Forst, Rainer. "Justifying Justification: Reply to My Critics." Justice, Democracy and the Right to Justification: Rainer Forst in Dialogue

Total Page:16

File Type:pdf, Size:1020Kb

Forst, Rainer. Forst, Rainer. "Justifying Justification: Reply to My Critics." Justice, Democracy and the Right to Justification: Rainer Forst in Dialogue. Ed. Rainer Forst. : Bloomsbury Academic, 2014. 169–216. Bloomsbury Collections. Web. 2 Oct. 2021. <http://dx.doi.org/10.5040/9781472544735.ch-008>. Downloaded from Bloomsbury Collections, www.bloomsburycollections.com, 2 October 2021, 17:03 UTC. Copyright © Rainer Forst and contributors, 2014. You may share this work for non-commercial purposes only, provided you give attribution to the copyright holder and the publisher, and provide a link to the Creative Commons licence. 8 Justifying Justification: Reply to My Critics Rainer Forst The task of replying to the distinguished colleagues gathered here presents an aporia for me. For it is such a great honour and pleasure to have these powerful minds comment on my work that out of sheer gratitude I feel I should applaud everything they say. But at the same time, that would violate the game of giving and asking for reasons that we are playing here – and it would be disrespectful of the marvellous reconstructions and thorough criticisms they have to offer. So I fear I am forced to show my gratitude by a response that explains, defends and refines my often inchoate and muddled views – though not really retracting. But I assume that – knowing me – my dear colleagues also did not quite expect me to go that far. I also want to express my heartfelt thanks for the completely unde- served privilege of being in the position to reply to these critics – and a special thanks to David Owen who, together with Matt Matravers, organized the wonderful conference at the University of York on my work in June 2011, where a number of these papers (and others which will appear in a second volume) were presented. David was also responsible for organizing a panel at the Annual Meeting of the American Political Science Association in Seattle in September 2011, from which three more papers included here stem.1 I am deeply indebted to him. 1 There was also a symposium at the American Philosophical Association’s Eastern Division Meeting 2012 in Atlanta with comments by Seyla Benhabib, Jeff Flynn and Matthias Fritsch to which I replied; the symposium is forth coming in Political Theory. 170 Justice, Democracy and the Right to Justification From Germany to Scotland – and back In his excellent piece, Andrea Sangiovanni forces me to clarify my discourse-theoretical constructivism, and I could not think of a better challenge to explain the moral-philosophical ‘groundwork’ of my Neo- Kantian view. I admire Sangiovanni’s work on justice and the relation between morality and politics, and I feel close to his ‘practice-dependent’ account of justice, though I have some questions about the relation of immanence and transcendence with respect to that.2 I leave that aside here, as I will have further occasion to comment on my view of practice in replying to some of the other papers. In a fine instance of Humean-humane empathy and solidarity, Sangiovanni wants to save me from German rationalism and asks me to join the club of what he calls Scottish constructivists, which strikes me as a rather new club, given that constructivism generally holds that the principles of construction are principles of practical reason – implying a notion of practical reason for which Hume had little time. So I think that Sangiovanni’s Scotland is already closer to the Continent than is normally the case. Still, according to him, ‘rationalist constructivism’ cannot stand on its own feet as long as it lacks a good account of moral emotions, like empathy. For him, these ‘contingent human sensibilities’ present the ‘seat of normativity’ (58); in other words, only where empathy is coupled with ‘deliberative reflection and action’ (62) can we find the very ground of morality. I think I should, in typical dialectical fashion, agree and (mostly, I fear) disagree: Empathy is an important capacity of responsible moral agents, but it can only be such if it is guided by practical reason and indeed a part of practical reason, properly understood. Otherwise, empathy can be partial and thus also be ‘morally blind’, to use Sangio- vanni’s term, to which I will return. In conjunction with norm-guided practical deliberation, empathy is a necessary condition for engaging 2 See my ‘Transnational Justice and Democracy. Overcoming Three Dogmas of Political Theory’, in Eva Erman and Sofia Näsström (eds), Political Equality in Transnational Democracy. New York: Palgrave Macmillan, 2013d, 41–59. Justifying Justification: Reply to My Critics 171 in moral justification in the right way, but that does not mean that it has a ‘grounding’ role to play. For the reconstruction of the moral point of view follows another route and presupposes a reconstruction of moral validity claims and criteria for their justification (one notion of ‘grounding’ I use),3 and, furthermore, the validity of the fundamental right and the categorical duty of justification cannot be made contingent upon the existence of certain humanitarian motives of persons (another notion of ‘grounding’). In a nutshell, that would be to mistake a justificatory and an explanatory account of moral action and to exchange the standpoint of the first and second person with that of the third person – a mistake easily made by those fully enthralled by Scottish empiricism, as Andrea Sangiovanni is not, I believe. According to my Kantian view of the autonomy of morality, morality can only be based on moral grounds, namely on the respect for every other person as an equal in the normative space of justifications, regardless of how close to or distant one feels from him or her. Moral empathy thus has gone through the filter of justificatory reason, not the other way around, for it recognizes the moral status of others as equals and thereby abstracts from the different ways in which we empathize with others as an empirical and emotional fact. That does not mean that moral respect only regards others as ‘generalized others’, as Seyla Benhabib once called it4; rather, it asks us to respect others as ‘concrete’, finite and needy, and yet still through a generalizing lens, not giving priority to some persons that could not be justified to all others as equals. As moral persons, we are all equal authorities in the realm of reasons. But I am leaping ahead. In order to do justice to Sangiovanni’s rescue efforts and in order to try to save him from Humeanism in return, 3 For the different ways to understand what it means to ‘ground’ morality, see my The Right to Justification, New York: Columbia University Press, 2012a, 22f. (henceforth RJ). 4 Seyla Benhabib, Situating the Self. Gender, Community and Postmodernism in Contemporary Ethics. New York: Routledge, 1992, ch. 5. See also the exchange between Rainer Forst, ‘Situations of the Self: Reflections on Seyla Benhabib’s Version of Critical Theory’,Philosophy & Social Criticism 23 (1997), 79–96, and Benhabib, ‘On Reconciliation and Respect, Justice and the Good Life: Response to Herta Nagl-Docekal and Rainer Forst’, ibid., pp. 97–114. 172 Justice, Democracy and the Right to Justification I will start from the basic tenets of Sangiovanni’s fine reconstruction of constructivism. There is much I agree with here, such as the thesis about the ‘stance-dependence’ of moral claims (31), yet I would emphasize the non-arbitrary, rational character of that stance, being guided by principles of practical reason. (I will come back to my notion of reason and that of Sangiovanni, for there one of our basic disagreements seems to lie.) Sangiovanni is also correct in locating my constructivism in the camp that makes no strong metaphysical investments – I call it a ‘practical’ and not a ‘metaphysical’ form of constructivism.5 That means that the reconstruction of reasonable principles of construction can remain agnostic about whether in following these principles moral reasons are ‘produced’ or ‘discovered’. In a further important step, Sangiovanni emphasizes that construc- tivists believe that the proper procedure of construction (or justification) generates categorical moral reasons and norms which ‘bind us whether or not we desire to be so bound or have an interest in being so bound’ (33). As I said above and as Sangiovanni affirms himself (59), this is no small burden for any form of constructivism that aims to settle on Scottish turf. Furthermore, Sangiovanni rightly stresses, as do I, that Kantian constructivists in particular need to explain the strong normativity of the constraints and principles of the justification procedure. And since this form of normativity obviously cannot be generated through the procedure which it is to ground, Sangiovanni sees a dilemma there: either one refers to an independent set of moral values to justify the procedure and thus includes a heteronomous normative element or one looks for non-moral grounds and then lacks moral reasons to engage in the procedure in the first place. This is indeed a problem that has haunted many discussions of constructivism6; and it has led to 5 RJ, p. 50. 6 See, for example, Onora O’Neill, Constructions of Reason. Explorations of Kant’s Practical Philosophy. Cambridge: Cambridge University Press, 1989, chs 3 and 11. Christine Korsgaard, The Constitution of Agency. Essays on Practical Reason and Moral Psychology. Oxford: Oxford University Press, 2008, ch. 10. Justifying Justification: Reply to My Critics 173 different versions of it that Sangiovanni calls – following Susan Street – ‘restricted’ and ‘unrestricted constructivism’ (34). In that connection, I have criticized Habermas’s constructivist discourse theory for not providing adequate moral grounds for the normativity of the discourse principle.7 My own suggestion tries to avoid that dilemma by interpreting the principle of justification in moral contexts as a moral principle of practical reason, thus going back to Kant’s essential thesis that the categorical imperative is a moral principle of practical reason.
Recommended publications
  • Justification and Emancipation: the Critical Theory of Rainer Forst. Edited by Amy Allen and Eduardo Mendieta. University Park
    UvA-DARE (Digital Academic Repository) [Review of: A. Allen, E. Mendieta (2019) Justification and emancipation : the critical theory of Rainer Forst] Skirke, C. DOI 10.1111/ejop.12588 Publication date 2020 Document Version Final published version Published in European journal of philosophy License CC BY-NC-ND Link to publication Citation for published version (APA): Skirke, C. (2020). [Review of: A. Allen, E. Mendieta (2019) Justification and emancipation : the critical theory of Rainer Forst]. European journal of philosophy, 28(3), 815–819. https://doi.org/10.1111/ejop.12588 General rights It is not permitted to download or to forward/distribute the text or part of it without the consent of the author(s) and/or copyright holder(s), other than for strictly personal, individual use, unless the work is under an open content license (like Creative Commons). Disclaimer/Complaints regulations If you believe that digital publication of certain material infringes any of your rights or (privacy) interests, please let the Library know, stating your reasons. In case of a legitimate complaint, the Library will make the material inaccessible and/or remove it from the website. Please Ask the Library: https://uba.uva.nl/en/contact, or a letter to: Library of the University of Amsterdam, Secretariat, Singel 425, 1012 WP Amsterdam, The Netherlands. You will be contacted as soon as possible. UvA-DARE is a service provided by the library of the University of Amsterdam (https://dare.uva.nl) Download date:01 Oct 2021 DOI: 10.1111/ejop.12588 BOOK REVIEW Justification and emancipation: The critical theory of Rainer Forst Edited by Amy Allen and Eduardo Mendieta University Park, PA: Pennsylvania State University Press, 2019, viii+200 pp.
    [Show full text]
  • The Justification of Basic Rights: a Discourse-Theoretical Approach1 Rainer Forst
    The Justification of Basic Rights: A Discourse-Theoretical Approach1 Rainer Forst 1. Justifying Basic Rights Very few people doubt that it is a fundamental demand of justice that members of legal- political normative orders ought to have legal rights that define their basic standing as subjects of such an order.2 But when it comes to the concrete understanding of such rights, debates abound. What is the nature of these rights – are they an expression of the sovereign will of individuals, or are they based on important human interests? How should these rights be justified – do they have a particular moral ground, and if so, only one or many? In what follows, I suggest a discourse theory of basic legal rights that answers such questions in a way that I argue is superior to rival approaches, such as a will-based or an interest-based theory of rights. The main argument runs as follows.3 Basic rights are reciprocally and generally valid – i.e. mutually justifiable – claims4 on others (agents or institutions) that they should do or refrain from doing certain things determined by the content of these rights. We call these rights basic or fundamental because they define the status of persons as full members of a normative order in such a way that they provide 1 Many thanks for helpful critical remarks to the editors of this journal, Lisette ten Haaf, Elaine Mak and Bertjan Wolthuis and to my critics at the occasion of the VWR conference in June 2016 to whom I will have the pleasure to reply: Laura Valentini, Marcus Düwell, Glen Newey and Stefan Rummens.
    [Show full text]
  • Noumenal Power
    Normative Orders Working Paper 02/2013 Noumenal Power Prof. Dr. Rainer Forst Cluster of Excellence The Formation of Normative Orders www.normativeorders.net Goethe-Universität Frankfurt am Main Grüneburgweg 1, Fach EXC 6, 60629 Frankfurt am Main [email protected] © 2013 by the author(s) 1 Noumenal Power by Rainer Forst 1. In political or social philosophy, we speak about power all the time. Yet the meaning of this important concept is rarely made explicit, especially in the context of normative discussions.1 But as with many other concepts, once one considers it more closely, fundamental problems arise, such as whether a power relation is necessarily a relation of subordination and domination. In the following, I suggest a novel understanding of what power is and what it means to exercise it. The title “noumenal power” might suggest that I am going to speak about a certain form of power in the world of ideas or of thought, and that this will be far removed from the reality of power as a social or institutional phenomenon. In Joseph Nye’s words, one might assume that I have only the “soft power” of persuasion in mind and not the “hard power” of coercion.2 Real and hard power, a “realist” might say, is about the empirical world, it is made of material stuff, like political positions, monetary means or, ultimately, military instruments of force. 1 There are of course exceptions, such as Philip Pettit’s work – see his recent book On the People’s Terms, Cambridge: Cambridge University Press, 2012 – as well as Ian Shapiro’s work, in particular Democratic Justice, New Haven: Yale University Press, 1999, and The Real World of Democratic Theory, Princeton: Princeton University Press, 2011.
    [Show full text]
  • Two Pictures of Justice." Justice, Democracy and the Right to Justification: Rainer Forst in Dialogue
    Forst, Rainer. "Two Pictures of Justice." Justice, Democracy and the Right to Justification: Rainer Forst in Dialogue. Ed. Rainer Forst. : Bloomsbury Academic, 2014. 3–26. Bloomsbury Collections. Web. 1 Oct. 2021. <http://dx.doi.org/10.5040/9781472544735.ch-001>. Downloaded from Bloomsbury Collections, www.bloomsburycollections.com, 1 October 2021, 16:30 UTC. Copyright © Rainer Forst and contributors, 2014. You may share this work for non-commercial purposes only, provided you give attribution to the copyright holder and the publisher, and provide a link to the Creative Commons licence. 1 Two Pictures of Justice Rainer Forst Professor of Political Theory and Philosophy Goethe University Frankfurt, Germany 1. At various times, human beings have made depictions of justice. She appears as the goddess Diké or Justitia, sometimes with, sometimes without a blindfold, though invariably with the sword and symbols of even-handedness and non-partisanship; one need only think, for example, of Lorenzetti’s ‘Allegory of Good Government’ in the Palazzo Pubblico in Siena. Mostly she is depicted as beautiful and sublime, yet at other times also as hard and cruel, as in Klimt’s famous paintings for Vienna University (which were destroyed during the war). Studying such representations is a fascinating enterprise.1 However, the understanding of ‘picture’ which informs my remarks is a different, linguistic, one. In his Philosophical Investigations, Wittgenstein writes: ‘A picture held us captive. And we could not get outside it, for it lay in our language and language seemed to repeat it to us inexorably.’2 A picture of this kind shapes our language in a particular way, brings together the various usages of a word and thus constitutes its ‘grammar’.
    [Show full text]
  • Reflexive Toleration – a Critical Inquiry Into Rainer Forst’S Theory of Toleration
    Uppsala University Faculty of Theology Studies in Systematic Theology, Ethics, and Philosophy of Religion E 30 ECTS-credits Ethics of Religion Spring semester 2017 Master’s Thesis Author: Martin Langby Supervisor: Professor Elena Namli Reflexive Toleration – A Critical Inquiry into Rainer Forst’s Theory of Toleration Abstract This master’s thesis provides a critical inquiry into Rainer Forst’s theory of toleration, including a descriptive section and a normative critical stance of said theory. Being placed in the tradition of critical theory, also applied as the theoretical framework, and using a hermeneutics methodology when approaching the material, the aim is to provide a close reading of Forst’s texts. The research question of the thesis is What are the possibilities and limits of Forst’s theory of toleration when applied to a democratic political community? The descriptive section of Forst's theory of toleration includes sections comprising of what constitutes the domain of toleration, the components and foundation of toleration, and toleration in relation to virtue and politics. In essence, Forst proposes a principle of justification as the foundation of toleration, mainly derived from his political theory of justification, practiced in a reciprocal and universal manner of the participants in a system combined with a reflexive component. The critique includes components of toleration in relation to the need of tradition, ambivalence in relation to the claims of the intolerants, and how spontaneity is needed in contrast to the mechanistic view mainly proposed by Forst. Other sections of the critique include the relation of toleration and whom can participate in the domain of it, inter- and intra-group deviances regarding power and perspective, but also a discussion of toleration and religious minorities – mainly focused on bodily integrity.
    [Show full text]
  • Toleration in Conflict: Past and Present Rainer Forst Frontmatter More Information
    Cambridge University Press 978-0-521-88577-5 - Toleration in Conflict: Past and Present Rainer Forst Frontmatter More information Toleration in Conflict Past and Present The concept of toleration plays a central role in pluralistic societies. It designates a stance which permits conflicts over beliefs and practices to persist while at the same time defusing them, because it is based on reasons for coexistence in conflict – that is, in continuing dissension. A critical examination of the concept makes clear, however, that its content and evaluation are profoundly contested matters and thus that the concept itself stands in conflict. For some, toleration was and is an expression of mutual respect in spite of far-reaching differences, but for others, it is a condescending, potentially repressive attitude and practice. Rainer Forst analyses these conflicts by reconstructing the philosophical and political discourse of toleration since antiquity. He demonstrates the diversity of the justifications and practices of toleration from the Stoics and early Christians to the present day and develops a systematic theory which he tests in discussions of contemporary conflicts over toleration. Rainer Forst is Professor of Political Theory and Philosophy at the Goethe University in Frankfurt am Main, Germany. In addition, he is Co-Director of the interdisciplinary Research Cluster ‘Formation of Normative Orders’ at the Goethe University. His books include Contexts of Justice, The Right to Justification and Justification and Critique. In 2012, he received the Gottfried Wilhelm Leibniz Prize, the highest honour awarded to German researchers. © in this web service Cambridge University Press www.cambridge.org Cambridge University Press 978-0-521-88577-5 - Toleration in Conflict: Past and Present Rainer Forst Frontmatter More information ideas in context Edited by David Armitage, Jennifer Pitts, Quentin Skinner and James Tully The books in this series will discuss the emergence of intellectual traditions and of related new disciplines.
    [Show full text]
  • Jeffrey Flynn August 2013
    JEFFREY FLYNN AUGUST 2013 DEPARTMENT OF PHILOSOPHY [email protected] FORDHAM UNIVERSITY, LINCOLN CENTER CAMPUS OFFICE: 212-636-7928 NEW YORK, NY 10023 ACADEMIC POSITIONS 2013 - Associate Professor Fordham University 2007 - 2013 Assistant Professor Fordham University 2006 - 2007 Assistant Professor Middlebury College 2005 - 2006 Instructor Middlebury College 2004 - 2005 Visiting Instructor Middlebury College EDUCATION Northwestern University Ph.D., Philosophy 2006 Goethe-Universität, Frankfurt DAAD Fellowship 2002-2003 Syracuse University Graduate Program in Philosophy 1997-1998 University of Notre Dame B.A., Philosophy & Anthropology 1995 AREAS OF SPECIALIZATION Critical Social Theory (esp. Habermas) Social and Political Philosophy Human Rights and Humanitarianism FELLOWSHIPS Member, Institute for Advanced Study, School of Social Science, Princeton, NJ, 2013-14. Mellon Sawyer Seminar Faculty Fellow, “Democratic Citizenship and the Recognition of Cultural Differences,” CUNY Graduate Center Seminar, 2012-13. NEH Summer Institute, “Human Rights in Conflict: Interdisciplinary Perspectives,” CUNY Graduate Center, June 24-July 28, 2006. DAAD Fellow, German Academic Exchange Service, 2002-2003. PUBLICATIONS Reframing the Intercultural Dialogue on Human Rights: A Philosophical Approach (Routledge, forthcoming). “System and Lifeworld in Habermas’s Theory of Democracy,” Philosophy & Social Criticism (forthcoming). “Truth, Objectivity, and Experience after the Pragmatic Turn: Bernstein on Habermas’s ‘Kantian Pragmatism,’” in Richard J Bernstein and the Pragmatist Turn in Contemporary Philosophy, Judith M. Green, ed. (Palgrave Macmillan, forthcoming). “Human Rights in History and Contemporary Practice: Source Materials for Philosophy,” in Philosophical Dimensions of Human Rights, Claudio Corradetti, ed. (Springer, 2012). Jeffrey Flynn – Curriculum Vitae, p. 2 “Two Models of Human Rights: Extending the Rawls-Habermas Debate,” in Habermas and Rawls: Disputing the Political, Gordon Finlayson and Fabian Freyenhagen, eds.
    [Show full text]
  • Political Legitimacy and Democracy in Transnational Perspective
    Political Legitimacy and Democracy in Transnational Perspective Rainer Forst and Rainer Schmalz-Bruns (eds) ARENA Report No 2/11 RECON Report No 13 Political Legitimacy and Democracy in Transnational Perspective Rainer Forst and Rainer Schmalz-Bruns (eds) Copyright ARENA and authors ISBN (print) 978-82-93137-30-6 ISBN (online) 978-82-93137-80-1 ARENA Report Series (print) | ISSN 0807-3139 ARENA Report Series (online) | ISSN 1504-8152 RECON Report Series (print) | ISSN 1504-7253 RECON Report Series (online) | ISSN 1504-7261 Printed at ARENA Centre for European Studies University of Oslo P.O. Box 1143, Blindern N-0318 Oslo, Norway Tel: + 47 22 85 87 00 Fax: + 47 22 85 87 10 E-mail: [email protected] http://www.arena.uio.no http://www.reconproject.eu Oslo, March 2011 Cover picture: ‘Untitled… Homage to Mark Rothko’ by Mike Lusk. © Mike Lusk 2007 Preface Reconstituting Democracy in Europe (RECON) is an Integrated Project supported by the European Commission’s Sixth Framework Programme for Research, Priority 7 ‘Citizens and Governance in a Knowledge-based Society’. The five-year project has 21 partners in 13 European countries and New Zealand, and is coordinated by ARENA – Centre for European Studies at the University of Oslo. RECON takes heed of the challenges to democracy in Europe. It seeks to clarify whether democracy is possible under conditions of pluralism, diversity and complex multilevel governance. See more on the project at www.reconproject.eu. The present report is part of RECON’s work package 1 ‘Theoretical Framework’, which seeks to develop an overarching theoretical approach to the study of European democracy.
    [Show full text]
  • Politikon: IAPSS Political Science Journal Vol. 25
    Politikon: IAPSS Political Science Journal Vol. 25 1 Politikon: IAPSS Political Science Journal Vol. 25 Volume 25: December 2014 Special Conference Volume of IAPSS Autumn Convention 2014, Nijmegen, The Netherlands Editor-in-Chief Vit Simral (Czech Republic) Editorial Board Caitlin Bagby (USA) Péter Király (Hungary) Caroline Ronsin (France) Eltion Meka (USA) Laurens Visser (Australia) 2 Politikon: IAPSS Political Science Journal Vol. 25 Table of Contents Editorial Note 4 Rights from the Other Side of the Line: Postcolonial perspectives on human rights Owen Brown 5 Perspectives for a Social Integration of Human rights in the Muslim world Efrem Garlando 27 Human Rights Relations between Europe and Russia A genealogy of diverging concepts Amelie Harbisch 37 Country Specifics of a Universal Right? Freedom of political speech in the Slovak Republic Max Steuer 56 “Positionality” and “Performativity”: Feminist theory and gender studies’ contributions to the construction of the concept of media literacy Raquel Tebaldi 80 Political Cartoon in Ecuador: Exploring a chilling-effect after the sanction against ‘Bonil’ and El Universo David Vásquez Léon 95 Theories of Universal Human Rights and the Individual’s Perspective Linda Walter 120 Call for Papers for Politikon 142 3 Politikon: IAPSS Political Science Journal Vol. 25 Editorial Note Dear Reader, You have before you a special Politikon volume comprised of works presented at the Autumn Convention of the International Association of Political Science Students in Nijmegen, The Netherlands, in October 2014. We selected in total seven original papers that show the wide variety of topics presented at the Convention: from post-colonial perspectives on human rights, through freedom of speech issues in Slovakia, feminist theory’s contribution to the construction of the concept of media literacy, to political cartoons in Ecuador.
    [Show full text]
  • 55Th Frank Fraser Potter Memorial Lecture in Philosophy - Amy Allen
    55th Frank Fraser Potter Memorial Lecture in Philosophy - Amy Allen MATT STICHTER: Good evening, everyone. My name is Matt Stichter. I'm a Professor of Philisophy in the School of Politics, Philosophy, and Public Affairs here at WSU. My colleagues and I would like to welcome you all to the 55th Memorial Lecture celebrating the Potters and their legacy. For those of you who it's the first time here, this annual Memorial Lecture series serves to commemorate the accomplishments of Professor Frank Potter, and his wife Irene, and what they gave to WSU and the community. Frank Potter was actually the first philosopher here at WSU, and was instrumental in starting the Philosophy Department here. In addition, he and his wife Irene regularly hosted students at their home over on B Street for intellectual discussions, for music. They'd play chess. Apparently they'd also get very well-fed. And this intellectual stimulation and generosity on behalf of the Potters really made a deep impact on their students. Furthermore, another accomplishment of the Potters can be seen in the mentoring that Frank Potter did with his students, because he mentored 10 Rhodes scholars over the course of here at WSU. And this Potter lecture series was actually started and funded by one of their students, Mildred Bissinger. And over the years, people who knew the Potters or know about their legacy have generously donated to help keeping this going now in its 55th year. And overall, I think this program helped serve some of the university's grand initiatives challenges with respect to social political issues, creating a more equitable and just society.
    [Show full text]
  • Decolonizing the Normative Foundations of Critical Theory
    Decolonizing the Normative Foundations of Critical Theory AMY ALLEN THE END OF PROGRESS new directions in critical theory New Directions in Critical Theory amy allen, general editor New Directions in Critical Theory presents outstanding classic and contem- porary texts in the tradition of critical social theory, broadly construed. The series aims to renew and advance the program of critical social theory, with a particular focus on theorizing contemporary struggles around gender, race, sexuality, class, and globalization and their complex interconnections. Narrating Evil: A Postmetaphysical Theory of Reflective Judgment, María Pía Lara The Politics of Our Selves: Power, Autonomy, and Gender in Contemporary Critical Theory, Amy Allen Democracy and the Political Unconscious, Noëlle McAfee The Force of the Example: Explorations in the Paradigm of Judgment, Alessandro Ferrara Horrorism: Naming Contemporary Violence, Adriana Cavarero Scales of Justice: Reimagining Political Space in a Globalizing World, Nancy Fraser Pathologies of Reason: On the Legacy of Critical Theory, Axel Honneth States Without Nations: Citizenship for Mortals, Jacqueline Stevens The Racial Discourses of Life Philosophy: Négritude, Vitalism, and Modernity, Donna V. Jones Democracy in What State?, Giorgio Agamben, Alain Badiou, Daniel Bensaïd, Wendy Brown, Jean-Luc Nancy, Jacques Rancière, Kristin Ross, Slavoj Žižek Politics of Culture and the Spirit of Critique: Dialogues, edited by Gabriel Rockhill and Alfredo Gomez-Muller Mute Speech: Literature, Critical Theory, and
    [Show full text]
  • Schriftenverzeichnis Von Mattias Iser
    Curriculum Vitae Mattias Iser October 2019 Binghamton University, State University of New York Department of Philosophy Binghamton, NY 13902-6000 Library Tower 1213 607-777-3492 [email protected] www.mattias-iser.com Academic Appointments 09/2016 – Associate Professor, Department of Philosophy, Binghamton University, State University of New York (SUNY) 09/2014 – 09/2016 Assistant Professor, Department of Philosophy, Binghamton University, State University of New York (SUNY) 12/2009 – 08/2014 Permanent Research Fellow & Member of the Board of Directors, Center for Advanced Studies “Justitia Amplificata: Rethinking Justice – Applied and Global,” Goethe University Frankfurt Spring 2014 Visiting Professor, Department of Philosophy, Karl Franzens- University Graz Spring 2013 Visiting Professor, Department of Philosophy, Karl Franzens- University Graz 03/2012 Visiting Scholar, Department of Philosophy, Karl Franzens- University Graz; invited by Lukas H. Meyer 02/2011 – 04/2011 Visiting Scholar, Department of Philosophy, University of California, Los Angeles (UCLA); invited by Barbara Herman 08/2009 – 10/2009 Visiting Scholar, Department of Philosophy, New York University; invited by Thomas Nagel 08/2005 – 12/2005 Theodor Heuss-Lecturer (Visiting Assistant Professor), New School for Social Research, New York 04/2005 – 11/2009 Junior Faculty for political theory and philosophy, Faculty of the Social Sciences, Goethe-University Frankfurt 10/2003 Visiting Lecturer, Higher School of Economics, Moscow 04/1999 – 03/2005 Pre-doctoral teaching position for political theory and philosophy, Faculty of the Social Sciences, Freie Universität Berlin Education 03/2005 Dr. phil., Freie Universität Berlin (grade: Summa cum laude – best possible grade) 12/2003 M.A. (philosophy), Freie Universität Berlin (grade: 1,0 – best possible grade between 1,0 and 6,0) 12/1998 M.A.
    [Show full text]