Einstein Was No Lone Genius

Total Page:16

File Type:pdf, Size:1020Kb

Einstein Was No Lone Genius COMMENT BESSO: BESSO FAMILY/AIP EMILIO SEGRE VISUAL ARCHIVES VISUAL EMILIO SEGRE FAMILY/AIP BESSO BESSO: GROSSMANN, EINSTEIN: ETH-BIBLIOTHEK ZÜRICH/BILDARCHIV; ZÜRICH/BILDARCHIV; ETH-BIBLIOTHEK GROSSMANN, EINSTEIN: Marcel Grossmann (left) and Michele Besso (right), university friends of Albert Einstein (centre), both made important contributions to general relativity. Einstein was no lone genius Lesser-known and junior colleagues helped the great physicist to piece together his general theory of relativity, explain Michel Janssen and Jürgen Renn. century ago, in November 1915, Technische Hochschule; ETH) — where, would account for a discrepancy of about Albert Einstein published his between 1896 and 1900, he studied to 43˝ (seconds of arc) per century between general theory of relativity in four become a school teacher in physics and Newtonian predictions and observations Ashort papers in the proceedings of the Prus- mathematics. Einstein also met his future of the motion of Mercury’s perihelion, the sian Academy of Sciences in Berlin1. The wife at the ETH, classmate Mileva Marić. point of its orbit closest to the Sun. landmark theory is often presented as the Legend has it that Einstein often skipped Einstein started to work in earnest on this work of a lone genius. In fact, the physicist class and relied on Grossmann’s notes to new theory only after he left the patent office received a great deal of help from friends pass exams. in 1909, to take up professorships first at the and colleagues, most of whom never rose Grossmann’s father helped Einstein to University of Zurich and two years later at to prominence and have been forgotten2–5. secure a position at the patent office in the Charles University in Prague. He realized (For full reference details of all Einstein texts Berne in 1902, where Besso joined him that gravity must be incorporated into the mentioned in this piece, see Supplementary two years later. Discussions between Besso structure of space-time, such that a particle Information; go.nature.com/ufcgp9.) and Einstein earned the former the sole subject to no other force would follow the Here we tell the story of how their acknowledgment in the most famous of straightest possible trajectory through a insights were woven into the final version Einstein’s 1905 papers, the one introduc- curved space-time. of the theory. Two friends from Einstein’s ing the special theory of relativity. As well In 1912, Einstein returned to Zurich and student days — Marcel Grossmann and as publishing the papers that made 1905 was reunited with Grossmann at the ETH. Michele Besso — were particularly impor- his annus mirabilis, Einstein completed The pair joined forces to generate a fully tant. Grossmann was a gifted mathemati- his dissertation that year to earn a PhD in fledged theory. The relevant mathematics cian and organized student who helped physics from the University of Zurich. was Gauss’s theory of curved surfaces, which the more visionary and fanciful Einstein at In 1907, while still at the patent office, he Einstein probably learned from Grossmann’s crucial moments. Besso was an engineer, started to think about extending the prin- notes. As we know from recollected conver- imaginative and somewhat disorganized, ciple of relativity from uniform to arbitrary sations, Einstein told Grossmann7: “You and a caring and lifelong friend to Einstein. motion through a new theory of gravity. must help me, or else I’ll go crazy.” A cast of others contributed too. Presciently, Einstein wrote to his friend Their collaboration, recorded in Einstein met Grossmann and Besso at Conrad Habicht — whom he knew from a Einstein’s ‘Zurich notebook’, resulted in a the Swiss Federal Polytechnical School in reading group in Berne mockingly called the joint paper published in June 1913, known Zurich6 — later renamed the Swiss Federal Olympia Academy by its three members — as the Entwurf (‘outline’) paper. The Institute of Technology (Eidgenössische saying that he hoped that this new theory main advance between this 1913 Entwurf 298 | NATURE | VOL 527 | 19 NOVEMBER 2015 | CORRECTED ONLINE 17 NOVEMBER 2015 © 2015 Macmillan Publishers Limited. All rights reserved COMMENT theory and the general relativity theory in their formulation of the Entwurf theory. theory using the same kind of mathematics of November 1915 are the field equa- During his Vienna lecture, Einstein called that he and Grossmann had used to for- tions, which determine how matter curves for Kottler to stand up and be recognized for mulate the Entwurf theory. Einstein and space-time. The final field equations are this work8. Fokker showed that in both theories the ‘generally covariant’: they retain their form Einstein also worked with Besso that gravitational field can be incorporated into no matter what system of coordinates is summer to investigate whether the Entwurf the structure of a curved space-time. This chosen to express them. The covariance of theory could account for the missing 43˝ per work also gave Einstein a clearer picture of the Entwurf field equations, by contrast, century for Mercury’s perihelion. Unfortu- the structure of the Entwurf theory, which was severely limited. nately, they found that it could only explain helped him and Grossmann in a second 18˝. Nordström’s theory, Besso checked later, joint paper on the theory. By the time it TWO THEORIES gave 7˝ in the wrong direction. These calcu- was published in May 1914, Einstein had In May 1913, as he and Grossmann put the lations are preserved in the ‘Einstein–Besso left for Berlin. finishing touches to their Entwurf paper, manuscript’ of 1913. Einstein was asked to lecture at the annual Besso contributed significantly to the THE BREAKTHROUGH meeting of the Society of German Natural calculations and raised interesting ques- Turmoil erupted soon after the move. Scientists and Physicians to be held that Sep- tions. He wondered, for instance, whether Einstein’s marriage fell apart and Mileva tember in Vienna, an invitation that reflects the Entwurf field equations have an unam- moved back to Zurich with their two the high esteem in which the 34-year-old biguous solution that uniquely determines young sons. Albert renewed the affair was held by his peers. the gravitational field of the Sun. Historical he had started and broken off two years In July 1913, Max Planck and Walther analysis of extant manuscripts suggests that before with his cousin Elsa Löwenthal (née Nernst, two leading physicists from Berlin, this query gave Einstein the idea for an argu- Einstein). The First World War began. Ber- came to Zurich to offer Einstein a well-paid ment that reconciled him with the restricted lin’s scientific elite showed no interest in and teaching-free position at the Prussian covariance of the Entwurf equations. This the Entwurf theory, although renowned Academy of Sciences in Berlin, which he ‘hole argument’ seemed to show that gen- colleagues elsewhere did, such as Lorentz swiftly accepted and took up in March 1914. erally covariant field equations cannot and Paul Ehrenfest in Leiden, the Nether- Gravity was not a pressing problem for Planck uniquely determine the gravitational field lands. Einstein soldiered on. and Nernst; they were mainly interested in and are therefore inadmissible9. By the end of 1914, his confidence had what Einstein could do for quantum physics. Einstein and Besso also checked whether grown enough to write a long exposition Several new theories had been proposed the Entwurf equations hold in a rotating of the theory. But in the summer of 1915, in which gravity, like electromagnetism, was coordinate system. In that case the inertial after a series of his lectures in Göttingen had represented by a field in the flat space-time forces of rotation, such as the centrifugal piqued the interest of the great mathemati- of special relativity. A particularly promising force we experience on a merry-go-round, cian David Hilbert, Einstein started to have one came from the young Finnish physicist can be interpreted as gravitational forces. serious doubts. He discovered to his dismay Gunnar Nordström. In his Vienna lecture, The theory seemed to pass this test. In that the Entwurf theory does not make Einstein compared his own Entwurf theory August 1913, however, Besso warned him rotational motion relative. Besso was right. to Nordström’s theory. Einstein worked on that it did not. Einstein did not heed the Einstein wrote to Freundlich for help: his both theories between May and late August warning, which would come back to haunt “mind was in a deep rut”, so he hoped that 1913, when he submitted the text of his lec- him. the young astronomer as “a fellow human ture for publication in the proceedings of the In his lecture in Vienna in September being with unspoiled brain matter” could tell 1913 Vienna meeting. 1913, Einstein concluded his comparison of him what he was doing wrong. Freundlich In the summer of 1913, Nordström visited the two theories with a call for experiment could not help him. Einstein in Zurich. Einstein convinced him to decide. The Entwurf theory predicts The problem, Einstein soon realized, lay that the source of the gravitational field in that gravity bends with the Entwurf field equations. Worried both their theories should be constructed light, whereas Nor- “Worried that that Hilbert might beat him to the punch, out of the ‘energy–momentum tensor’: in dström’s does not. It Hilbert might Einstein rushed new equations into print in pre-relativistic theories, the density and the would take another beat him to early November 1915, modifying them the flow of energy and momentum were repre- five years to find out. the punch, following week and again two weeks later in sented by separate quantities; in relativity Erwin Finlay Freun- Einstein subsequent papers submitted to the Prussian theory, they are combined into one quantity dlich, a junior astron- rushed new Academy.
Recommended publications
  • The Principle of Equivalence As a Criterion of Identity Ryan Samaroo
    Forthcoming in Synthese The Principle of Equivalence as a Criterion of Identity Ryan Samaroo Somerville College, Woodstock Road, Oxford, OX2 6HD, United Kingdom [email protected] Dedicated to the memory of William (Bill) Demopoulos Abstract In 1907 Einstein had the insight that bodies in free fall do not “feel” their own weight. This has been formalized in what is called “the principle of equivalence.” The principle motivated a critical analysis of the Newtonian and special-relativistic concepts of inertia, and it was indispensable to Einstein’s development of his theory of gravitation. A great deal has been written about the principle. Nearly all of this work has focused on the content of the principle and whether it has any content in Einsteinian gravitation, but more remains to be said about its methodological role in the development of the theory. I argue that the principle should be understood as a kind of foundational principle known as a criterion of identity. This work extends and substantiates a recent account of the notion of a criterion of identity by William Demopoulos. Demopoulos argues that the notion can be employed more widely than in the foundations of arithmetic and that we see this in the development of physical theories, in particular space-time theories. This new account forms the basis of a general framework for applying a number of mathematical theories and for distinguishing between applied mathematical theories that are and are not empirically constrained. 1. Introduction “The principle of equivalence,” which Einstein originally used to refer to one particular statement, has come to refer to a number of interrelated principles in the theory of gravitation.1 1 Einstein’s first formulation of the principle can be found in his article “On the Relativity Principle and the Conclusions Drawn from It” (1907, p.
    [Show full text]
  • The Universe of General Relativity, Springer 2005.Pdf
    Einstein Studies Editors: Don Howard John Stachel Published under the sponsorship of the Center for Einstein Studies, Boston University Volume 1: Einstein and the History of General Relativity Don Howard and John Stachel, editors Volume 2: Conceptual Problems of Quantum Gravity Abhay Ashtekar and John Stachel, editors Volume 3: Studies in the History of General Relativity Jean Eisenstaedt and A.J. Kox, editors Volume 4: Recent Advances in General Relativity Allen I. Janis and John R. Porter, editors Volume 5: The Attraction of Gravitation: New Studies in the History of General Relativity John Earman, Michel Janssen and John D. Norton, editors Volume 6: Mach’s Principle: From Newton’s Bucket to Quantum Gravity Julian B. Barbour and Herbert Pfister, editors Volume 7: The Expanding Worlds of General Relativity Hubert Goenner, Jürgen Renn, Jim Ritter, and Tilman Sauer, editors Volume 8: Einstein: The Formative Years, 1879–1909 Don Howard and John Stachel, editors Volume 9: Einstein from ‘B’ to ‘Z’ John Stachel Volume 10: Einstein Studies in Russia Yuri Balashov and Vladimir Vizgin, editors Volume 11: The Universe of General Relativity A.J. Kox and Jean Eisenstaedt, editors A.J. Kox Jean Eisenstaedt Editors The Universe of General Relativity Birkhauser¨ Boston • Basel • Berlin A.J. Kox Jean Eisenstaedt Universiteit van Amsterdam Observatoire de Paris Instituut voor Theoretische Fysica SYRTE/UMR8630–CNRS Valckenierstraat 65 F-75014 Paris Cedex 1018 XE Amsterdam France The Netherlands AMS Subject Classification (2000): 01A60, 83-03, 83-06 Library of Congress Cataloging-in-Publication Data The universe of general relativity / A.J. Kox, editors, Jean Eisenstaedt. p.
    [Show full text]
  • On Levi-Civita's Alternating Symbol, Schouten's Alternating Unit Tensors
    Mathematics Faculty Works Mathematics 2012 On Levi-Civita’s Alternating Symbol, Schouten’s Alternating Unit Tensors, CPT, and Quantization Evert Jan Post University of Houston Stan Sholar The Boeing Company Hooman Rahimizadeh Loyola Marymount University Michael Berg Loyola Marymount University, [email protected] Follow this and additional works at: https://digitalcommons.lmu.edu/math_fac Part of the Geometry and Topology Commons, and the Quantum Physics Commons Recommended Citation Sholar, S., H. Rahimizadeh, E. J. Post,“On Levi-Civita’s Alternating Symbol, Schouten’s Alternating Unit Tensors, CPT, and Quantization.” International Journal of Pure and Applied Mathematics, 78(6), 2012, 895-907. This Article is brought to you for free and open access by the Mathematics at Digital Commons @ Loyola Marymount University and Loyola Law School. It has been accepted for inclusion in Mathematics Faculty Works by an authorized administrator of Digital Commons@Loyola Marymount University and Loyola Law School. For more information, please contact [email protected]. International Journal of Pure and Applied Mathematics Volume 78 No. 6 2012, 895-907 AP ISSN: 1311-8080 (printed version) url: http://www.ijpam.eu ijpam.eu ON LEVI-CIVITA’S ALTERNATING SYMBOL, SCHOUTEN’S ALTERNATING UNIT TENSORS, CPT, AND QUANTIZATION Evert Jan Post1, Stan Sholar2, Hooman Rahimizadeh3, Michael Berg4 § 1The University of Houston 4800, Calhoun Road, Houston, Texas, 77004, USA 2The Boeing Company 3Department of Mathematics Loyola Marymount University 1 LMU Drive, Los Angeles, CA 90045, USA Abstract: The purpose of the present article is to demonstrate that by adopt- ing a unifying differential geometric perspective on certain themes in physics one reaps remarkable new dividends in both microscopic and macroscopic domains.
    [Show full text]
  • Why Einstein Did Not Believe That General Relativity Geometrizes Gravity
    Why Einstein did not believe that general relativity geometrizes gravity Dennis Lehmkuhl, IZWT Wuppertal and Einstein Papers Project, Caltech Email: [email protected] Address: IZWT, University of Wuppertal, Gausstrasse 20, 42119 Wuppertal, Germany Telephone: +49 202 439 3605 Abstract I argue that, contrary to folklore, Einstein never really cared for geometrizing the gravitational or (subsequently) the electromagnetic field; indeed, he thought that the very statement that General Rela- tivity geometrizes gravity \is not saying anything at all". Instead, I shall show that Einstein saw the “unification” of inertia and gravity as one of the major achievements of General Relativity. Interestingly, Einstein did not locate this unification in the field equations but in his interpretation of the geodesic equation, the law of motion of test particles. Contents 1 Introduction 2 2 What Einstein did not believe 4 2.1 The Einstein-Meyerson debate: against the reduction of grav- ity to geometry . 4 2.2 Analysis of the debate . 11 3 What Einstein could have believed 13 3.1 The geodesic equation as the equation of motion of test par- ticles subject to gravity . 14 3.2 Kottler and the generalised law of inertia . 18 4 What Einstein did believe 20 5 Conclusion 27 6 Acknowledgements 28 1 INTRODUCTION 2 1 Introduction What could be more beautiful than the idea that all there is to the world is geometry? What could cause a bigger sense of wonder than finding out that something we do not normally conceive as geometrical is exactly that at its core: a feature of the geometry of space or spacetime.
    [Show full text]
  • At the Time and the Hardships Explorers Had to Endure When Making Quantitative and Qualitative Observa- Tions. This Aspect of Be
    194 Book Reviews: Modern at the time and the hardships explorers had to endure when making quantitative and qualitative observa- tions. This aspect of Bessels’s account might have been of even greater value to historians of science if Barr had included a translation of an appendix summarizing scientific results, including Bessels’s interpretation of the tidal data he collected—though Barr rightly points out that these results had already been published in English in contemporary literature. Barr’s translation of Bessels’s several-hundred-page work is diligent. He has managed to retain much of the feel of the original, while also ensuring smooth readability in English. Barr’s comprehensive knowl- edge of the history of arctic exploration becomes palpable in the extensive and helpful footnotes he has added. Sometimes, however, the detail they contain can be overwhelming to the reader less familiar with polar exploration and its history. All the images included in the original publication are reproduced in high quality in this sturdy paperback. The entire work is also available through an open-access scheme, although its sheer length will make this relevant primarily to those hoping to use a search function to find very specific details within Bessels’s account. In sum, this translation is of great value to anyone interested in the history of polar science and explo- ration and should be included in any library devoted to these topics. Moreover, Polaris: The Chief Scien- tist’s Recollections of the American North Pole Expedition, 1871–73, breaks down a major language barrier at a time when historians are increasingly turning toward an international, comparative narrative for the history of the engagement with the polar regions.
    [Show full text]
  • On the Argument from Physics and General Relativity
    1 On the Argument from Physics and General Relativity Christopher Gregory Weaver This is a draft of a paper that has been accepted for publication in Erkenntnis. Please cite and quote from the version that will appear in Erkenntnis. Abstract: I argue that the best interpretation of the general theory of relativity (GTR) has need of a causal entity (i.e., the gravitational field), and causal structure that is not reducible to light cone structure. I suggest that this causal interpretation of GTR helps defeat a key premise in one of the most popular arguments for causal reductionism, viz., the argument from physics. “The gravitational field manifests itself in the motion of bodies.” - Einstein and Infeld (1949, p. 209) 0. Introduction Causal anti-reductionism or fundamentalism is the view that the causal relation is not grounded in, reduced to, or completely determined by some non-causal phenomenon or phenomena. Causal reductionism is the doctrine that obtaining causal relations are grounded in, reduced to, or completely determined by natural nomicity coupled with the world’s unfolding non-causal history. There are two commonly traveled direct paths to causal reductionism. First, one could try to demonstrate that a reductive theory of the causal relation is correct. The accounts of David Fair (1979) and David Lewis (1986a, c) constitute reductive theories. Fair (1979, p. 236) argued that causation is nothing over and above the transfer of momentum or energy (a conserved quantity), while Lewis maintained that causation reduces to counterfactual dependence or the ancestral of that relation.1 Lewis’s complete story characterized counterfactual dependence in terms of the truth of particular counterfactual conditionals whose truth-conditions are strongly related to obtaining degreed similarity relations between possible, albeit, concrete physical worlds.2 Laws of nature and the overall history of the involved concrete physical worlds fix the similarity relations.
    [Show full text]
  • THE IMPACT of WORLD WAR I on RELATIVITY: a PROGRESS REPORT by Virginia Trimble University of California Irvine, Las Cumbres Obse
    THE IMPACT OF WORLD WAR I ON RELATIVITY: A PROGRESS REPORT By Virginia Trimble University of California Irvine, Las Cumbres Observatory and Queen Jadwiga Observatory, Rzepiennik, Poland From an astronomical and relativistic point of view, the Great War began with the August, 1914 capture and imprisonment of the members of a German eclipse expedition that had gone to the Crimea to look, at the request of Einstein, for bending of starlight by the sun. And it ended in 1919 with the Eddington-inspired measurements of that light bending from Principe and Sobral and with the founding of the International Astronomical Union by scientists from “the countries at war with the Central Powers.” In between came unprecedented, and in some ways unequaled, death and destruction. The scientists lost were mostly too young to have made an impact (Henry Moseley and Karl Schwarzschild are exceptions), but many of the best-known of the next generation had, if citizens of the belligerent countries, served on the battle lines, and most of the rest contributed in some other way. It may come as a surprise to find that both theoretical physics and observational astronomy of relevance to general relativity continued to take place and that there was a certain amount of communication of results, information, and even goods in both directions. The early post-war years saw something of a flowering of the subject, before the majority of physicists turned their attention to quantum mechanics and astronomers to stellar physics, though both had already been under consideration during the war. War-based bitterness between French and German scholars was surely part of the context in which Einstein and Henri Bergson faced off on 6 April 1922, in a debate on the nature of time, as part of an Einsteinian visit to Paris that had originally been planned for Fall, 1914.
    [Show full text]
  • The Principle of Equivalence As a Criterion of Identity
    Synthese https://doi.org/10.1007/s11229-018-01897-w The principle of equivalence as a criterion of identity Ryan Samaroo1,2 Received: 15 May 2017 / Accepted: 28 July 2018 © The Author(s) 2018 Abstract In 1907 Einstein had the insight that bodies in free fall do not “feel” their own weight. This has been formalized in what is called “the principle of equivalence.” The principle motivated a critical analysis of the Newtonian and special-relativistic concepts of inertia, and it was indispensable to Einstein’s development of his theory of gravitation. A great deal has been written about the principle. Nearly all of this work has focused on the content of the principle and whether it has any content in Einsteinian gravitation, but more remains to be said about its methodological role in the development of the theory. I argue that the principle should be understood as a kind of foundational principle known as a criterion of identity. This work extends and substantiates a recent account of the notion of a criterion of identity by William Demopoulos. Demopoulos argues that the notion can be employed more widely than in the foundations of arithmetic and that we see this in the development of physical theories, in particular space–time theories. This new account forms the basis of a general framework for applying a number of mathematical theories and for distinguishing between applied mathematical theories that are and are not empirically constrained. Keywords Principle of equivalence · Criterion of identity · Foundations of space-time theories · Frege · Einstein · Newton 1 Introduction “The principle of equivalence,” which Einstein originally used to refer to one particular statement, has come to refer to a number of interrelated principles in the theory of Dedicated to the memory of William (Bill) Demopoulos.
    [Show full text]
  • “Gravitation” in the German Speaking Physics Community
    Version vom 22. 6. 2016 General relativity and the growth of a sub-discipline “gravitation” in the German speaking physics community Hubert Goenner Institute for Theoretical Physics University G¨ottingen Friedrich-Hund-Platz 1 37077 G¨ottingen 1 Introduction During the 19th century, the topic of gravitation had been firmly embedded into the teaching of Newtonian mechanics although, occasionally, other the- ories of gravitation had also been discussed during this century (Huygens, Secchi, Lesage-Thomson, Weber-Tisserand etc) [1], [2]. Gravitational theory as a topic of research was the exception, though; only its applications played a role. Focal points were celestial mechanics and the study of the Earth’s gravitational field – in the framework of the Newtonian gravitational force. Cf. the section “Universal gravitation” of 1908 in Winkelmann’s “Handbuch der Physik” by Felix Auerbach (1856-1933) [3] who in 1921 also contributed a popularizing booklet on relativity theory [4]. It seems interesting that even in the 1960s, in an encyclopedic dictionary, a rigorous separation between the entries for gravitation/gravity (with no mention of Einstein’s theory) and general relativity was upheld [5]. Here, we will follow the growth of gravitational theory, i.e. relativistic theories of gravitation, mainly Einstein’s, as a branch of physics in the sense 1 arXiv:1607.03324v1 [physics.hist-ph] 12 Jul 2016 of social, more precisely institutional history. Thus, the accompanying con- ceptional development is touched only as a way of loosening the narration and as help for a better understanding.2 As a first step, we will ask when 1We are aware that there is an overlap between work on special relativistic theories and past research in general relativity.
    [Show full text]
  • On Kottler's Path: Origin and Evolution of the Premetric Program in Gravity
    On Kottler’s path: origin and evolution of the premetric program in gravity and in electrodynamics∗ Friedrich W. Hehl1, Yakov Itin2, Yuri N. Obukhov3 1Inst. for Theor. Physics, Univ. of Cologne, Germany and Dept. Physics & Astron., Univ. of Missouri, Columbia, MO, USA; [email protected] 2Inst. of Math. Hebrew Univ. of Jerusalem and Jerusalem College of Technology, Israel; [email protected] 3Nuclear Safety Inst., Russian Academy of Sciences, Moscow, Russia; [email protected] Abstract In 1922, Kottler put forward the program to remove the gravita- tional potential, the metric of spacetime, from the fundamental equa- tions in physics as far as possible. He successfully applied this idea to Newton’s gravitostatics and to Maxwell’s electrodynamics, where arXiv:1607.06159v1 [gr-qc] 21 Jul 2016 Kottler recast the field equations in premetric form and specified a metric-dependent constitutive law. We will discuss the basics of the premetric approach and some of its beautiful consequences, like the di- vision of universal constants into two classes. We show that classical ∗Based on an invited talk given at the Annual Meeting of the German Physical Society (DPG) in Berlin on 20 March 2015, “Working Group on Philosophy of Physics (AGPhil)”. We sincerely thank Dennis Lehmkuhl (Wuppertal, now Pasadena) and his co-organizers Meinard Kuhlmann (Mainz) and Wolfgang Pietsch (Munich) [92] for the invitation. In the present version, we appreciably enriched our text by adding more formalism. We apologize to the philosophers for any inconvenience. A short version of this paper will be submitted to the International Journal of Modern Physics D.
    [Show full text]
  • The Equivalence Principle(S)
    View metadata, citation and similar papers at core.ac.uk brought to you by CORE provided by PhilSci Archive The Equivalence Principle(s) Dennis Lehmkuhl Lichtenberg Group for History and Philosophy of Physics, University of Bonn Email: [email protected] Forthcoming in the Routledge Companion to the Philosophy of Physics1 Abstract I discuss the relationship between different versions of the equiva- lence principle in general relativity, among them Einstein's equivalence principle, the weak equivalence principle, and the strong equivalence principle. I show that Einstein's version of the equivalence principle is intimately linked to his idea that in GR gravity and inertia are unified to a single field, quite like the electric and magnetic field had been unified in special relativistic electrodynamics. At the same time, what is now often called the strong equivalence principle, related to the local validity of special relativity, can also be found in Einstein's writings, albeit by a different name and clearly separated from what he calls the equivalence principle. I discuss both the development of Einstein's thoughts on the different versions of the equivalence principle, their relationship to the relativity principle, as well as later reflections and variants proposed. Contents 1 Introduction: A manifold of principles 2 2 The Weak Equivalence Principle: How it all began 4 1This chapter was written for the Routledge Companion in 2017; the current version is an updated version from 2019. Participating in the companion included adhering to a strict page limit, as well as aiming to write a text that would be accessible both to advanced undergraduates and to graduate students, while at the same time aiming to be useful to researchers in physics on the one hand and history and philosophy of physics on the other.
    [Show full text]
  • Claudia E. Graf-Grossmann and Tilman Sauer, Marcel Grossmann
    Claudia E. Graf-Grossmann and Tilman Sauer, Marcel Grossmann. For the Love of Mathematics (Springer, 2018). Scott Walter To cite this version: Scott Walter. Claudia E. Graf-Grossmann and Tilman Sauer, Marcel Grossmann. For the Love of Mathematics (Springer, 2018).. 2020, pp.194-195. hal-02975669 HAL Id: hal-02975669 https://hal.archives-ouvertes.fr/hal-02975669 Submitted on 31 Oct 2020 HAL is a multi-disciplinary open access L’archive ouverte pluridisciplinaire HAL, est archive for the deposit and dissemination of sci- destinée au dépôt et à la diffusion de documents entific research documents, whether they are pub- scientifiques de niveau recherche, publiés ou non, lished or not. The documents may come from émanant des établissements d’enseignement et de teaching and research institutions in France or recherche français ou étrangers, des laboratoires abroad, or from public or private research centers. publics ou privés. Distributed under a Creative Commons Attribution - NonCommercial| 4.0 International License Claudia E. Graf-Grossmann. Marcel Grossmann. For the Love of Mathematics. Translated by William D. Brewer. (Springer Biographies.) xviii + 261 pp., bibl., illus., index. Cham, Switzerland: Springer, 2018. £24.99 (cloth), ISBN 9783319900766. Isis 111(1), 2020, 194–195. Scott A. Walter∗ 2019-08-22 Contemporary theoretical physics is so tightly bound to mathematics that it is unthinkable to pursue it as a career without a solid background in higher mathematics. This was not true at the turn of the twentieth century, when the subdiscipline was in its infancy, and Albert Einstein was a student at the Polytechnikum in Zurich (now the Eidgen¨ossische Technische Hochschule, or ETH).
    [Show full text]