Emergence Theory and the Demonic

Total Page:16

File Type:pdf, Size:1020Kb

Emergence Theory and the Demonic chapter 7 Emergence Theory and the Demonic In this book so far we have reviewed the history of demonology, explored social scientific analyses of possession phenomena, and inquired into philosophical theories to determine if and how spiritual realities might causally interact with the physical world. If our historical overviews have forced us to recognize the plurality of experiences with the demonic and the multiplicity of perspectives on the demonic, and if our social scien- tific assessments have insisted that we look beyond reductionist, materi- alist, or merely anthropological explanations of possession, the preceding chapter gives us some hope for forging a contemporary theology of the de- monic that is philosophically cogent, scientifically plausible, and historically responsible. We, therefore, turn in this chapter to a more complete explication of the emergence theory of the demonic initially sketched in the introduc- tion. I propound that non-reductive physicalism produces a scaffold around which to build an emergentist demonology that is philosophically and scientifically viable. Additionally, drawing on insights from the phi- losophy of the mind, emergence theory also offers some promising impli- cations for top-down causation without subscribing to supernaturalistic interventionism. I begin by providing a detailed historical and conceptual explanation of emergence theory. Then, in dialogue with Philip Clayton and Amos Yong, I propose that we can use emergence theory to develop a robust theology of the demonic. Our goal is to argue that such an emergence demonology offers a preferable model to traditionalist, dualist, and supernaturalist views on one side – various forms of which have been common views throughout the history of Christian thought – and on the other side liberal, demythologiz- ing, and reductionist approaches that are popular in academic, scientistic, and elite environments. But an emergent theology of the demonic not only offers a via media between these alternatives, it also assists in formulating a viable theory of demonic causation that is scientifically and philosophically sound for the twenty-first century. Along the way, I hope to demonstrate that such a proposal is able to embrace the gains we have made along the way in this book while avoiding the pitfalls that other demonologies have not been able to avoid. © koninklijke brill nv, leiden, ���7 | doi �0.��63/97890043506�8_008 <UN> Emergence Theory and the Demonic 191 A Emergence Theory The following begins by overviewing the origination and progression of emer- gence theory within the history of philosophical thought and then analyzes its major precepts. The third subsection will pay special attention to mind- body interaction as well as the social dimensions of an emergence theory of causality. 1 The History of Emergence Theory in Philosophical Thought In the 1920s a number of British philosophers, including George Henry Lewes, Samuel Alexander, C. Lloyd Morgan, and C.D. Broad, began to propose a new philosophical perspective that developed metaphysics in light of the burgeon- ing field of evolution.1 They coined their philosophy “Emergent Evolutionism,” and later it came to be known as emergence theory (or emergentism). Ansgar Beckermann summarizes emergent evolutionism in this manner: The whole universe develops in such a way that the configurations of its basic material elements become more and more complex. This growth in complexity, however, is not a gradual process exhaustively describ- able in purely quantitative terms. For when the complexity of material configurations reaches a certain critical level, genuinely novel properties emerge, properties that have never been instantiated before. This evolu- tionary process is moreover hierarchically structured. For complex ob- jects with their emergent properties may also combine to form still more complex entities so that further novel properties emerge.2 These early emergentists embraced evolutionary theories and attempted to find ways of incorporating these ideas into a cogent philosophical system. Emergence theory was significant because it provided an alternative to Aristotelean substance metaphysics and Cartesian-based mechanical and 1 Some suggest that the roots of emergence can be traced back to John Stuart Mill and Alexander Bain. Historians of philosophy especially recognize Mill’s A System of Logic (1843) as influential upon the early emergentists. See Achim Stephan, “Emergence – A Systematic View on Its Historical Aspects,” in Emergence or Reduction? Essays on the Prospects of Nonre- ductive Physicalism, eds. Ansgar Beckermann, Hans Flohr, and Jaegwon Kim (Berlin: Walter de Gruyter, 1992), 25. 2 Beckermann, “Introduction,” 15. <UN>.
Recommended publications
  • Stanislaw Piatkiewicz and the Beginnings of Mathematical Logic in Poland
    HISTORIA MATHEMATICA 23 (1996), 68±73 ARTICLE NO. 0005 Stanisøaw PiaËtkiewicz and the Beginnings of Mathematical Logic in Poland TADEUSZ BATO G AND ROMAN MURAWSKI View metadata, citation and similar papers at core.ac.uk brought to you by CORE Department of Mathematics and Computer Science, Adam Mickiewicz University, ul. Matejki 48/49, 60-769 PoznanÂ, Poland provided by Elsevier - Publisher Connector This paper presents information on the life and work of Stanisøaw PiaËtkiewicz (1849±?). His Algebra w logice (Algebra in Logic) of 1888 contains an exposition of the algebra of logic and its use in representing syllogisms. This was the ®rst original Polish publication on symbolic logic. It appeared 20 years before analogous works by èukasiewicz and Stamm. 1996 Academic Press, Inc. In dem Aufsatz werden Informationen zu Leben und Werk von Stanisøaw PiaËtkiewicz (1849±?) gegeben. Sein Algebra w logice (Algebra in der Logik) von 1888 enthaÈlt eine Darstel- lung der Algebra der Logik und ihre Anwendung auf die Syllogistik. PiaËtkiewicz' Schrift war die erste polnische Publikation uÈ ber symbolische Logik. Sie erschien 20 Jahre vor aÈhnlichen Arbeiten von èukasiewicz und Stamm. 1996 Academic Press, Inc. W pracy przedstawiono osobeË i dzieøo Stanisøawa PiaËtkiewicza (1849±?). W szczego lnosÂci analizuje sieË jego rozpraweË Algebra w logice z roku 1888, w kto rej zajmowaø sieË on nowymi no wczas ideami algebry logiki oraz ich zastosowaniami do sylogistyki. Praca ta jest pierwszaË oryginalnaË polskaË publikacjaË z zakresu logiki symbolicznej. Ukazaøa sieË 20 lat przed analog- icznymi pracami èukasiewicza i Stamma. 1996 Academic Press, Inc. MSC 1991 subject classi®cations: 03-03, 01A55.
    [Show full text]
  • An Introduction to Late British Associationism and Its Context This Is a Story About Philosophy. Or About Science
    Chapter 1: An Introduction to Late British Associationism and Its Context This is a story about philosophy. Or about science. Or about philosophy transforming into science. Or about science and philosophy, and how they are related. Or were, in a particular time and place. At least, that is the general area that the following narrative will explore, I hope with sufficient subtlety. The matter is rendered non-transparent by the fact that that the conclusions one draws with regard to such questions are, in part, matters of discretionary perspective – as I will try to demonstrate. My specific historical focus will be on the propagation of a complex intellectual tradition concerned with human sensation, perception, and mental function in early nineteenth century Britain. Not only philosophical opinion, but all aspects of British intellectual – and practical – life, were in the process of significant transformation during this time. This cultural flux further confuses recovery of the situated significance of the intellectual tradition I am investigating. The study of the mind not only was influenced by a set of broad social shifts, but it also participated in them fully as both stimulus to and recipient of changing conditions. One indication of this is simply the variety of terms used to identify the ‘philosophy of mind’ as an intellectual enterprise in the eighteenth and nineteenth centuries.1 But the issue goes far deeper into the fluid constitutive features of the enterprise - including associated conceptual systems, methods, intentions of practitioners, and institutional affiliations. In order to understand philosophy of mind in its time, we must put all these factors into play.
    [Show full text]
  • Neural Networks
    Neural Networks 1. Introduction Spring 2020 1 Neural Networks are taking over! • Neural networks have become one of the major thrust areas recently in various pattern recognition, prediction, and analysis problems • In many problems they have established the state of the art – Often exceeding previous benchmarks by large margins 2 Breakthroughs with neural networks 3 Breakthrough with neural networks 4 Image segmentation and recognition 5 Image recognition https://www.sighthound.com/technology/ 6 Breakthroughs with neural networks 7 Success with neural networks • Captions generated entirely by a neural network 8 Breakthroughs with neural networks ThisPersonDoesNotExist.com uses AI to generate endless fake faces – https://www.theverge.com/tldr/2019/2/15/18226005/ai-generated- fake-people-portraits-thispersondoesnotexist-stylegan 9 Successes with neural networks • And a variety of other problems: – From art to astronomy to healthcare.. – and even predicting stock markets! 10 Neural nets can do anything! 11 Neural nets and the employment market This guy didn’t know This guy learned about neural networks about neural networks (a.k.a deep learning) (a.k.a deep learning) 12 Objectives of this course • Understanding neural networks • Comprehending the models that do the previously mentioned tasks – And maybe build them • Familiarity with some of the terminology – What are these: • http://www.datasciencecentral.com/profiles/blogs/concise-visual- summary-of-deep-learning-architectures • Fearlessly design, build and train networks for various tasks
    [Show full text]
  • Pragmatism and 'Pragmatism'
    Appendix THE BEGINNING OF PRAGMATISM AND 'PRAGMATISM' PEIRCE CLAIMS TO HAVE USED THE WORD "PRAGMATISM" in philosophical conversations from the mid-'seventies on, to designate his theory of be­ lief, and, although he explained the main elements of his pragmatic theory of meaning in the two articles published in the Popular Science Monthly in 1877 and 1878, he still did not dare to use the word "prag­ matism" in print until 1902. He used it then only in response to a spe­ cial request, in Baldwin's Dictionary of Philosophy and Psychology, under the heading "Pragmatism" (5.414n; 5.1-4). In preparing to write the articles for Baldwin, Peirce wrote to James on November 10, 1900: "Who originated the term pragmatism, I or you? Where did it first appear in print? What do you understand by it?" And on a postcard dated November 26, 1900 James replied: "You invented 'pragmatism' for which I gave you full credit in a lecture entitled 'Philosophical con­ ceptions and practical results' of which I sent you 2 (unacknowledged) copies a couple of years ago" (8.253). The lecture to which James refers was his famous paper delivered in 1898 at the University of California, wherein he presented his views of pragmatism. James' understanding of pragmatism was so different from Peirce's that the latter, to avoid ambiguity, devised a n ew term "pragmaticism" to describe his doctrine, in an article in The Monist in 1905. "The writer, finding his bantling 'pragmatism' so promoted, feels 147 148 PEIRCE's THEORY OF SCIENTIFIC METIIOD that it is time to kiss his child good-by and relinquish it to its higher destiny; while to serve the precise purpose of expressing the original definition, he begs to announce the birth of the word 'pragmaticism,' which is ugly enough to be safe from kidnappers" (5.414).
    [Show full text]
  • The Development and Early Research Results of Mill Marginalia Online
    ILCEA Revue de l’Institut des langues et cultures d'Europe, Amérique, Afrique, Asie et Australie 39 | 2020 Les humanités numériques dans une perspective internationale : opportunités, défis, outils et méthodes Handwritten Marginalia and Digital Search: The Development and Early Research Results of Mill Marginalia Online Marginalia manuscrits et recherche numérique : développement et résultats préliminaires de l’édition en ligne de Mill Marginalia. Albert D. Pionke Electronic version URL: http://journals.openedition.org/ilcea/8582 DOI: 10.4000/ilcea.8582 ISSN: 2101-0609 Publisher UGA Éditions/Université Grenoble Alpes Printed version ISBN: 978-2-37747-174-4 ISSN: 1639-6073 Electronic reference Albert D. Pionke, « Handwritten Marginalia and Digital Search: The Development and Early Research Results of Mill Marginalia Online », ILCEA [Online], 39 | 2020, Online since 03 March 2020, connection on 10 October 2020. URL : http://journals.openedition.org/ilcea/8582 ; DOI : https://doi.org/10.4000/ ilcea.8582 This text was automatically generated on 10 October 2020. © ILCEA Handwritten Marginalia and Digital Search: The Development and Early Research... 1 Handwritten Marginalia and Digital Search: The Development and Early Research Results of Mill Marginalia Online Marginalia manuscrits et recherche numérique : développement et résultats préliminaires de l’édition en ligne de Mill Marginalia. Albert D. Pionke 1 Victorian Britain’s leading philosophical empiricist and liberal theorist—and, perhaps the dominant figure in Victorian intellectual life from the 1860s, when he was elected to Parliament as Liberal Member for Westminster, through the 1880s, the decade after his death in which intellectuals in a variety of fields continued to define themselves with respect to his legacy—John Stuart Mill authored significant works on logic, epistemology, political economy, aesthetics, and social reform.
    [Show full text]
  • UNIVERSITY of CALIFORNIA Los Angeles Dread: the Literary History
    UNIVERSITY OF CALIFORNIA Los Angeles Dread: The Literary History of a Political Affect, 1750-1900 A dissertation submitted in partial satisfaction of the requirements for the degree of Doctor of Philosophy in English by Samantha Ellen Morse 2020 © Copyright by Samantha Ellen Morse 2020 ABSTRACT OF THE DISSERTATION Dread: The Literary History of a Political Affect, 1750-1900 by Samantha Ellen Morse Doctor of Philosophy in English University of California, Los Angeles 2020 Professor Sarah Tindal Kareem, Chair This dissertation analyzes the cultural urgency of dread—a profound feeling of fear about the future—in a range of canonical and popular British novels, poems, periodicals, and philosophical treatises. In our own time, we tend to think of dread as a negative, paralyzing affect. Yet I elucidate the many ways in which nineteenth-century authors, philosophers, political reformers, and theologians regarded this feeling as an impetus for bringing about a better future. The anticipatory qualities of dread served as a catalyst for ethical and political transformations in the Enlightenment all the way through the Victorian era. Beginning with David Hume and ending with H. G. Wells, I examine the ways in which dread entered into and shaped philosophical thought, popular culture, and political life, especially radicalism, through shifting literary forms, many of which stemmed from the Gothic mode. While numerous studies have investigated fearful affects such as terror, horror, and anxiety, my dissertation is the first ii sustained examination of dread, which reconceptualizes the Gothic’s literary and political significance. While it is a critical commonplace that Gothic fiction stages encounters with the past, I show how the Gothic stimulates dread in order to orient its readers toward future possibilities.
    [Show full text]
  • Empiricist Roots of Modern Psychology
    Raymond Martin Department of Philosophy Union College Schenectady, NY 12308 USA Empiricist Roots of Modern Psychology From the thirteenth through the sixteenth centuries, European philosophers were preoccupied with using their newfound access to Aristotle’s metaphysics and natural philosophy to develop an integrated account, hospitable to Christianity, of everything that was thought to exist, including God, pure finite spirits (angels), the immaterial souls of humans, the natural world of organic objects (plants, animals, and human bodies) and inorganic objects. This account included a theory of human mentality. In the sixteenth and early seventeenth centuries, first in astronomy and then, later, in physics, the tightly knit fabric of this comprehensive medieval world view began to unravel. The transition from the old to the new was gradual, but by 1687, with the publication by Isaac Newton (1642-1727) of his Principia Mathematica, the replacement was all but complete. Modern physical science had fully arrived, and it was secular. God and angels were still acknowledged. But they had been marginalized. Yet, there was a glaring omission. Theorists had yet to expand the reach of the new science to incorporate human mentality. This venture, which initially was called “moral philosophy” and came to be called “the science of human nature,” became compelling to progressive eighteenth century thinkers, just as British empiricism began to seriously challenge an entrenched Cartesian rationalism. Rationalism and Empiricism The dispute between rationalists and empiricists was primarily over concepts and knowledge. In response to such questions as, where does the mind get its stock of concepts, how do humans justify what they take to be their knowledge, and how far does human knowledge extend, rationalists maintained that some concepts are innate, and hence not derived from experience, and that reason, or intuition, by itself, independently of experience, is an important source of knowledge, including of existing [25] 1 things.
    [Show full text]
  • Humour and Incongruity JOHN LIPPITT
    Humour and incongruity JOHN LIPPITT The first in aseries of articles on the philosophy of humour and laughter looks at attempts made to explain humour in terms of incongruity. Introduction The philosophy of humour and laughter is a rarely studied field. This is despite the fact that many of the West's most celebrated thinkers-Plato, Aristotle, Descartes, Hobbes, Kant, Schopenhauer, Kierkegaard, Nietzsche, Bergson, Freud-have advanced views on the subject; and the fact that interdisciplinary research on humour has grown enormously in the recent past. This series of articles will attempt to offer a survey of some major views on the nature of humour and laughter. Throughout, in line with contemporary humour research, 'humour' will be used as an umbrella term to cover all categories of the funny; the general term of which wit, satire, jokes, etc., may be viewed as subcategories. Contemporary humour researchers often divide accounts of humour into three main theoretical traditions, focusing on, respectively, incongruity, superiority and the release of energy. We will consider one of these traditions in each of the first three articles. This first piece will examine the 'incongruity' tradition; it will offer a critical analysis of attempts made to argue that the nature of humour is to be explained in terms of incongruity. By far the most commonly discussed comments in this tradition are those of Arthur Schopenhauer, and we will turn to these shortly. But a brief comment from Kant's Critique of Judgement will be useful to get us going. Kant claims that: 'Something absurd (something in which, therefore, the understanding can of itself find no delight) must be present in whatever is to raise a hearty convulsive laugh.
    [Show full text]
  • Pragmatism in Florence: the Magicians and the Logicians
    Chapter 1 Pragmatism in Florence: The Magicians and the Logicians Cornelis de Waal As, to papal minds, protestantism has often seemed a mere mess of anar- chy and confusion, such, no doubt, will pragmatism often seem to ultra- rationalist minds in philosophy. William James Pragmatism is often seen as America’s contribution to world philosophy. It emerged in the early 1870s when a small group of young men from Cambridge, Massachusetts, came together to discuss philosophy. With an ironic and defi- ant air, they called themselves—in honour of a discipline they considered obsolete—The Metaphysical Club. No records of their meetings survive, but from correspondence and publications it is clear that they rejected philosophy as it was practiced at the time. The group included, among others, William James (1842–1910), Charles Sanders Peirce (1839–1914), and the future Supreme Court justice Oliver Wendell Holmes Jr. (1841–1935). At a pivotal moment their discussions centered around Alexander Bain’s definition of belief as “that upon which a man is prepared to act.” As Peirce later recalled, once that definition is granted, pragmatism follows almost immediately. In the eyes of both Peirce and James, who became the first major proponents of this philosophical out- look, pragmatism was not some revolutionary new approach, but was merely the conscious and systematic adoption of a method that philosophers had been practicing from antiquity onward. Peirce boldly declared that the new- ness of a philosophical idea is one of the surest signs that it is false, and he called even Jesus a pragmatist. James sought to drive home this same point when he subtitled his famous book Pragmatism as “A New Name for Some Old Ways of Thinking.” Despite the pragmatists’ claim that philosophers have always been practic- ing pragmatism, its explicit enunciation as a method for doing philosophy by James, Peirce, and others got a cold reception in Europe, where it was seen as designed for people who have little patience for philosophy and who prefer to stick to practical affairs.
    [Show full text]
  • The Mystery of Common Sense
    View metadata, citation and similar papers at core.ac.uk brought to you by CORE provided by CommonKnowledge Essays in Philosophy Volume 3 Article 2 Issue 2 Pragmatism and Neopragmatism 6-2002 Who is Exaggerating? The ysM tery of Common Sense Heidi Salaverria Follow this and additional works at: http://commons.pacificu.edu/eip Part of the Philosophy Commons Recommended Citation Salaverria, Heidi (2002) "Who is Exaggerating? The ysM tery of Common Sense," Essays in Philosophy: Vol. 3: Iss. 2, Article 2. Essays in Philosophy is a biannual journal published by Pacific nivU ersity Library | ISSN 1526-0569 | http://commons.pacificu.edu/eip/ Essays in Philosophy Essays in Philosophy A Biannual Journal Volume 3, Number 2 Who is Exaggerating? The Mystery of Common Sense “The most difficult thing in the world to learn to see is the obvious, the familiar, the universally taken for granted.”1 (John Dewey) Throughout the history of Pragmatism, the notion of common sense has been recurrent, but rather than a central feature it seems to be an underlying, over the time changing, and indefinite motif, which nevertheless has unceasingly accompanied pragmatist thought. common sense has taken on a range of meanings, varying from vague beliefs, everyday-knowledge, common experience, sound understanding, good judgment, anachronistic truth, hidden intuition, custom and routine on the one hand to innate knowledge and universal truth on the other hand - just to name a few. To add some confusion, common sense has sometimes been located in the past, sometimes in the present or even in the future. It focuses either on epistemological, moral, or aesthetic questions.
    [Show full text]
  • The Philosophy David Hume
    THE PHILOSOPHY OF DAVID HUME A CRITICAL STUDY OF ITS ORIGINS AND CENTRAL DOCTRINES BY NORMAN KEMP SMITH D.LITT., LL.D., F.B.A. SOMETIME PROFESSOR OF LOGIC AND METAPHYSICS IN THE UNIVERSITY Or EDINBURGH WITH A NEW INTRODUCTION BY DON GARRETT ©Norman Kemp Smith 1941 Introduction © Don Garrett ZOOS All rights reserved. No reproduction, copy or transmission of this publication may be made without written permisston. No paragraph of th1s publication may be reproduced, copied or transmitt save with written permission or in accordance with the provisions of the Copyright, Designs and Patents Act 1988, or under the terms of any licen· permitting limited copying issued by the Copyright Licensing Agency, 90 Totten ham Court Road, London W1T 4LP. Any person who does any unauthorised act in relation to this publication may be liable to criminal prosecution and civil claims for damages. The authors have asserted their rights to be identified as the authors oft work in accordance with the Copyright, Designs and Patents Act 1988. First published 1941 This edition published 2005 by PALGRAVE MACMILLAN Houndmills, Basingstoke, Hampshire RG21 6XS and 175 Fifth Avenue, New York, N.Y. 10010 Companies and representatives throughout the world PALGRAVE MACMILLAN is the global academic imprint of the Palgrave Macmillan division of St. Martin's Press, LLC and of Palgrave Macmillan Lt Macmillan"' is a registered trademark in the United States, United Kingdc and other countries. Palgrave is a registered trademark in the European Union and other countries. ISBN 978-1-4039-1507-8 ISBN 978-0-230-51117-0 (eBook) DOI 10.1057/9780230511170 This book is printed on paper suitable for recycling and made from fully managed and sustained forest sources.
    [Show full text]
  • European Journal of Pragmatism and American Philosophy, IX-1 | 2017 Habit Beyond Psychology 2
    European Journal of Pragmatism and American Philosophy IX-1 | 2017 Pragmatism and Psychologism Habit Beyond Psychology The Evolution Of The Concept Aleksandar Feodorov Electronic version URL: http://journals.openedition.org/ejpap/1007 DOI: 10.4000/ejpap.1007 ISSN: 2036-4091 Publisher Associazione Pragma Electronic reference Aleksandar Feodorov, « Habit Beyond Psychology », European Journal of Pragmatism and American Philosophy [Online], IX-1 | 2017, Online since 22 July 2017, connection on 12 June 2020. URL : http:// journals.openedition.org/ejpap/1007 ; DOI : https://doi.org/10.4000/ejpap.1007 This text was automatically generated on 12 June 2020. Author retains copyright and grants the European Journal of Pragmatism and American Philosophy right of first publication with the work simultaneously licensed under a Creative Commons Attribution- NonCommercial-NoDerivatives 4.0 International License. Habit Beyond Psychology 1 Habit Beyond Psychology The Evolution Of The Concept Aleksandar Feodorov Introduction 1 Psychologists would often attribute the success or failure of our everyday behavior to the habits we develop throughout our lives. Walking, eating or even speaking are acquired habits, whereas physiological processes like breathing or even the ability to think – inherent habits or instincts. Beyond the level of the individual, all conventions of society and moral values signaling the emergence of civilization can be analyzed into elements, which form a structural equivalent to the habits of a single person. Since it is possible to approach a given multitude such as a congestion of atoms or a social community as an individual, nothing surprising emerges out of these propositions: there is no immediate reason to doubt the effects of habit.
    [Show full text]