Disorder As “Pseudo-Idea”

Total Page:16

File Type:pdf, Size:1020Kb

Disorder As “Pseudo-Idea” Disorder as “Pseudo-Idea” Steven Angelides is Honorary Senior In the tradition of Western metaphysics, Research Fellow in the Department of Modern the concepts of “order” and “disorder” invoke— indeed, are constituted by and constitutive of— History, Politics and International Relations at 1 Macquarie University, Australia. He is the sequential and dichotomous logics. Within author of A History of Bisexuality (2001) and these logics order functions as the privileged is completing a book entitled The Fear of term, the norm, that which is primordial and Child Sexuality. Preliminary work from this prior to the differences that go by the name of manuscript, published in GLQ, was awarded disorders. Disorders figure not only as second- the 2004 MLA Crompton-Noll Award for best ary, temporary, or erroneous re-iterations of essay in lesbian, gay, and queer studies. prior orders (biological, psychological, epistemological, or social). Disorders also figure—as the prefix of “dis” suggests—as Abstract negations of these orders. Disorder acts, in This essay deconstructs the order/disorder other words, against the “natural” or binary. Drawing on the work of Henri Bergson, normative order(s) of life. Where order is it replaces the idea of disorder with the con- naturalized, idealized, and perpetually pursued, cept of two positive orders. The essay con- disorder is lamented, depreciated, or cludes with a philosophical example of how we might reconceive the biomedical opposition of pathologized as something to be corrected, normality/pathology without relying on the cured, or transcended, if not in the present idea of disorder. tense then in an imaginary future order. But what is this notion of disorder that functions as order’s negation? Of what does it consist? Résumé Cet essai déconstruit le concept binaire de And what is its relationship to order? normal/trouble. En se basant sur le travail Questions about the epistemological d’Henri Bergson, il remplace l’idée du trouble status of the pairing of order and disorder are avec le concept de deux « normativités » anything but abstract and immaterial. Notions of positives. L’essai conclut en offrant un exemple order and disorder are much more than philosophique sur comment re-concevoir ideational. Ideas and concepts are, as quantum l’opposition biomédicale de normalité/ path- theorist Karen Barad (2007) notes (following ologie, sans avoir recours à l’idée du trouble. Niels Bohr), part of “material-discursive apparatuses” which are themselves “formative of matter and meaning” (146). In other words, ideas of order and disorder are intrinsic to the material structures and practices that produce what come to be known as individuals and populations, just as these ideas assemble, organize, govern, and give meaning and affective depth to human lives. This is nowhere more apparent than in the material- discursive apparatus that is the Diagnostic and Statistical Manual of Mental Disorders (DSM). Far from a directory of inconsequential and abstract technical jargon, the DSM 4th edition comprises concepts of mental disorder that profoundly shape the embodied realities of human life, happiness, suffering, and even death. Alterations to meanings of disorders correspondingly produce alterations to the sub- stance and liveability of human life. 10 www.msvu.ca/atlantis ■□ 35.2, 2011 This essay is an attempt not to map commonplace, “the idea of order itself is the effects of categories of disorder on either briefly sketched, implied, or it is ignored individual lives, but to contribute to one such altogether” (8). This is more than a little un- epistemological alteration to the very notion settling, especially given the prevalence of of disorder itself; an alteration that might clear the term disorder as a descriptor and the ground for profound transformations of definition for innumerable behaviours, identities, human life. It is divided into three parts, two conditions, and states of being. So what of which correspond roughly to two moves of exactly is order? To be sure, it has multiple deconstruction—reversal and displacement— meanings. At its simplest, we might think of and the final section, which considers, via the order, following the OED, as “sequence or work of Georges Canguilhem, an example of succession in space or time,” as “the course how we might reconceive the biomedical or method of occurrence or action,” or as an opposition of normality/pathology without relying “arrangement found in the existing con- on the idea of disorder. stitution of things” (1459‒1460). Implicit here are notions of complexity and heterogeneity Order and Its Other(s) (i.e., an entity or system having distinct parts). It seems obvious, perhaps even Pure homogeneity is not ordered according to necessary, to begin a discussion of disorder standard logic, it would seem, because there by first considering the notion of order. is no differentiation, no arrangement, and no The concept of order is fundamental sequence. There is, rather, only uniformity. to Western thought and to thought itself. It is Usually, some notion of lawfulness or necessity central to perception, to action, to organization, is implicit or added to the definition of order, to categorization, to language, to causality, to such that the parts of an entity or system are the event, to the phenomenon, and to governed or patterned by some ordering communication. As physicists David Bohm principle. Rudolph Arnheim, for example, and David Peat (2000) note, the “notion of defines order as “the degree and kind of order extends beyond the confines of a lawfulness governing the relations among the particular theory; permeates the whole infra- parts of an entity” (in Lorand 2000, 9). structure of concepts, ideas, and values; and Similarly, order is usually assumed to be a con- enters the very framework in which human dition of logical or comprehensible arrange- thought is understood and action carried out” ment among the separate elements of a (104‒5). Two of the hegemonic traditions of group. Western thought, namely metaphysics and What unites (or perhaps “orders”) any rationalist science, are both made possible concept of order, however, is the idea that it by, and are centrally concerned with, order: can be defined in a single concept. This orders of nature and orders of logic, orders of assumption of only one type of order is endemic experience and orders of meaning, practical to rationalistic science and metaphysics, and orders and ideal orders, unknown orders and it operates as a default or foundational con- known orders, existent orders and orders cept of these paradigms. That is, at its simplest, longed for. Thought, knowledge, human only one kind of order exists, and this is practice, and life are reflective of both the opposed binarily to disorder. Of course, within drive to order and the drive to apprehend the metaphysical schema, it is certainly order. Thought, knowledge, practice, and life granted that there are multiple sub-orders or are reflective of order itself. types of order. However, all sub-orders and However, despite, or as philosopher types of order are conceptually derivative of, Ruth Lorand suggests, perhaps because of, its or secondary to, some prior notion of order as centrality to thought, knowledge, experience, a singular concept. Order resides, it appears, and action, order is a concept that has re- at the origin of all sequence, and sequence is ceived relatively scant philosophical con- the essence of order. The definition of order sideration. Lorand (2000) notes that while dis- is thus circular, tautologous, and self-referential: cussions of “existence, status, kinds and order is part of its own definition. measure of order in a given system” are www.msvu.ca/atlantis ■□ 35.2, 2011 11 The distinction between order and groups, and societies that take disorder as an disorder usually operates as a classical binary organizing principle. The categorization and opposition. The binary functions as a hierarchy: treatment of individuals defined by the DSM IV order precedes disorder; order is privileged is one of the more obvious examples of this. over disorder; order sets the terms of Throughout the last several decades, disorder’s meaning; and order requires a a number of social movements have emerged contrast with its subordinate to establish its to challenge hegemonic constructions of superiority. In this way the order/disorder binary apparently “disordered” subjectivities, be- is exemplary of the Derridean “metaphysics haviours, conditions, and bodies. Among these of presence.” Order becomes what Jacques prominent movements are, of course, anti- Derrida (1976) would call the “transcendental psychiatry, gay liberation (and queer), and signified” (49). Its presence is implied by, and disability movements of the 1960s, 70s, and figured as, the foundation of, all meaning. 80s. (Feminism is another obvious move- Disorder, in contrast, is the absence of order ment.) As we know, anti-psychiatry led the (and thus meaning); it is order’s negation. Of way by launching an attack on the normative course, within metaphysics, even though terrain of mental health. R.D. Laing, Thomas disorder is constituted as the negation of Szasz, Michel Foucault, and others fiercely order, like order itself, disorder is assumed to contested notions of mental disorder and be a reality—even if only an intuited one. illness, normality, and pathology. (Unfortunately, Disorder exists, so it is assumed, despite the this does not seem to have inhibited the fact that the dualistic logic of its framing seemingly ever-expanding list of mental dis- constructs it as an absence of order. It is the orders in the DSM IV.) Drawing on anti- reality of the other to order, even if that is not psychiatry, gay liberation applied this critique to possible to conceptualize. Epistemologically, dominant notions of homosexuality as a mental therefore, disorder is almost always the disorder and pathology. And disability activists projection of absence onto the Other (by and scholars have rigorously challenged pre- other I mean other entities, other conditions, vailing notions of disability as an individualized other states of affairs, other people).
Recommended publications
  • New Yorkers Had Been Anticipating His Visit for Months. at Columbia
    INTRODUCTION ew Yorkers had been anticipating his visit for months. At Columbia University, where French intellectual Henri Bergson (1859–1941) Nwas to give twelve lectures in February 1913, expectations were es- pecially high. When first approached by officials at Columbia, he had asked for a small seminar room where he could directly interact with students and faculty—something that fit both his personality and his speaking style. But Columbia sensed a potential spectacle. They instead put him in the three- hundred-plus-seat lecture theater in Havemeyer Hall. That much attention, Bergson insisted, would make him too nervous to speak in English without notes. Columbia persisted. So, because rhetorical presentation was as impor- tant to him as the words themselves, Bergson delivered his first American lec- ture entirely in French.1 Among the standing-room-only throng of professors and editors were New York journalists and “well-dressed” and “overdressed” women, all fumbling to make sense of Bergson’s “Spiritualité et Liberté” that slushy evening. Between their otherwise dry lines of copy, the reporters’ in- credulity was nearly audible as they recorded how hundreds of New Yorkers strained to hear this “frail, thin, small sized man with sunken cheeks” practi- cally whisper an entire lecture on metaphysics in French.2 That was only a prelude. Bergson’s “Free Will versus Determinism” lec- ture on Tuesday, February 4th—once again delivered in his barely audible French—caused the academic equivalent of a riot. Two thousand people attempted to cram themselves into Havemeyer. Hundreds of hopeful New Yorkers were denied access; long queues of the disappointed snaked around the building and lingered in the slush.
    [Show full text]
  • INTUITION .THE PHILOSOPHY of HENRI BERGSON By
    THE RHYTHM OF PHILOSOPHY: INTUITION ·ANI? PHILOSO~IDC METHOD IN .THE PHILOSOPHY OF HENRI BERGSON By CAROLE TABOR FlSHER Bachelor Of Arts Taylor University Upland, Indiana .. 1983 Submitted ~o the Faculty of the Graduate College of the · Oklahoma State University in partial fulfi11ment of the requirements for . the Degree of . Master of Arts May, 1990 Oklahoma State. Univ. Library THE RHY1HM OF PlllLOSOPHY: INTUITION ' AND PfnLoSOPlllC METHOD IN .THE PHILOSOPHY OF HENRI BERGSON Thesis Approved: vt4;;. e ·~lu .. ·~ests AdVIsor /l4.t--OZ. ·~ ,£__ '', 13~6350' ii · ,. PREFACE The writing of this thesis has bee~ a tiring, enjoyable, :Qustrating and challenging experience. M.,Bergson has introduced me to ·a whole new way of doing . philosophy which has put vitality into the process. I have caught a Bergson bug. His vision of a collaboration of philosophers using his intuitional m~thod to correct, each others' work and patiently compile a body of philosophic know: ledge is inspiring. I hope I have done him justice in my description of that vision. If I have succeeded and that vision catches your imagination I hope you Will make the effort to apply it. Please let me know of your effort, your successes and your failures. With the current challenges to rationalist epistemology, I believe the time has come to give Bergson's method a try. My discovery of Bergson is. the culmination of a development of my thought, one that started long before I began my work at Oklahoma State. However, there are some people there who deserv~. special thanks for awakening me from my ' "''' analytic slumber.
    [Show full text]
  • NYU Paris PHIL-UA 9026 C01, History of French Philosophy
    NYU Paris PHIL-UA 9026 C01, History of French philosophy Instructor Information ● Philippe Lusson ● office hours TBD ● [email protected] Course Information ● PHIL-UA 9026 C01 ● History of French Philosophy ● An overview of important developments in French philosophy from the 16th century to the 1960s. We will pay close attention this semester to the relationship between the self and others. We will look at the debates that followed the rediscovery of Ancient philosophy and the Copernican revolution with Descartes’ rationalist and individualistic philosophy, Condillac’s empiricist critique, whose role for language brings the self into a web of social relations, and the growing recognition of the problem of society with Rousseau. We will then look at Henri Bergson’s reaction to the rise of the empirical sciences in the 19th century and especially at his distinction between the deep self and the social self. We will deepen our appreciation of the issues Bergson highlights with readings from René Girard and Jean Baudrillard, and we will look for possible solutions in Alexandre Kojève’s reading of Hegel and in Jean-Paul Sartre and Simone de Beauvoir’s distinctive development of existentialism. ● No prerequisites ● Lecture Tuesday 5 to 6:30pm, recitation sections Thursday 3-4:30pm and 5-6:30pm ● NYU Paris, room TBD Course Overview and Goals Upon Completion of this Course, students will be able to: ● get a sense of the historical evolution of philosophy since the 16th-century, ● see how French philosophers developed some of the key ideas and movements in that history ● identity and debate important issues philosophers still discuss today ● learn how to assess the strength and weaknesses of arguments, ● engage in constructive philosophical discussion, give reasons, and raise objections, Page 1 ● perfect their skills in argumentative writing.
    [Show full text]
  • Bergsoniana, 1
    Bergsoniana 1 | 2021 Reassessing Bergson The Duration of History in Bergson Caterina Zanfi Electronic version URL: https://journals.openedition.org/bergsoniana/435 DOI: 10.4000/bergsoniana.435 ISSN: 2800-874X Publisher Société des amis de Bergson Electronic reference Caterina Zanfi, “The Duration of History in Bergson ”, Bergsoniana [Online], 1 | 2021, Online since 01 July 2021, connection on 14 September 2021. URL: http://journals.openedition.org/bergsoniana/435 ; DOI: https://doi.org/10.4000/bergsoniana.435 Les contenus de la revue sont mis à disposition selon les termes de la Licence Creative Commons Attribution 4.0 International. THE DURATION OF HISTORY IN BERGSON Caterina ZANFI I. Is There a Philosophy of History in Bergson? Bergson has often been criticised for not thinking history. Although he developed one of the most relevant philosophies of time of the last century, his rare statements on history are said to betray an impoverished sense of properly historical issues. Moreover, this criticism is made concerning both his consideration of history as the becoming of human reality and his consideration of historical knowledge and narrative — of both history and historiography. It was first articulated in the 1930s by Marxist intellectuals like Paul Nizan (who was to perish in the fight against Nazism in 1940). In 1932, Nizan published a polemic entitled The Watchdogs against the so called “Philosophers of the Established Order.” There he includes Bergson among the philosophers who are “against history” (Nizan 1965, 29),1 considering him incapable of understanding the time and space in which philosophical ideas arise and therefore lacking in sensitivity for the material and embodied aspects of the historical becoming of philosophy.
    [Show full text]
  • Philosophy of Time: a Slightly Opinionated Introduction
    Philosophy of time: A slightly opinionated introduction Florian Fischer There are several intertwined debates in the area of contemporary philos- ophy of time. One field of inquiry is the nature of time itself. Presentists think that only the present moment exists whereas eternalists believe that all of (space-)time exists on a par. The second main field of inquiry is the question of how objects persist through time. The endurantist claims that objects are three-dimensional wholes, which persist by being wholly1 present, whereas the perdurantist thinks that objects are four- dimensional and that their temporal parts are the bearers of properties. The third debate in the field of contemporary philosophy of time is about tense- versus tenseless theory. Tensers are at odds with detensers about the status of the linguistic reference to the present moment. These are only very crude characterizations and it is even disputed by some ad- vocates of the corresponding positions that they are accurate. However this very sketchy picture already reveals a fundamental difference: The eternalism/presentism and endurance/perdurance discussions belong to the field of metaphysics, whereas tense is in the first instance a linguistic phenomenon. Among the many fields of philosophy, there are two that are more intimately interconnected than most but whose practi- tioners have too long pursued relatively independent paths. On the one hand, there are philosophers of language, who have devoted much attention to indexicals (`now', etc.), tem- poral operators (`it has been the case that', etc.), and tensed sentences. On the other hand, there are the philosophers of tensed and tenseless time (also called A-time or B-time, dynamic time or static time, etc.).
    [Show full text]
  • The Organism – Reality Or Fiction?
    The organism – reality or fiction? organism CHARLES T WOLFE SCOUTS THE ANSWERS forum/ hat is an “organism”? A state We murder to dissect, or as the famous physicist of matter, or a particular type Niels Bohr warned, we may kill the organism of living being chosen as an with our too-detailed measurements. experimental object, like the Historically, the word “organism” emerged in Wfruit fly or the roundworm c. elegans, which the late seventeenth and early eighteenth centu- 96 are “model organisms”? Organisms are real, in ries, in particular, in the debate between the a trivial sense, since flies and Tasmanian tigers philosopher and polymath Gottfried Wilhelm and Portuguese men-o-war are (or were, in the Leibniz and the chemist and physician Georg- case of the Tasmanian tiger) as real as tables and Ernest Stahl, the author of a 1708 essay On the chairs and planets. But at the same time, they difference between mechanism and organism. are meaningful constructs, as when we describe Both Leibniz and Stahl agree that organisms Hegel or Whitehead as philosophers of organism are not the same as mere mechanisms, but in the sense that they insist on the irreducible they differ on how to account for this differ- properties of wholes – sometimes, living wholes ence. For Leibniz, it is more of a difference in in particular. In addition, the idea of organism complexity (for him, organisms are machines is sometimes appealed to in a polemical way, as which are machines down to their smallest parts), when biologists or philosophers angrily oppose a whereas for Stahl, the organism is a type of whole more “holistic” sense of organism to a seemingly governed by the soul (at all levels of our bodily cold-hearted, analytic and dissective attitude functioning, from the way I blink if an object associated with “mechanism” and “reductionism”.
    [Show full text]
  • 'Continental' Philosophy
    Russell’s critique of Bergson and the divide between ‘Analytic’ and ‘Continental’ philosophy Final draft version of article published in the Balkan Journal of Philosophy, Vol. 3, No. 1, pp. 123- 134, 2011. Andreas Vrahimis Birkbeck, University of London 2010 Russell’s critique of Bergson and the divide between ‘Analytic’ and ‘Continental’ philosophy Abstract: In 1911, Bergson visited Britain for a number of lectures which led to his increasing popularity. Russell personally encountered Bergson during his lecture at University College London on 28 October, and on 30 October Bergson attended one of Russell’s lectures. Russell went on to write a number of critical articles on Bergson, contributing to the hundreds of publications on Bergson which ensued following these lectures. Russell’s critical writings have been seen as part of a history of controversies between so-called ‘Continental’ and ‘Analytic’ philosophers in the twentieth century. Yet Russell’s engagement with Bergson’s thought comes as a response to a particular British form of Bergsonism and is involved with the wider phenomenon of the British import of Bergsonism (by figures connected in different ways to Russell, such as Hulme, Wildon Carr or Eliot). Though this may challenge the view of Russell and Bergson as enacting an early version of the ‘Analytic’-‘Continental’ divide, there are however some particular characterisations of Bergson by Russell which contribute to the subsequent formation of the ‘rotten scene’ (Glendinning 2006: 69) of the divide in the second half of the twentieth century. Keywords: Russell; Bergson; Analytic; Continental; divide 1. Introduction The twentieth century has seen the rise of an image of Western academic philosophy as divided between two predominant camps, one ‘Continental’ and the other ‘Analytic’.
    [Show full text]
  • Durée and Temporality : a Defense of Bergson's
    DURÉE AND TEMPORALITY: A DEFENSE OF BERGSON’S CONCEPTION OF TIME DURACIÓN Y TEMPORALIDAD: UNA DEFENSA DE LA CONCEPCIÓN DEL TIEMPO DE BERGSON JORGE ALEJANDRO FLÓREZ RESTREPO* Universidad de Caldas, Colombia. [email protected] RECIBIDO EL 18 DE JULIO DE 2015, APROBADO EL 30 DE OCTUBRE DE 2015 RESUMEN ABSTRACT Este artículo es una defensa del concepto This paper is a defense of Bergson’s de tiempo en Bergson, en contra de las conception of time against Heidegger’s acusaciones de Heidegger en Ser y tiempo. accusation on Being and Time. There, Allí, Heidegger acusó el concepto de tiempo Heidegger accused Bergson’s conception bergsoniano de incurrir en el mismo error of committing the same mistake of de la tradición filosófica al tomar el tiempo the traditional conception of time as a como una sucesión espacial de “ahoras”. spatialized succession of “nows.” This is Esta es una acusación injusta porque los an unfair accusation, for Bergson’s main conceptos de tiempo en Bergson, duración concepts of Duration and Élan Vital are y Élan vital, son precisamente opuestos precisely opposite to that. In fact, Bergson’s a la concepción tradicional. De hecho, concept of time coincides with Heidegger’s el concepto de tiempo según Bergson conception of Temporality which is coincide con la concepción heideggeriana essential in his existential analytical and de temporalidad, la cual es esencial fundamental ontology. para su analítica existencial y ontología fundamental. PALABRAS CLAVE KEY WORDS Bergson, Heidegger, tiempo, duración, Bergson, Heidegger, time, duration, Élan Élan Vital, temporalidad. vital, temporality. * orcid.org/0000-0003-2346-0926 Discusiones Filosóficas.
    [Show full text]
  • The Bergsonian Moment: Science and Spirit in France, 1874-1907
    THE BERGSONIAN MOMENT: SCIENCE AND SPIRIT IN FRANCE, 1874-1907 by Larry Sommer McGrath A dissertation submitted to Johns Hopkins University in conformity with the requirements for the degree of Doctor of Philosophy Baltimore, Maryland June, 2014 © 2014 Larry Sommer McGrath All Rights Reserved Intended to be blank ii Abstract My dissertation is an intellectual and cultural history of a distinct movement in modern Europe that I call “scientific spiritualism.” I argue that the philosopher Henri Bergson emerged from this movement as its most celebrated spokesman. From the 1874 publication of Émile Boutroux’s The Contingency of the Laws of Nature to Bergson’s 1907 Creative Evolution, a wave of heterodox thinkers, including Maurice Blondel, Alfred Fouillée, Jean-Marie Guyau, Pierre Janet, and Édouard Le Roy, gave shape to scientific spiritualism. These thinkers staged a rapprochement between two disparate formations: on the one hand, the rich heritage of French spiritualism, extending from the sixteenth- and seventeeth-century polymaths Michel de Montaigne and René Descartes to the nineteenth-century philosophes Maine de Biran and Victor Cousin; and on the other hand, transnational developments in the emergent natural and human sciences, especially in the nascent experimental psychology and evolutionary biology. I trace the influx of these developments into Paris, where scientific spiritualists collaboratively rejuvenated the philosophical and religious study of consciousness on the basis of the very sciences that threatened the authority of philosophy and religion. Using original materials gathered in French and Belgian archives, I argue that new reading communities formed around scientific journals, the explosion of research institutes, and the secularization of the French education system, brought about this significant, though heretofore neglected wave of thought.
    [Show full text]
  • Bergsoniana, 1
    Bergsoniana 1 | 2021 Reassessing Bergson What Bergson Should Have Said to Einstein Steven Savitt Electronic version URL: https://journals.openedition.org/bergsoniana/333 DOI: 10.4000/bergsoniana.333 ISSN: 2800-874X Publisher Société des amis de Bergson Electronic reference Steven Savitt, “What Bergson Should Have Said to Einstein”, Bergsoniana [Online], 1 | 2021, Online since 01 July 2021, connection on 14 September 2021. URL: http://journals.openedition.org/bergsoniana/ 333 ; DOI: https://doi.org/10.4000/bergsoniana.333 Les contenus de la revue sont mis à disposition selon les termes de la Licence Creative Commons Attribution 4.0 International. WHAT BERGSON SHOULD HAVE SAID TO EINSTEIN1 Steven SAVITT Let me begin by repeating (changing only the name) a paragraph from a recent paper by David Chalmers: I should say that I am not a historian or a serious scholar of Bergson. These are merely some speculative remarks not well-grounded in scholarly attention to Bergson’s texts. But I think the speculative question is interesting. I’m going to sketch one speculative answer. I’m going to be interested to hear from people who know much more about Bergson than I do about whether this speculation has any remote plausibility. If the historical speculation has none, as may well be possible, I think there is still a very interesting philosophical project in the neighbourhood which is itself worthy of attention (Chalmers 2018). My speculative remarks concern the famous debate between Henri Bergson and Albert Einstein that took place in Paris on 6 April 1922. This encounter has recently received a book-length treatment (Canales 2015), but little of the substance of the debate was actually reported in it.
    [Show full text]
  • Bertrand Russell's Criticism of Bergson's Views About
    FILOZOFIA ___________________________________________________________________________ Roč. 68, 2013, č. 10 BERTRAND RUSSELL’S CRITICISM OF BERGSON’S VIEWS ABOUT CONTINUITY AND DISCRETENESS VESSELIN PETROV, Institute for the Study of Societies and Knowledge, Bulgarian Academy of Sciences, Sofia, Bulgaria PETROV, V.: Bertrand Russell’s Criticism of Bergson’s Views about Continuity and Discreteness FILOZOFIA 68, 2013, No 10, p. 890-904 This paper is devoted to Bertrand Russell’s criticism of Henri Bergson’s philosophy. It traces out the origins of that criticism and analyzes its essence, reasons and devel- opment in Russell’s works. Because of the importance of the concepts of space and time for Bergson’s philosophy and, in turn, the importance of continuity and dis- creteness for the understanding of space and time, the central part of the analysis concerns the views of both philosophers on continuity and discreteness, including Zeno’s paradoxes. The main thesis of the paper is that Russell’s criticism of Berg- son’s philosophy comes, to a great extent, from Russell’s misunderstanding of Berg- son. Keywords: Bertrand Russell’ philosophy – Bergson’s philosophy – Continuity – Dis- creteness – Zeno’s paradoxes 1. Introduction. In 1911 Henri Bergson visited Great Britain to deliver several lec- th tures on his philosophy. His first meeting with Bertrand Russell happened on October 28 at one of these lectures. Two days after this initial meeting Bergson attended Russell’s lecture. However these meetings between them did not stimulate a kind of cooperation. Just the opposite, shortly after their meeting Russell initiated a severe criticism of Berg- son’s philosophy. In fact Russell’s criticism of Bergson is a reaction against the penetra- tion of Bergsonism into Great Britain that influenced British thinkers such as Wildon Carr, Thomas Eliot and Alfred North Whitehead.
    [Show full text]
  • Absurd Time: Understanding Camus' Quantitative Ethics Through
    6 Absurd Time Absurd Time: Understanding Camus’ Quantitative Ethics Through Bergsonian Duration Thomas Ruan “Only through time time is conquered” T.S. Eliot In The Myth of Sisyphus, Albert Camus tries to work through what he calls the “one truly serious philosophical problem”: sui- cide (3). He begins by noting that the human experience is funda- mentally marked by absurdity, which he defines as the opposi- tion between the irrational nature of the world and man's innate desire to understand it. The absurd is not merely the passive in- difference and irrationality of the world around us; it arises more specifically from our continual failure to make any kind of ade- quate sense of it. This is why Camus points out that “'It's absurd' means 'It's impossible' but also 'It's contradictory'” (29). The sim- plest way to deal with absurdity, then, is to remove one term from the equation by committing suicide. Camus resists this so- lution, because suicide fails to pay heed to the power that the ab- surd can give to our lives. By living in absurdity, and accepting its fundamental contradiction, we revolt against the temptation to shy away from existence– “that revolt gives life its value” (55). “Living is keeping the absurd alive,” and it is this affirmation of the absurdity of our condition that allows us to live purposive and meaningful lives. However Camus then makes a conclusion that seems quite troubling. He writes that, “belief in the meaning of life always implies a scale of values, a choice, our preferences.
    [Show full text]