Plotinus on <I>Eudaimonia</I>: a Commentary on <I>Ennead</I

Total Page:16

File Type:pdf, Size:1020Kb

Plotinus on <I>Eudaimonia</I>: a Commentary on <I>Ennead</I 82 Book Reviews / Th e International Journal of the Platonic Tradition 2 (2008) 76-92 Kiernan McGroarty, Plotinus on Eudaimonia: A Commentary on Ennead 1.4, Oxford: Oxford University Press, 2006, xxiii + 236 pp., $95.00. What does eudaimonia involve, according to Plotinus? Posing this question is particularly difficult in light of the fact that “eudaimonia” is a term specifically associated with Aristotle, and yet eudaimonia for Plotinus differs in important ways from Aristotelian eudaimonia, focusing as it does on soul living the per- fect, true life in the intelligible realm. Posing the question involves further difficulties because Plotinus, according to the report we receive from Porphyry in the Vita Plotini, in fact lived an exemplary life here in the sensible realm, taking in orphans, earning the trust of Roman politicians, and treating friends and students with particular dignity. In short, the virtuous life that Plotinus led appears to be at variance with the vision of the life of eudaimonia on behalf of which Plotinus argues. Plotinus’ ethical writings are located primarily in Ennead I, and interest in and focus on them has increased significantly in recent years, with translations and commentaries by Pavlos Kalligas and Allesandro Linguiti on treatises in Ennead I, a book by Alexandrine Schniewind (with extensive discussion of Ennead I.4), and other articles. Kiernan McGroarty’s translation and com- mentary is the first English translation with commentary on Ennead I.4 (46th out of 54 treatises in Porphyry’s chronological sequencing of the Enneads), and by his own acknowledgement, the author has been able to build upon work done in recent years in order to strengthen his discussion. Th e book includes an introduction which situates well (and briefly) Ennead I.4 within the context of Plotinus’ life and in relation to his philosophical predecessors. Th e text and translation of Ennead I.4 follow, and in the remain- der of the body of the work, McGroarty engages in a detailed commentary on I.4. Th e volume closes with two brief appendices, one focusing on St. Ambrose’s use of Ennead I.4 in his sermon “Jacob and the Happy Life,” and the other providing a brief essay on Plotinus’ views on suicide (with McGroarty arguing, against John Rist in Plotinus: Th e Road to Reality, that Plotinus did allow for the possibility of suicide in certain circumstances). Th e translation of the text is very good. By McGroarty’s own account, he has “sacrificed style for accuracy” (xx), but that accuracy nevertheless brings forth a very readable translation. McGroarty also does not attempt to translate some crucial Greek terms, including eudaimonia and spoudaios (what A.H. Armstrong translated in the Loeb series as “well-being” and “a good man,” respectively). Th is allows the meaning of those words to be understood on the basis of what Plotinus says, not on the basis of preconceptions we may have about them. Fur- ther, McGroarty’s translation makes Plotinus’ language, where appropriate, © Koninklijke Brill NV, Leiden, 2008 DOI: 10.1163/187254708X282321 Downloaded from Brill.com09/28/2021 06:46:33PM via free access Book Reviews / Th e International Journal of the Platonic Tradition 2 (2008) 76-92 83 gender neutral (as opposed to Armstrong’s translation, which is dominated by talk of “man” and “he”). Compare McGroarty’s I.4.11 with Armstrong’s. Th e commentary too is nicely done. McGroarty helpfully begins every chapter of commentary with an overview of the theme of the chapter and some of the major issues to focus on during the chapter. He is particularly attentive in these opening remarks to the logic of Marsilio Ficino’s division of the text into various chapters. In the early chapters of the treatise, where Plo- tinus addresses the views of opposing schools, McGroarty expends much energy reflecting on precisely which school (Aristotelian, Stoic, Epicurean, for example) Plotinus is opposing in a given line of text or through a particular choice of words. Such extremely detailed work will be helpful for scholars who wish to be clear about Plotinus’ philosophical predecessors and his relation to them. As Plotinus turns to setting out his own philosophical position regard- ing eudaimonia in ch. 3 ff., McGroarty rightly focuses on the metaphysical foundations for Plotinus’ views about eudaimonia. Central to this discussion is Plotinus’ belief that while the Stoics are essentially correct (against Aristotle) that the spoudaios who has eudaimonia cannot be affected by adverse circum- stances (ill health, pain, misfortune), the Stoics do not have a sufficient meta- physics to explain the spoudaios’ imperviousness to such misfortunes. Plotinus, by contrast, does, because of the sensible-intelligible distinction central to his Platonic philosophy. Th e spoudaios achieves eudaimonia at the level of Nous, where mind thinks Platonic Forms and thinks them as a unity, not as a series of discrete entities. Because eudaimonia involves this non-discursive thinking of the spoudaios, and because both ontologically and epistemologically, non- discursive thinking, which takes place at the level of Nous, is separate from discursive thinking, which takes place in everyday consciousness, Plotinus is able to provide a theoretical justification for the Plotinian spoudaios’ insuscep- tibility to pain, misfortune, and the like. Th is is a move which the Stoic appears unable to justify theoretically due to the Stoic belief that existence is corporeal. Th e force of this argument becomes very clear in the context of Plotinus’ famous treatment of the “bull of Phalaris.” If we assume that someone is roasted in this bull, Plotinus’ metaphysics allows him to distinguish an outer, sensible person who suffers in the bull and an inner person, residing always among the intelligibles and not composed of matter, who would not suffer during the roasting. By contrast, according to Plotinus, it makes no sense for the Stoics to claim that such an experience is pleasant for the Stoic sage, since there is no comparable metaphysical distinction between an “outer” person and an “inner” person in Stoic thought. Th e above Plotinian position and its accompanying arguments make up much of the philosophical work being done in Ennead I.4. While I am not one Downloaded from Brill.com09/28/2021 06:46:33PM via free access 84 Book Reviews / Th e International Journal of the Platonic Tradition 2 (2008) 76-92 necessarily to agree with all that Porphyry says in the Vita Plotini about Ploti- nus, Porphyry’s general comment about the late treatises—namely, that they show Plotinus’ powers waning—seems apt in the case of this particular trea- tise. It does not show the theoretical or argumentative complexity of even the treatise which precedes it in chronological order—III.7 (45), On Eternity. Th ese comments on Plotinus’ fundamental argument in the treatise and the quality of this piece of argumentation bring us back to McGroarty’s transla- tion and commentary. McGroarty himself acknowledges frequently through the text that there are signs of Plotinus’ waning abilities. Th is, then, makes this reader wonder whether this is the best treatise of Plotinus’ upon which to focus so much energy. Th e obvious retort to this concern, however, is that Plotinus’ ethical thought and argumentation deserve closer scrutiny than they traditionally have received. Th is seems fair, and I applaud such efforts. But it would have been good in this volume to see an even more complete account of the life of the Plotinian spoudaios as engaged both in the abstract non-dis- cursive thinking which Plotinus so often advocates and in the everyday atti- tudes and behaviors of excellence which Plotinus lived. One of the great challenges we face in understanding Plotinus’ approach to eudaimonia and the spoudaios is how we are to integrate these qualities. McGroarty rightly focuses on the relation between civic virtues and purificatory virtues as discussed by Plotinus in I.2 [19], but he seems unable to work through the tension, some- thing for which one might hope in a manuscript such as this. It might be possible to develop an understanding of the relation between the two by focus- ing on what is often referred to as Plotinus’ double-energeia principle, accord- ing to which the activity of the soul at its highest level, Nous, necessarily flows out to produce an activity from the soul, i.e., a human being deeply and inti- mately engaged with the world. In any case, although McGroarty discusses the issue of the self engaged at these two different levels, it’s clear that work remains to be done and that the discussion should continue among all of the scholars who are currently wrestling with this important aspect of Plotinus’ thought. David B. Rehm Mount St. Mary’s University Emmitsburg, Maryland, USA [email protected] Downloaded from Brill.com09/28/2021 06:46:33PM via free access.
Recommended publications
  • Pursuing Eudaimonia LIVERPOOL HOPE UNIVERSITY STUDIES in ETHICS SERIES SERIES EDITOR: DR
    Pursuing Eudaimonia LIVERPOOL HOPE UNIVERSITY STUDIES IN ETHICS SERIES SERIES EDITOR: DR. DAVID TOREVELL SERIES DEPUTY EDITOR: DR. JACQUI MILLER VOLUME ONE: ENGAGING RELIGIOUS EDUCATION Editors: Joy Schmack, Matthew Thompson and David Torevell with Camilla Cole VOLUME TWO: RESERVOIRS OF HOPE: SUSTAINING SPIRITUALITY IN SCHOOL LEADERS Author: Alan Flintham VOLUME THREE: LITERATURE AND ETHICS: FROM THE GREEN KNIGHT TO THE DARK KNIGHT Editors: Steve Brie and William T. Rossiter VOLUME FOUR: POST-CONFLICT RECONSTRUCTION Editor: Neil Ferguson VOLUME FIVE: FROM CRITIQUE TO ACTION: THE PRACTICAL ETHICS OF THE ORGANIZATIONAL WORLD Editors: David Weir and Nabil Sultan VOLUME SIX: A LIFE OF ETHICS AND PERFORMANCE Editors: John Matthews and David Torevell VOLUME SEVEN: PROFESSIONAL ETHICS: EDUCATION FOR A HUMANE SOCIETY Editors: Feng Su and Bart McGettrick VOLUME EIGHT: CATHOLIC EDUCATION: UNIVERSAL PRINCIPLES, LOCALLY APPLIED Editor: Andrew B. Morris VOLUME NINE GENDERING CHRISTIAN ETHICS Editor: Jenny Daggers VOLUME TEN PURSUING EUDAIMONIA: RE-APPROPRIATING THE GREEK PHILOSOPHICAL FOUNDATIONS OF THE CHRISTIAN APOPHATIC TRADITION Author: Brendan Cook Pursuing Eudaimonia: Re-appropriating the Greek Philosophical Foundations of the Christian Apophatic Tradition By Brendan Cook Pursuing Eudaimonia: Re-appropriating the Greek Philosophical Foundations of the Christian Apophatic Tradition, by Brendan Cook This book first published 2013 Cambridge Scholars Publishing 12 Back Chapman Street, Newcastle upon Tyne, NE6 2XX, UK British Library Cataloguing in Publication Data A catalogue record for this book is available from the British Library Copyright © 2013 by Brendan Cook All rights for this book reserved. No part of this book may be reproduced, stored in a retrieval system, or transmitted, in any form or by any means, electronic, mechanical, photocopying, recording or otherwise, without the prior permission of the copyright owner.
    [Show full text]
  • Philosophy As a Path to Happiness
    CORE Metadata, citation and similar papers at core.ac.uk Provided by Helsingin yliopiston digitaalinen arkisto Philosophy as a Path to Happiness Attainment of Happiness in Arabic Peripatetic and Ismaili Philosophy Janne Mattila ACADEMIC DISSERTATION To be publicly discussed, by due permission of the Faculty of Arts at the University of Helsinki in auditorium XII, University main building, on the 13th of June, 2011 at 12 o’clock. ISBN 978-952-92-9077-2 (paperback) ISBN 978-952-10-7001-3 (PDF) http://ethesis.helsinki.fi/ Helsinki University Print Helsinki 2011 2 Abstract The aim of this study is to explore the idea of philosophy as a path to happiness in medieval Arabic philosophy. The starting point is in comparison of two distinct currents within Arabic philosophy between the 10th and early 11th centuries, Peripatetic philosophy, represented by al-Fārābī and Ibn Sīnā, and Ismaili philosophy represented by al-Kirmānī and the Brethren of Purity. These two distinct groups of sources initially offer two contrasting views about philosophy. The attitude of the Peripatetic philosophers is rationalistic and secular in spirit, whereas for the Ismailis philosophy represents the esoteric truth behind revelation. Still, the two currents of thought converge in their view that the ultimate purpose of philosophy lies in its ability to lead man towards happiness. Moreover, they share a common concept of happiness as a contemplative ideal of human perfection, merged together with the Neoplatonic goal of the soul’s reascent to the spiritual world. Finally, for both happiness refers primarily to an otherworldly state thereby becoming a philosophical interpretation of the Quranic accounts of the afterlife.
    [Show full text]
  • Neoplatonism: the Last Ten Years
    The International Journal The International Journal of the of the Platonic Tradition 9 (2015) 205-220 Platonic Tradition brill.com/jpt Critical Notice ∵ Neoplatonism: The Last Ten Years The past decade or so has been an exciting time for scholarship on Neo­ platonism. I ought to know, because during my stint as the author of the “Book Notes” on Neoplatonism for the journal Phronesis, I read most of what was published in the field during this time. Having just handed the Book Notes over to George Boys­Stones, I thought it might be worthwhile to set down my overall impressions of the state of research into Neoplatonism. I cannot claim to have read all the books published on this topic in the last ten years, and I am here going to talk about certain themes and developments in the field rather than trying to list everything that has appeared. So if you are an admirer, or indeed author, of a book that goes unmentioned, please do not be affronted by this silence—it does not necessarily imply a negative judgment on my part. I hope that the survey will nonetheless be wide­ranging and comprehensive enough to be useful. I’ll start with an observation made by Richard Goulet,1 which I have been repeating to students ever since I read it. Goulet conducted a statistical analy­ sis of the philosophical literature preserved in the original Greek, and discov­ ered that almost three­quarters of it (71%) was written by Neoplatonists and commentators on Aristotle. In a sense this should come as no surprise.
    [Show full text]
  • The Stoics and the Practical: a Roman Reply to Aristotle
    DePaul University Via Sapientiae College of Liberal Arts & Social Sciences Theses and Dissertations College of Liberal Arts and Social Sciences 8-2013 The Stoics and the practical: a Roman reply to Aristotle Robin Weiss DePaul University, [email protected] Follow this and additional works at: https://via.library.depaul.edu/etd Recommended Citation Weiss, Robin, "The Stoics and the practical: a Roman reply to Aristotle" (2013). College of Liberal Arts & Social Sciences Theses and Dissertations. 143. https://via.library.depaul.edu/etd/143 This Thesis is brought to you for free and open access by the College of Liberal Arts and Social Sciences at Via Sapientiae. It has been accepted for inclusion in College of Liberal Arts & Social Sciences Theses and Dissertations by an authorized administrator of Via Sapientiae. For more information, please contact [email protected]. THE STOICS AND THE PRACTICAL: A ROMAN REPLY TO ARISTOTLE A Thesis Presented in Partial Fulfillment of the Degree of Doctor of Philosophy August, 2013 BY Robin Weiss Department of Philosophy College of Liberal Arts and Social Sciences DePaul University Chicago, IL - TABLE OF CONTENTS - Introduction……………………..............................................................................................................p.i Chapter One: Practical Knowledge and its Others Technê and Natural Philosophy…………………………….....……..……………………………….....p. 1 Virtue and technical expertise conflated – subsequently distinguished in Plato – ethical knowledge contrasted with that of nature in
    [Show full text]
  • Meet the Philosophers of Ancient Greece
    Meet the Philosophers of Ancient Greece Everything You Always Wanted to Know About Ancient Greek Philosophy but didn’t Know Who to Ask Edited by Patricia F. O’Grady MEET THE PHILOSOPHERS OF ANCIENT GREECE Dedicated to the memory of Panagiotis, a humble man, who found pleasure when reading about the philosophers of Ancient Greece Meet the Philosophers of Ancient Greece Everything you always wanted to know about Ancient Greek philosophy but didn’t know who to ask Edited by PATRICIA F. O’GRADY Flinders University of South Australia © Patricia F. O’Grady 2005 All rights reserved. No part of this publication may be reproduced, stored in a retrieval system or transmitted in any form or by any means, electronic, mechanical, photocopying, recording or otherwise without the prior permission of the publisher. Patricia F. O’Grady has asserted her right under the Copyright, Designs and Patents Act, 1988, to be identi.ed as the editor of this work. Published by Ashgate Publishing Limited Ashgate Publishing Company Wey Court East Suite 420 Union Road 101 Cherry Street Farnham Burlington Surrey, GU9 7PT VT 05401-4405 England USA Ashgate website: http://www.ashgate.com British Library Cataloguing in Publication Data Meet the philosophers of ancient Greece: everything you always wanted to know about ancient Greek philosophy but didn’t know who to ask 1. Philosophy, Ancient 2. Philosophers – Greece 3. Greece – Intellectual life – To 146 B.C. I. O’Grady, Patricia F. 180 Library of Congress Cataloging-in-Publication Data Meet the philosophers of ancient Greece: everything you always wanted to know about ancient Greek philosophy but didn’t know who to ask / Patricia F.
    [Show full text]
  • The Ancient Greek Philosophers, Motivated
    The ancient Greek philosophers and coaching In the pursue of Eudemonia (flouring life) The ancient Greek philosophers, motivated by their love of knowledge (the actual word “philosopher” derives from the Greek words “filos” and “Sophia” which mean “friend” and “wisdom” respectively) have been preoccupied with the investigation of the reasons for human existence and the way we should live, so as to be consistent with our reason for being. Their views widely appealed to the western world and formed the foundation for western philosophy and psychology, influencing the philosophers who followed, from the oldest to the most contemporary ones and inspiring passionate support but not without also being questioned. Today, most of their views seem to have lost nothing of their lustre and stand out like shining beacons, especially now that the western world is desperately seeking answers in order to relight its fires!!! In the text below, I refer to Aristotle and Socrates, the principles and practices they bequeathed us, so as to prove that these have a lot in common with the principles and practices of coaching. In addition, I will attempt to prove that Socrates is the first ever coach!!! Aristotle, a student of Socrates and Plato, the most important philosopher according to some and teacher of Great Alexander, clearly stated why and how men should live. According to Aristotle we should pursue happiness, well-being or in other words eudaimonia. And a happy life is a life full of virtue! o A coach urges us to lead a happy life. According to Aristotle, true happiness is permanent and timeless; it is achieved when people develop and leverage all their capabilities.
    [Show full text]
  • 1 the Compatibility of Augustine's Formal Account of Eudaimonia With
    1 The Compatibility of Augustine’s Formal Account of Eudaimonia with his Neoplatonic Metaphysics of Goodness. Abstract: Augustine’s moral philosophy follows the general pattern of ancient moral theory by distinguishing between the formal and substantive conceptions of ethical eudaimonism. In this paper, I develop Augustine’s ethical theory, demonstrating its grounding in both eudaimonism and Christian Neo- Platonism: the former provides its formal structure, the latter its substance or content, consisting in its metaphysical grounding and teleological end. In the first section, I consider the formal structure of Augustine’s ethics. Second, I argue God’s role as the summum bonum is grounded in Augustine’s Neo- Platonic metaphysics of goodness. Finally, I explore a puzzle raised by Augustine’s ethics: is loving God for His own sake compatible with loving God because it makes us happy? In other words, is Augustine’s formal account of eudaimonia compatible with the substance of his ethics informed by Christian Neoplatonism? 2 In De Moribus Ecclesiae Catholicae, Augustine makes two significant claims that summarize his moral philosophy. First, everyone desires happiness and this consists in loving man’s highest good. Second, since this highest good is identified with God himself, man’s happiness is only found in God.1 This pair of principles encapsulate two streams of ethical thought converging together to form Augustine’s moral philosophy, following the general pattern of ancient moral theory by distinguishing between the formal and substantive conceptions of ethical eudaimonism. In what follows, I develop Augustine’s moral philosophy, demonstrating its grounding in both eudaimonism and Christian Neoplatonism: the former provides its formal structure, the latter its substance or content, consisting in its metaphysical grounding and teleological end.
    [Show full text]
  • Sextus Empiricus and the Scientific Scepticism
    ENCEPHALOS 50, 62-74, 2013 SEXTUS EMPIRICUS AND THE SCIENTIFIC SCEPTI- CISM STAVROS J.BALOYANNIS* Summary philosophical books, which survived, but remained for long in obscurity, been rediscovered in the late Renaissance. Two Sextus Empiricus is the most eminent representative of these works on the title, “Adversus Mathematikus”, include of the ancient sceptisism, which is a Post-Classical, Hellenis- large number of strong arguments against the Logicians, the tic philosophy based on the criterion of life, the experience Physicists and the Ethicists. The third and most important of and the analysis of phenomena, aiming to provide a straight the books on the title “Outlines of Pyrrhonism” provides an out- and practical way of life, leading to interior peace and mental line of Pyrrhonian scepticism, incorporating at the same time tranquility, sharply opposed to a purely theoretical pursuit of his own philosophical doctrines. Sextus offers thoroughly a dogmatic philosophy. The term “sceptic” is a derivative of the general overview of scepticism, describing and explaining the noun, skepsis (σκέψις), which means thought, examination, meaning of the sceptical investigation, the value of suspen- inquiry, consideration, meditation and investigation. The scep- sion of judgment and the importance of the sceptical dialectics. tical school was connected for a long period of time with the Sextus insists that the skepticism does not accept or reject any Empirical school of physicians, who based the good medical impression and substantially does not affirm or deny anything. practice on the clinical experience rather than on the theoret- Sextus claims that appearances (φαινόμενα) are the practical ical erudition, dedicating themselves to observation, memory criteria of approaching to the truth and by the continuous inves- and continuous clinical practice.
    [Show full text]
  • Happiness in Ancient Philosophy
    View metadata, citation and similar papers at core.ac.uk brought to you by CORE provided by Helsingin yliopiston digitaalinen arkisto Happiness in Ancient Philosophy Juha Sihvola Helsinki Collegium for Advanced Studies The article discusses the conceptions of eudaimonia in the philosophy of Socrates, Plato, Aristotle, and the Stoics and argues against the growing tendency to make a sharp distinction between the ancient notion of eudaimonia and the modern notion of happiness. On the contrary, the traditional translation of eudaimonia as happiness is defended because it emphasizes the powerfulness of the challenge that the ancient eudaimonistic theories of ethics provide for our contemporary ways of thinking. Comparison with the ancient views encourages us to reject a purely subjective conception of happiness, defined with a reference to beliefs that one is getting the important things one wants and accompanying pleasant affects. The paradigm of happiness as subjective desire-satisfaction is shown to disregard the notion’s more objective aspects which can be uncovered by philosophical reflection. At the beginning of his famous Nicomachean Ethics, Aristotle states that his aim is to determine what the ultimate end or good is that human beings aim at in their lives (I 2, 1094a18–28). He spells out certain formal criteria that this final end should fulfill: it is something complete and self-sufficient, something we aim at for its own sake and not for the sake of anything else. When we have reached this end, our lives are as good as they can possibly become; nothing further can improve our lives in any way.
    [Show full text]
  • Can an Ancient Greek Sceptic Be Eudaimôn (Or Happy)? and What Difference Does the Answer Make to Us?
    Journal of Ancient Philosophy Vol. VI 2012 Issue 1 Can an ancient Greek sceptic be eudaimôn (or happy)? And what difference does the answer make to us? Richard Bett (Johns Hopkins University) The paper explores how far the ancient Greek sceptics in fact accept, and how far they should accept, the central Greek ethical notion of eudaimonia , usually translated "happiness" - and what, if anything, the answers may tell us today. The first section shows that sceptics of both the Academic and Pyrrhonist traditions frequently employ the notion of eudaimonia , apparently without discomfort. The second section draws attention to a contrast within the relevant works of Sextus Empiricus - one of them being willing to speak of the sceptic's eudaimonia and the other entirely avoiding this - and considers some possible reasons why, at some point in his life, Sextus might have found the notion problematic. The answers suggested are, first, that the term eudaimonia , at least as normally used by non-sceptical philosophers, presupposes that it is possible to rank human lives objectively in terms of their levels of well-being, and second, that the term standardly carries with it a commitment to a certain kind of long-term structure in one's life; there is at least a serious question whether either of these is consistent with sceptical suspension of judgement. The third section examines how far a sceptic could aspire to happiness , where this is not assumed to be equivalent to eudaimonia , and touches on several modern philosophers who have focused on happiness or, more generally, on well- being.
    [Show full text]
  • Sextus Was No Eudaimonist
    Georgia State University ScholarWorks @ Georgia State University Philosophy Theses Department of Philosophy 7-14-2008 Sextus was no Eudaimonist Joseph B. Bullock Follow this and additional works at: https://scholarworks.gsu.edu/philosophy_theses Part of the Philosophy Commons Recommended Citation Bullock, Joseph B., "Sextus was no Eudaimonist." Thesis, Georgia State University, 2008. https://scholarworks.gsu.edu/philosophy_theses/40 This Thesis is brought to you for free and open access by the Department of Philosophy at ScholarWorks @ Georgia State University. It has been accepted for inclusion in Philosophy Theses by an authorized administrator of ScholarWorks @ Georgia State University. For more information, please contact [email protected]. SEXTUS WAS NO EUDAIMONIST by JOSEPH B. BULLOCK Under the Direction of Dr. Tim O’Keefe ABSTRACT Ancient Greek philosophical schools are said to share a common structure in their ethical theories which is characterized by a eudaimonistic teleology based in an understanding of human nature. At first glance, the skepticism of Sextus Empiricus as described in the Outlines of Pyrrhonism seems to fit into this model insofar as he describes the end of the skeptic as ataraxia, a common account of the expression of human happiness. I argue that this is a misunderstanding of Sextus’s philosophy for several reasons. “The end of skepticism” cannot be eudaimonistic or teleological in the way that other ancient ethical theories are typically understood; moreover, ataraxia is not an end derived from a theory about human nature. For these reasons, the skeptical way of life is radically different than the ethical theories proposed by other schools. I argue that this difference is a result of the character of the skeptical enterprise which involves the implicit rejection of norms in both the epistemological and the ethical spheres.
    [Show full text]
  • A Study on Dikaiosune and Eudaimonia in Plato's Republic
    A STUDY ON DIKAIOSUNE AND EUDAIMONIA IN PLATO’S REPUBLIC A THESIS SUBMITTED TO THE GRADUATE SCHOOL OF SOCIAL SCIENCES OF MIDDLE EAST TECHNICAL UNIVERSITY BY EYLÜL ŞENTUNA IN PARTIAL FULFILLMENT OF THE REQUIREMENTS FOR THE DEGREE OF MASTER OF SCIENCE IN THE DEPARTMENT PHILOSOPHY FEBRUARY 2012 i Approval of the Graduate School of Social Sciences _____________________ Prof. Dr. Meliha Altunışık Director I certify that this thesis satisfies all the requirements as a thesis for the degree of Master of Science of Philosophy. _____________________ Prof. Dr. Ahmet İnam Head of Department This is to certify that we have read this thesis and that in our opinion it is fully adequate, in scope and quality, as a thesis for the degree of Master of Science of Philosopy. _____________________ Prof. Dr. Ahmet İnam Supervisor Examining Committee Members Assoc. Prof. Ertuğrul R. TURAN (AU,PHIL) _____________________ Prof. Dr. Ahmet İNAM (METU,PHIL) ______________________ Assist. Prof. Elif ÇIRAKMAN (METU,PHIL) ______________________ ii I hereby declare that all information in this document has been obtained and presented in accordance with academic rules and ethical conduct. I also declare that, as required by these rules and conduct, I have fully cited and referenced all material and results that are not original to this work. Name, Last name : Eylül Şentuna Signature : iii ABSTRACT A STUDY ON DIKAOSUNE AND EUDAIMONIA IN PLATO’S REPUBLIC Şentuna, Eylül M.S., Department of Philosophy Supervisor: Prof. Dr. Ahmet İnam February 2012, 74 pages The aim of this study is to analyze the concept of dikaiosunê in Plato’s Republic with its main aspects.
    [Show full text]