Nobody to Shoot? Power, Structure, and Agency: a Dialogue. Journal
Total Page:16
File Type:pdf, Size:1020Kb
This article was downloaded by: On: 30 January 2009 Access details: Access Details: Free Access Publisher Routledge Informa Ltd Registered in England and Wales Registered Number: 1072954 Registered office: Mortimer House, 37-41 Mortimer Street, London W1T 3JH, UK Journal of Power Publication details, including instructions for authors and subscription information: http://www.informaworld.com/smpp/title~content=t778749998 Nobody to shoot? Power, structure, and agency: A dialogue Clarissa Hayward a; Steven Lukes b a Washington University in Saint Louis, Political Science, b New York University, Sociology, Online Publication Date: 01 April 2008 To cite this Article Hayward, Clarissa and Lukes, Steven(2008)'Nobody to shoot? Power, structure, and agency: A dialogue',Journal of Power,1:1,5 — 20 To link to this Article: DOI: 10.1080/17540290801943364 URL: http://dx.doi.org/10.1080/17540290801943364 PLEASE SCROLL DOWN FOR ARTICLE Full terms and conditions of use: http://www.informaworld.com/terms-and-conditions-of-access.pdf This article may be used for research, teaching and private study purposes. Any substantial or systematic reproduction, re-distribution, re-selling, loan or sub-licensing, systematic supply or distribution in any form to anyone is expressly forbidden. The publisher does not give any warranty express or implied or make any representation that the contents will be complete or accurate or up to date. The accuracy of any instructions, formulae and drug doses should be independently verified with primary sources. The publisher shall not be liable for any loss, actions, claims, proceedings, demand or costs or damages whatsoever or howsoever caused arising directly or indirectly in connection with or arising out of the use of this material. Journal of Power Vol. 1, No. 1, April 2008, 5–20 Nobody to shoot? Power, structure, and agency: A dialogue Clarissa Haywarda* and Steven Lukesb aWashington University in Saint Louis, Political Science; bNew York University, Sociology TaylorRPOW_A_294502.sgm10.1080/17540290801943364Journal0000-0000Original20081000000AprilClarissaHaywardchayward@wustl.edu and& of Article Francis Power (print)/0000-0000Francis 2008 (online)In this dialogue, Clarissa Hayward and Steven Lukes debate the relation among power, social structure, and human agency. The authors converge on the view that not only moral responsibility, but also political responsibility is relevant to the study of power. They disagree about how to analyze difficult cases in which some agents are clearly subject to social constraints on freedom, but no powerful actors seem responsible for their constraint. Keywords: agency; determinacy; power; responsibility; structure Concerns about human agency and about social structure have long been central to the study of power. Beginning with Michel Foucault, contemporary social and political theorists (especially, but not exclusively, theorists who self-identify as postmodernists or poststructuralists) have prob- lematized the relation among these three terms.1 In so doing, they have generated important insights – insights about the normalizing power of constructed social identities, for example – which were not thematized in the postwar power debate in Anglo-American political and social science.2 Yet they have done so while largely neglecting the normative concerns that animated that debate. Indeed, one of the striking oddities about work on power from the middle of the last century to the present day is that these two debates – the latter, which originated with the so-called ‘community power studies’ of the 1950s, and the former, largely inspired by Foucault’s genea- logical works – have developed parallel to, while only rarely engaging, one another.3 The failure of these approaches to confront each other head on represents a loss on both sides. Downloaded At: 02:36 30 January 2009 Participants in the Anglo-American power debate have yet to come to terms with Foucauldian claims about the ways identities, norms, and other social constraints typically thought of as ‘struc- tural’ differentially enable and constrain what human agents can do, and what they can be. At the same time, Foucauldians have yet to articulate a coherent normative account of the grounds on which one might criticize particular power relations, and to elaborate avenues for challenging and changing them.4 In this essay, our aim is to bring these two sets of concerns face to face. We decided to write the essay together, because we share nontrivial premises about how power shapes human free- dom, and about how social theorists and social scientists should study it. We both reject strongly determinist positions, which deny the existence and/or the importance of human agency. At the same time, we both reject naively voluntaristic views, which reduce power to the conscious and intentional actions of agents. What is more, we both share the conviction that analyzing power relations is an inherently evaluative and critical enterprise, one to which questions of freedom, domination, and hierarchy are – and should be – central.5 We decided to structure the essay as a dialogue, however, because important differences sepa- rate our views of power, structure, and agency, and because our aim is in large part to explore and to clarify (if not resolve) those differences. One of us, Steven Lukes, believes the importance of *Corresponding author. Email: [email protected] ISSN 1754-0291 print/ISSN 1754-0305 online © 2008 Taylor & Francis DOI: 10.1080/17540290801943364 http://www.informaworld.com 6 C. Hayward and S. Lukes the notion of responsibility to claims about power makes the latter, necessarily, an agent-centered concept. The powerful, by this view, are those actors (individual or collective) who can reason- ably be held responsible for limits imposed on the freedom of other actors. The other, Clarissa Hayward, thinks that because constraints typically identified as ‘structural’ are social in origin, and because their effects are very often amenable to change, they are relevant to the normative project that drives the power debate. That project is badly served, her claim is, when those who study power fail to analyze and to evaluate structural constraints on freedom that are significant, inegalitarian, and remediable. The essay proceeds as follows. In the first and second sections, we present, in abbreviated form, our arguments – first articulated in PRV and DFP – about the relation among power, social structure, and human agency. In the third and fourth, we further focus our disagreement, respond- ing to each other’s principal claims. The exchange helps to clarify the difference between our views, and it brings to light important points of agreement. Perhaps most significant among the latter is our shared belief that multiple forms of responsibility are relevant to the analysis of power relations: not just moral responsibility, understood as liability, or worthiness of blame (or of praise), but also political responsibility for those outcomes to which multiple agents contribute, without any necessarily being ‘at fault.’ The former – our differences – center on how to grapple with those cases in which some agents seem clearly to be subject to power, but no identifiable actors seem responsible for their constraint. Should such cases be analyzed, as Hayward has suggested, using the language of power and of domination, or are the latter terms, as Lukes has argued, necessarily ‘agency’ terms? 1. Power and agency (Steven Lukes) In his fine book Power: A Philosophical Analysis, Peter Morriss asks an excellent and insuffi- ciently addressed question: ‘Why do we need concepts of power?’ (2002, ch.6) What jobs, in other words, do we want concepts of power to do? What is our purpose in studying power? Morriss’ answer is threefold. We want to know, in practical contexts, what our capacities and the capacities of others are, in order to achieve desired outcomes. (As Brian Barry has remarked, the Downloaded At: 02:36 30 January 2009 CIA needs to know whom to bribe). We want to know, in moral contexts, whom to hold respon- sible (whom to blame, and I would add, whom to praise) for outcomes that affect the interests of others. Moreover, we want to know, in evaluative contexts, when we are judging social systems, to what extent they give their citizens freedom from the power of others, and to what extent citi- zens have the power to meet their own needs or wants. Morriss’ question and his answers relate to power in the general sense of ‘the capacity to bring about effects.’ It is a useful exercise. His answers, however, as we will see, need some refinement and extension. In my book, PRV, I focus, more narrowly than does Morriss, on power over others and, more narrowly still, on power over others that is dominating, and yet more narrowly still, on what I call the third dimension of such power, where the power consists, not in prevailing over the opposition of others, nor in imposing an agenda on them, but in influencing their desires, beliefs and judg- ments in ways that work against their interests.6 This third dimension of power is usually hidden from direct observation; it has to be inferred via the postulation of relevant counterfactuals, to the effect that but for the exercise of the power in question those subject to it would have thought and acted otherwise, in accordance with their ‘real’ interests. Considering this third dimension of power, raises two sets of difficult questions. The first concerns the ‘subjects’ of power: that is, those actors or agents who are subject to it. The central set of questions here centers on how to justify the ascription of real interests to such subjects. The second set of questions raised by power’s third dimension concerns the ‘sources’ of power: that is, those agents or actors who have or who exercise power. Here the central set of questions centers Journal of Power 7 on whether power is to be conceived as located in agents, individual or collective, or, alternatively, in impersonal structures.