The Falsifiabtlity Criterion and the Cognitive Statws Of
Total Page:16
File Type:pdf, Size:1020Kb
The falsifiability criterion and the cognitive status of religious belief Item Type text; Thesis-Reproduction (electronic) Authors Gettman, Gary Lee, 1942- Publisher The University of Arizona. Rights Copyright © is held by the author. Digital access to this material is made possible by the University Libraries, University of Arizona. Further transmission, reproduction or presentation (such as public display or performance) of protected items is prohibited except with permission of the author. Download date 29/09/2021 14:06:51 Link to Item http://hdl.handle.net/10150/317923 THE FALSIFIABTLITY CRITERION AND THE COGNITIVE STATWS OF RELIGIONS BELIEF by Gary Lo Gettmm A Thesis Submitted to the Faculty of the DEPARTMENT OF PHILOSOPHY In Partial Fulfillment of the Requirements ■ ■ For the Degree of MASTER OF ARTS In the Graduate College THE UNIVERSITY OF ARIZONA 19 6 6 STATEMENT BY AUTHOR This thesis has been submitted in partial fulfill ment of requirements for an advanced degree at The Uni versity of Arizona and is deposited in the University Library to be made available to borrowers under rules of the Libraryo Brief quotations from this thesis are allowable without special permission, provided that accurate acknow ledgment of source is made. Requests for permission for extended quotation from or reproduction of this manuscript in whole or in part may be granted by the head of the major department or the Dean of the Graduate College when in his judgment the proposed use of the material is in the inter ests of scholarship* In all other instances, however, permission must be obtained from the author* SIGNEDs APPROVAL BY THESIS DIRECTOR This thesis has been approved on the date shown belows ROBERT L* CALDWELL Date Associate Professor of Philosophy ACKNOWLEDGMENTS I wish to express my gratitude to Pro fessor Robert Lo Caldwell who served as my advisor during the final stages of preparation* TABLE OF CONTENTS INTRODUCTIONo 0000=00000= THE HEAD-ON RESPONSE TO FLEWo = = = Basil Mitohello <,0000000 I0 Ho Crombie 000000000 THE SHIFTED-GROUND TECHNIQUEo = 0 » R o Ho Rai*@ 00000000000 Alasdair Haelntyreo 0=0000 HITCHELL°S REPLY TO HACINTYRE , = « CONCLUSIONo 000000000000 REFERENCES 00000000000 = 0 ABSTBACT The falsiflability criterion states that if any utterance is cognitive or factual, it must be capable of verification or falsificationo Religious beliefs accord ing to the sceptics, will allow nothing to falsify their claims § therefore they are non-eognitive0 Responses to the sceptic in recent analytical philo sophy have followed two approaches^ One accepts the falsi- flability criterion but denies the sceptic’s premise that religious beliefs are held unconditionally0 Facts do count against their being true5 therefore they are cognitive0 The other response agrees with the sceptic that religious beliefs are held unconditionally, thus failing the falsi- flability test, but denies that this is the only criterion for cognitive status= I reject both responses0 The first only pays "lip- service" to the sceptic’s criterion and does not let facts count in the required sense0 The second fails because accepting the unconditionality of religious beliefs forces it to repeat the sceptic’s comclusiom0 Both responses, however, are rejected, not because they fail to meet the sceptic’s objections, but because they and the sceptic are v unaware that the mistaken philosophical framework surround ing the falsiflability criterion prevents them from command ing a clear view of the use of the words 6,belief11 and M justification,,88 INTRODUCTION Even though Logical Positivism as a philosophical movement may rightfully be said to be dead, its ghost still haunts traditional systematic theology0 With the advent of the recent analytical movement associated with the name of Wittgenstein, the inadequacy of the positivist8 s wholesale rejection of religious beliefs as nonsense is now generally recognized| beyond this, however, there is little agreement as to what sense religious beliefs do haveo For some this has only led to a more sophisticated, but essentially neo- positivistic position, and for still others, this latter renewal of scepticism has sparked new efforts, in the spirit of linguistic analysis, to search for the cognitive meaning of religious beliefs on their own terms and in contexts where they are foundo Such efforts have led to a recent and lively discussion of this subject among Oxford and other British philosophers, and although their activities have not necessarily been antithetical to religious dis course, as were their positivist forebears, the question of the cognitive status of religious beliefs has not seemed readily soluble, for upon examining such beliefs in con texts where they are expressed, they discovered that it is 1 the eogmitive use in these contexts that made them appear so paradox!calo They also found that, unlike many philo sophical problems 9 such as the private language argument v other minds9 or the sense-datum theory8 which have their origin and expression only among academic circles9 their problem is a dilemma that is of urgent concern for both the lay thinker and the professionals that it is not only a problem for philosophers but also for those who “play,68 as it were 9 the religious “language-game»M Historically9 the first significant work to appear in this tradition was John Wisdom's provocative essay entitled9 “Gods,“ published in 1944„ But by far the most controversial discussions which actually initiated today's analytical interest in religious beliefs and discourse, was the symposium, "Theology and Falsification," which appeared in New Essays in Philosophical Theology in 1955° This symposium consisted, among other things, of the now quite famous sceptical challenge presented by Antony Flew in which, using an adaptation of a parable originally con ceived by Wisdom, he revitalizes the positivist's position Once upon a time two explorers came upon a clear ing in the jungle» In the clearing were growing many flowers and many weeds0 One explorer says, "Some gardener must tend this plot»” The other disagrees, "There is no gardener„" So they pitch their tents and set a watch» No gardener is ever seen* "But perhaps he is an invisible gardenero" So they set up a barbed-wire fenceo They electrify ito They patrol with bloodhoundso (For they 3 remember how Ho Go Wells°s The Invisible Man could be both smelt and touched though he could not be seeno) But no shrieks ever suggest that some intru der has received a shock= 1© movements of the wire ever betray an invisible climber» The bloodhounds never give the cry. let still the Believer is not convinced» "But there is a gardener* invisible* intangible* insensible to electric shocks* a gar dener who has no scent and makes no sound, a gar dener who comes secretly to look after the garden which he loves»68 At last the Sceptic despairs, "But what remains of your original assertion? Just how does what you call an invisible, intangible, eternally elusive gardener differ from an imagin ary gardener or even from no gardener at all?"l What Flew is attempting to illustrate through the use of this analogy is that what begins as an existential assertion of a gardener is capable of being reduced inch by inch into a statement dealing with a completely different subject than that conceived in the original assertion* What to the Believer seems to be a vast cosmological assertion, ends up being destroyed step by step by a "death by a thous- 2 and qualifications *" As an example of this type of quali fication, some people say that Christ ascended into heaven, and surely many of them picture Jesus, flanked by patriarchs and surrounded by cherubim, rising up into the sky on a cloud * But when asked whether they really mean angels on clouds defying the law of gravity, they perhaps begin to hedge and offer other pictures which do not seem so 1* Antony Flew, "Theology and Falsification," New in Philosophical Theology, p* 960 2* Ibid*, p* 97< fantastic9 yet when pressed9 they als© refuse to take literallyo If this were to continue long enough, most likely they would reach the point where they "become so deceived by their religious imagery that in the end they are only left with empty concepts and nothing, logically or empirically, upon which they can take a rational stando But there is another equally important, but logic ally opposite point to this whole analogy,, Besides the fact that the Believer’s idea of the gardener, when pressed is shown to lack any cognitive content, one can also see that his belief in the gardener has become impervious to those facts in the garden which seem to count against his assertion. For if, indeed, his feeling towards the garden includes the assertion that a gardener must tend it, then his statement must be logically equivalent to the denial of the negation of that statement, that is, that it is not the case that a gardener does not exist ( X exists s — -x exists). So anything that can be given as evidence to falsify the assertion and induce the Believer to withdraw it, admitting he was mistaken, must be considered a part or whole of the meaning of the negation of the assertion. To know the meaning of the statement, 18God is the father of all mankind,” it is also necessary to know the meaning of its negation, that is, what state of affairs would have to exist for us to know that God was not the father of all mankindo If one has mo idea what it would he like for God not to love us or not to exist* then he could continue to "maintain** the assertion no