Rationality and Irrationality in the History of Continental Drift Was the Hypothesis of Continental Drift Worthy of Pursuit?
Total Page:16
File Type:pdf, Size:1020Kb
Rationality and Irrationality in the History of Continental Drift Was the Hypothesis of Continental Drift Worthy of Pursuit? Dunja Seˇseljaˇ 1, Erik Weber1 Abstract The revolution in geology, initiated with Alfred Wegener’s theory of continental drift, has been the subject of many philosophical discussions aiming at resolv- ing the problem of rationality underlying this historical episode. Even though the debate included analyses in terms of scientific methodology, applications of concrete accounts of epistemic justification to this case study have been rare. In particular, the question as to whether Wegener’s theory was epistemically worthy of pursuit in the first half of the twentieth century, that is, in its early development, remained open or inadequately addressed. The aim of this paper is to offer an answer to this question. The evaluation of Drift will be done by means of an account of theory evaluation suitable for the context of pursuit, developed in Seˇseljaˇ & Straßer (201x). We will argue that pursuing the theory of continental drift was rational, i.e., that it was irrational to reject its pursuit as unworthy. Key words: Alfred Wegener, continental drift, rationality, context of pursuit, pursuit worthiness 1. Introduction Ever since the revolution in the earth sciences culminated in the overall ac- ceptance of the theory of plate tectonics, philosophers and historians of science have been analyzing this shift in geology. What made the development in ge- ology very interesting is its specific dynamics. Even though the hypothesis of continental drift was proposed by Alfred Wegener already around the 1920s, it was firmly rejected by many geologists not only as unacceptable but even as unworthy of further pursuit. Almost half a century had to pass in order for this hypothesis to become finally accepted and elaborated into the theory of plate tectonics. Such a development inspired discussions among philosophers and his- torians of science, which especially focused around two issues: first, the nature Email addresses: [email protected] (Dunja Seˇselja),ˇ [email protected] (Erik Weber) Preprint submitted to Studies in History and Philosophy of Science June29,2011 of the revolution in geology and the applicability of different methodological frameworks to it, and second, the rationality or irrationality of the stances of scientists throughout the revolution. With regard to the first question, some philosophers and historians of science argued that this episode can be described in terms of Kuhn’s notion of scientific revolution (e.g. Stewart (1990)). However, the majority of them agreed that Laudan’s account of progress of science is more suitable for this case-study (see e.g. Le Grand (1988), Frankel (1979), Laudan (1987)). The aptness of Laudan’s framework stems from two important notions in his account. On the one hand, his notion of a research tradition as a broader theoretical framework, constituted by specific scientific theories, has been shown useful for capturing the rivaling camps in geology, neither of which could be reduced to one generally accepted theory.1 On the other hand, his distinction between the context of pursuit and the context of acceptance (Laudan, 1977, p. 108-110) proved to be important for analyzing questions of rationality regarding this case study. According to Laudan, “acceptance, rejection, pursuit and non-pursuit constitute the major cognitive stances which scientists can legitimately take towards research tradi- tions (and their constituent theories)” (Laudan, 1977, p. 119). As the names suggest, the context of acceptance deals with the question as to whether a certain theory is to be accepted as the standard in the given field, while the context of pursuit deals with the question as to whether a (possibly young, un- developed) theory is at all worthy of further pursuit. Such a distinction allows for a twofold analysis of the rationality of judgments made by geologists during this time. This brings us to the second important topic that attracted interests of philosophers and historians of science, as we have mentioned above. With respect to the context of acceptance, there has been a general agree- ment that it was rational to reject Wegener’s theory of drift when it first ap- peared in the 1912-1915, and to accept Drift2 in the early 1960s, after it had developed into the theory of plate tectonics. With respect to the context of pursuit, most of the authors simply described the views of geologists at the time. Nevertheless, the question: Was pursuing the theory of continental drift in the first half of the twentieth century at all rational (in the sense of being epistemically justified), or was it rational to reject its pursuit? – so far has not been properly addressed. The aim of this paper is to answer this question in terms of a concrete account of epistemic justification. To this end, we will use the account developed 1In contrast to Lakatos’ notion of a research program, Laudan’s notion of research tradition allows for an evolving hardcore, which, according to some authors, makes it especially suitable for describing the geological sciences in the first half of the twentieth century (see e.g. (Frankel, 1979, p. 53)). According to Laudan, what makes theories belong to the same research tradition is its hardcore, which, even though sacrosanct for its proponents, can still evolve. In other words, theories belong to the same tradition not because some of their crucial assumptions are identical, but rather because these assumptions overlap (see Laudan (1977), p. 99). 2As it is usual in the literature on this case study, we will call this research tradition and its constituting theories (running from Wegener’s theory of continental drift to the theory of plate tectonics) – Drift. 2 in Seˇseljaˇ & Straßer (201x), which offers the criteria of epistemic justification suitable for the context of pursuit. The paper is structured as follows. We begin in Section 2 by offering a brief historical overview of the revolution in geology. InSection 3 we will explicate our research question in some more detail, and in Section 4 show that so far this question has not been properly addressed in the literature on this historical episode. In Section 5 we will present a summary of the account of epistemic justification which we shall employ in this paper. Sections 6 to 9 bring an evaluation of pursuit worthiness of Drift in the first half of the twentieth century. In Section 10 we will discuss the epistemic stances of geologists in this time period in view of our evaluation. Moreover, we will point out the importance of the evaluation of epistemic pursuit worthiness and some undesirable implications for scientific debates once this type of assessment has been neglected. Section 11 concludes the paper. 2. Historical Overview of the Revolution in Geology 2.1. Rivaling Theories Alfred Wegener launched the idea of continental drift in a short article in Wegener (1912). A more elaborate version appeared as a book in 1915 Wegener (1915). His central claims were that all the continents had once been united, had broken apart and had drifted through the ocean floor to their current locations (Le Grand, 1988, p. 1). Following Le Grand we call adherents of the of large scale lateral movements of continents drifters. Wegener probably was not the first drifter, but he was the first to develop a full-fledged argumentation for it. He tried to show that Drift is superior to the two theories that already existed, viz. permanentism and contractionism. The summary of views and arguments presented below is based on Le Grand (1988) (especially p. 19-28, 40-46 and 55-57).3 According to permanentists “... the continents were formed in remote ge- ological times as the earth had gradually cooled down and contracted. Since then, they had been permanent features of the earths surface.” (Ibid., p. 20-21). Continents do not move laterally (this is how permanentism differs from Drift) and do not disappear (this is how it differs from contractionism, see below). James D. Dana, professor at Yale University from 1850 to 1892 and one of the main adherents of this theory, used the slogan “Once a continent, always a con- tinent; once an ocean, always an ocean” (quoted from: Ibid., p. 21). According to permanentists there have been small elevations (producing mountains) and small subsidences (producing e.g. shallow inland seas). The most important representative of contractionism was the German ge- ologist Eduard Suess. The central claim of his theory was the following: “As the earth lost its heat, a rigid crust formed. As the earth continued to cool and 3Even though Le Grand offers a good overview of this debate, some details that are relevant for our discussion are better worked out in Oreskes (1999) (see Sections 6-9). 3 shrink, this crust wrinkled, folded and subsided” (Ibid., p. 25). This process ex- plains how mountains come into existence (lateral movement of parts of crust). The collapses occur sporadically, creating new oceans and new continents: when the crust collapses in a certain region, the water flows to the new lowest point; continents thus can become oceans and oceans land. Because the collapses occur sporadically, contractionists see the history of the earth as divided into periods of rapid change and periods of stability. According to Wegener the earth consists of a series of concentric shells with different compositions and densities (highest density in the near to the core). The temperature also is higher closer to the core. The continents constitute the outermost shell and consist of blocks of sial (silica + alumina) which (like icebergs in the sea) partially float on and extend into blocks of sima (silica + magnesia). The oceans are situated between the blocks of sial, and ocean floor is made of sima.