors: C. Chihara, S. Neale, and J. Searle BA in Philosophy, Politics, and Economics. 1989 Balliol College, Oxford MAJOR RESEARCH GRANTS • ConsciousBrainConcepts – 16 million NOK (PI: J. Storm, with collaborators from medicine, philosophy and psychology) (2019- 2022) • Toppforsk for Conceptual Engineering, 25 million NOK (with Øystein Linnebo and Camilla Serck-Hanssen and Rachel Sterken). (2016-21) • CSMN, Phase II: approximately 60 million NOK over 5 years from the Norwegian Research Council (with 7 other applicants). • Rethinking Mind and Meaning: £250,000 from AHRC (PI: Juan Gomez).(2014-16) • Intuitions and Philosophical Methodology: £990.000 from AHRC (PI: Jessica Brown) (2008-12) • Contextualism and Relativism: £990.000, from AHRC (PI: Crispin Wright).(2007-10) • CSMN Phase I: approximately 60 million (NOK) over 5 years from the Norwegian Research Council (with 7 other applicants).( 2007-12) • Shared Content: Awarded 4.5 million (NOK), from The Norwegian Research Council.
    [Show full text]
  • Belief in Psyontology Cumstances (Ross & Schroeder, 2014; Schwitzgebel, 2015)
    Philosophers’ volume 20, no. 11 ow are full and partial belief related in psychology’s ontology? Imprint april 2020 H Credence-first philosophers think partial belief is more funda- mental. For example, Lockeans say that to believe P is just to have high credence in P. Whereas categorical-first philosophers make full beliefs fundamental instead. Having credence x in P might just amount to having a categorical belief that P’s probability is x, for example. Work in cognitive psychology supports a different view, however. In humans, beliefs come in both coarse and fine kinds, with neither BELIEF IN more fundamental than the other. Epistemologists who focus on one kind to the exclusion of the other, or who treat one as central and the other as an afterthought, risk toiling at a fiction. This conclusion is necessarily tentative. For one thing, the empir- PSYONTOLOGY ical work is nascent and ongoing, its results subject to revision. But more than that, it’s sometimes unclear what the present results tell us about the ontological and epistemological questions of interest to philosophers. Still, a prima facie case can be made. And making it is an essential step in bringing our best science to bear on what is, at least in part, an empirical question. 1. Background Jonathan Weisberg 1.1 Why Monism? Why think one kind of belief is more fundamental than the other? It’s not just that Anglophone philosophers use ‘belief’ for both kinds, so University of Toronto they must really be the same thing deep down.1 It’s rather what causes us to use ‘belief’ for both attitudes.
    [Show full text]
  • Stephen Pepper's World Hypotheses: Season 1, Episode 1 Welcome To
    Stephen Pepper’s World Hypotheses: Season 1, Episode 1 Welcome to the first episode of the Stephen Pepper thread. The focus of this post is World Hypotheses, Chapters 1-4. My reflections today are largely confined to definitional matters, but I also hope to set the stage for an examination (in my next post) of Pepper’s “root metaphor” theory. Perhaps the clearest path into Pepper’s thought is to consider the place where most of us began our intellectual journey: common sense. For Pepper, common sense includes “the sorts of things we think of when we ordinarily read the papers…or the sort of things we see and hear and smell and feel as we walK along the street or in the country…” (p. 39). Pepper considers common sense as a loose synonym for Plato’s notion of “opinion” (p. 39). I’m also reminded of the “natural attitude” described by phenomenologists. For Pepper, the world of common sense can be characterized as “secure” in the sense that it is “never lacking” – i.e., we can always fall back on it: • “No cognition can sink lower than common sense, for when we completely give up trying to Know anything, then is precisely when we Know things in the common-sense way. In that lies the security of common sense” (p. 43). But, in spite of its security, common sense is also “cognitively irritable”: • “The materials of common sense are changing, unchanging, contradictory, vague, rigid, muddled, melodramatically clear, unorganized, rationalized, dogmatic, shrewdly dubious, recKlessly dubious, piously felt, playfully enjoyed, and so forth.
    [Show full text]
  • Quine's Naturalized Epistemology, Epistemic Normativity
    Quine’s Naturalized Epistemology, Epistemic Normativity and the Gettier Problem Dr. Qilin Li ([email protected]; [email protected]) The Department of Philosophy, Peking University Beiijing, P. R. China 100871 W. V. Quine is one of the most prominent advocates of the naturalistic approach to epistemology and he argues that epistemology should be naturalized and transformed into a sub-discipline of psychology and hence a chapter in science. In his famous paper “Epistemology Naturalized,” Quine starts to compare epistemology with the logical and set-theoretical studies of the foundations of mathematics. Similar to the studies of the foundations of mathematics, as Quine suggests, epistemological studies, which are “concerned with the foundation of science” (Quine 1968, p. 69), can be divided into two sorts— one is conceptual and the other is doctrinal. Quine further argues that the conceptual ones are concerned with meaning of our material object concepts, which are clarified by reducing them into sense experience concepts; and, on the other hand, the doctrinal ones are concerned with truth of our material object beliefs, which are established by deducing them from the premises about observations. According to Quine, both sorts of studies in traditional epistemology are doomed, since traditional epistemology shows no real advantages over sciences, especially psychology. Thus, Quine advocates that we should abandon this traditional epistemology; but this does not imply the death of epistemology per se, since epistemology can still go on “in a new setting and a clarified status” (Quine 1 1968, p.82). We should embrace this new epistemology, i.e., naturalized epistemology, which “falls into place as a chapter of psychology and hence of natural science” (Quine 1968, p.82), in other words, unlike traditional epistemology, new epistemology “is contained in natural science, as a chapter of psychology” (Quine 1968, p.83).
    [Show full text]
  • Pragmatism, Holism, and the Concept of Law
    Pragmatism, Holism, and the Concept of Law Adam Michał Dyrda* equally, most commonplace) accusations against a cer- Abstract tain legal theory is the ‘methodological objection’ (MO). In its general form, it is as follows: When discussing O. W. Holmes’s answer to the question What constitutes the law? Morton White underlines the (MO) The discussed theory fails because it uses the fact that Holmes’s inquiry didn’t focus on developing the wrong methodology and asks the wrong questions, concept of law. White states: ‘…Holmes said little in The which precludes the theory from reaching the right Path of the Law about the notion of legal authority, perhaps (adequate) conclusions. Without putting our ques- because he was interested not in what he called a “useless tions in the right way, we cannot grasp any substan- quintessence of all legal systems” but in “an accurate anat- tial answers, i.e. such answers that (at least) could omy of one”’. Such ambition (or lack of ambition) is charac- have a claim to adequacy.1 teristic of many pragmatic enterprises in the field of jurispru- dence. However, sometimes the opposition between legal It seems, then, that for researchers who use this argu- pragmatism and other legal theories is built upon a refer- ment against a particular theory T, the theory T fails on ence to the notion of the ‘nature’ or ‘essence’ of law. Many its own grounds because it asks the wrong questions legal philosophers who aim to reveal the very ‘nature of and, thus, receives inadequate answers. However, it is law’ (or ‘the concept of law’ as H.
    [Show full text]
  • The Rationality Postulate in Economics: Its Ambiguity, Its Deficiency and Its Evolutionary Alternative
    Walter Eucken Institut ORDO Constitutio in Libertate The Rationality Postulate in Economics: Its Ambiguity, its Deficiency and its Evolutionary Alternative Viktor J. Vanberg 03/3 Freiburger Diskussionspapiere zur Ordnungsökonomik Freiburg Discussion Papers on Constitutional Economics Institut für Allgemeine Wirtschaftsforschung Abteilung für Wirtschaftspolitik Albert-Ludwigs-Universität Freiburg i. Br. ISSN 1437-1510 The Rationality Postulate in Economics: Its Ambiguity, its Deficiency and its Evolutionary Alternative Viktor J. Vanberg 03/3 Albert-Ludwigs-Universität Freiburg und Walter Eucken Institut, Freiburg [email protected] Freiburger Diskussionspapiere zur Ordnungsökonomik Freiburg Discussionpapers on Constitutional Economics 03/3 ISSN 1437-1510 Walter Eucken Institut, Goethestr. 10, D-79100 Freiburg i. Br. Tel.Nr.: +49 +761 / 79097 0; Fax.Nr.: +49 +761 / 79097 97 http://www.walter-eucken-institut.de Institut für Allgemeine Wirtschaftsforschung; Abteilung für Wirtschaftspolitik; Albert-Ludwigs-Universität Freiburg, D-79085 Freiburg i. Br. Tel.Nr.: +49 +761 / 203 2317; Fax.Nr.: +49 +761 / 203 2322 http://www.vwl.uni-freiburg.de/fakultaet/wipo/ The Rationality Postulate in Economics: Its Ambiguity, its ∗ Deficiency and its Evolutionary Alternative by Viktor J. Vanberg Albert-Ludwigs-Universität Freiburg Wirtschafts- und Verhaltenswissenschaftliche Fakultät Abteilung Wirtschaftspolitik und Walter Eucken Institut 1. Introduction 2. Rationality Principle vs. Rationality Hypotheses 3. Gary S. Becker’s Economic Approach to Human Behavior: Rationality Principle or Rationality Hypothesis? 4. The ‘Economic Approach’ Between Rationality Principle and Rationality Hypotheses 5. An Evolutionary Alternative to the Rational Choice Paradigm 6. J.H. Holland’s Theory of Rule-Based Adaptive Agents 7. Rationality and Markets 8. Conclusion Abstract: Though the rationality postulate is generally considered the paradigmatic core of economics, there is little agreement about its specific content and methodological status.
    [Show full text]