Veganism of Harm to Animals

Total Page:16

File Type:pdf, Size:1020Kb

Veganism of Harm to Animals V Veganism of harm to animals. Other famous vegan advo- cates, before the term was coined by Watson, were Alejandra Mancilla the British doctor William Lambe (1765–1848), Centre for the Study of Mind in Nature (CSMN), who adopted a vegan diet based on health and Faculty of Humanities, The University of Oslo, ethical considerations, and the British poet Percy Oslo, Norway Bysshe Shelley (1792–1822), who publicly objected to the consumption of dairy and eggs. In a recent poll, it was estimated that there are Introduction at least 542,000 vegans in Britain, a steep increase from the 150,000 estimated in 2006 (Vegan Soci- Narrowly understood, veganism is the practice of ety 2016a). In the USA, a recent study showed excluding all animal products from one’s diet, that 3.3% of the population declared to be vege- with the exception of human milk. More broadly, tarian, half of which claim to be vegan – that is, veganism is not only a food ethics, but it encom- around five million people (The Vegetarian passes all other areas of life. As defined by the Resource Group 2016). Vegan Society when it became an established There are two main moral justifications for charity in the UK in 1979, veganism is best under- veganism, both of which rely on a common stood as “a philosophy and way of living which assumption: that sentience, i.e., the capacity to seeks to exclude – as far as is possible and feel pleasure and pain, is the necessary and suffi- practicable – all forms of exploitation of, and cient trait to be morally considerable. (Although it cruelty to, animals for food, clothing or any is a disputed matter whether insects possess this other purpose; and by extension, promotes the trait or not, vegans tend to avoid the consumption development and use of animal-free alternatives of products such as honey or the use of products for the benefit of humans, animals and the envi- like silk, and generally oppose the idea of eating ronment” (Vegan Society 2016b). insects. Cf. McWilliams 2014.) In what follows, The Vegan Society was founded in 1944 in I present these two arguments and a third one Leicester by Donald Watson (1910–2005), his which, although less popular, captures some core wife, Dorothy, and five other friends. But, like intuitions among vegans. I then present a chal- vegetarian principles, vegan principles have been lenge faced by veganism and two arguments that around for much longer – for example, among reject it as discriminatory, and briefly conclude. adherents of Jainism who avoid doing any sort # Springer Science+Business Media B.V. 2016 P.B. Thompson, D.M. Kaplan (eds.), Encyclopedia of Food and Agricultural Ethics, DOI 10.1007/978-94-007-6167-4_578-1 2 Veganism Arguments for Veganism male chicks and free-range laying hens who are no longer productive are routinely killed, and painful The Argument Against Unnecessary Suffering debeaking remains a standard procedure. It is Vegans and vegetarians coincide that the human hypocritical at worst, because it seeks to legiti- interest in nourishment and gustatory pleasure mize certain forms of animal rearing while derived from consuming nonhuman flesh is condemning others, occluding the cruelty inherent largely outweighed by the interests of nonhumans to these practices. in not being subject to the conditions of factory Depending on how they interpret P2’, vegans farms. Moreover, vegans accept the most influen- can be divided into two groups. On the one hand, tial argument for vegetarianism, known as the principled vegans believe that it is simply not the welfarist argument. This could be summarized case that the rearing of nonhuman animals for thus: food can be done in a way that causes no suffer- ing. It is therefore always impermissible to con- P1. It is morally wrong to cause unnecessary sume all animal products. On the other hand, suffering to nonhuman animals. contingent vegans believe that under current con- P2. The production process of meat and of many ditions it is morally wrong to consume all other nonhuman animal products causes nonhuman animal products, but this is not inevi- unnecessary suffering to nonhuman animals. table and could change in the future – for instance, C: It is morally wrong to participate (as a pro- if our patterns of consumption and modes of pro- ducer, distributor, consumer, and so on and so duction changed radically. forth) in the production process of meat and of Among both groups, moreover, there is a sub- many other nonhuman animal products. set who aspires not merely to change human diets into vegan diets, but to turn the whole natural The main complaint of vegans against vegetar- world into a vegan world where suffering is inso- ians, however, is that the second, factual premise far as possible eradicated. Along these lines, Jeff does not go far enough and should be replaced by McMahan asks whether we should gradually get the following one: rid of carnivorous species in their entirety, given that they cause so much pain to others. P2’. The production process of all animal prod- McMahan’s point is that, “even if we are not ucts causes unnecessary suffering to required to prevent suffering among animals in nonhuman animals. the wild for which we are not responsible, we do have a moral reason to prevent it”–so long as our This leads to the following conclusion: acting on that reason does not bring about worse effects than those we could prevent, like massive C’: It is morally wrong to participate (as a pro- ecosystemic imbalances and loss of biodiversity ducer, distributor, consumer, and so on and so (McMahan 2010, his emphases). This position fi forth) in the production process of all has been identi ed by some as a reductio against nonhuman animal products. the ideals of veganism. For vegans, endorsing the production process The Argument Against Exploitation of some animal products (paradigmatically, free- This argument, also known as the abolitionist range dairy and eggs) while banning others is argument, runs as follows: misinformed at best and hypocritical at worst. It is misinformed at best, because it ignores the fact P1: It is morally wrong to treat sentient beings as that even the most progressive animal-rearing property. practices inflict unnecessary suffering on the ani- P2: Nonhuman animals are sentient beings. mals involved. For example, in free-range farms, Veganism 3 P3: The production process of all nonhuman ani- between veganism and exploitation. Fourth, the mal products requires treating them as only trait that matters to be morally considerable is property. sentience. Fifth, all forms of human discrimina- C: It is morally wrong to participate in any way tion, including speciesism, ought to be rejected. (as a producer, distributor, consumer, and so on Sixth, nonviolence is the core principle of aboli- and so forth) in the production process of all tionism (Francione and Charlton 2015). nonhuman animal products. Some radical abolitionists claim that at the core of their position is the idea that human and Contra welfarists, who seek to improve the nonhuman animals are moral equals and have a living conditions of farmed animals (for example, right not to be treated as resources of others. This by advocating for larger cages for factory farm is why killing animals for food is always wrong. hens, by demanding that more humane slaughter In order for this idea to gain traction, two major methods be employed, etc.), abolitionists seek a assumptions over which most human cultures total ban on nonhuman animal production which, have been constructed over centuries need to be for them, is synonymous with exploitation. As debunked: first, that human interests are more their name reveals, abolitionists regard their important than nonhuman interests and that quest as analogous to the quest of those who human lives are worth more than nonhuman rejected human slavery: just as the latter did not lives. Let me present two of the most well- demand a better treatment for slaves, but the end known arguments used to support these claims of the institution as such, contemporary abolition- and the abolitionist’s reply (Bernstein 2015). ists do not wish to better regulate the meat and When it comes to interests, it has been typically animal production industry, but fight to put a argued that the interests of individuals who are definitive end to it. claimed to possess rationality (i.e., humans) ought Gary Francione and Anna Chorlton summarize to count more than those of individuals who are abolitionism in six principles. First, there is no claimed to lack such capacity (i.e., most morally relevant trait that distinguishes humans nonhumans). It is not the case, however, that from nonhumans that justifies treating the latter as humans consistently act on this prescription. For property and, therefore, as having mere economic one thing, we do not grant a higher moral status to use for us. Just as treating humans as property is humans with a higher degree of rationality; for inconsistent with recognizing all humans as mem- another, we do grant moral status to humans who bers of the moral community, treating nonhuman completely lack this capacity. This shows that animals as property goes against their recognition speciesism (the term popularized by Peter Singer as members of the moral community. All kinds of to refer to our unjustifiable bias toward members animal use, even humane ones, are thus of our own species) determines our moral behav- unjustified. Second, if we recognize the right not ior. When it comes to the value of human lives to be treated as property, we must not seek to vis-à-vis the lives of nonhumans, a stock argu- regulate, but plainly to abolish all institutionalized ment in defense of giving more weight to the animal exploitation.
Recommended publications
  • It's a (Two-)Culture Thing: the Laterial Shift to Liberation
    Animal Issues, Vol 4, No. 1, 2000 It's a (Two-)Culture Thing: The Lateral Shift to Liberation Barry Kew rom an acute and, some will argue, a harsh, a harsh, fantastic or even tactically naive F naive perspective, this article examines examines animal liberation, vegetarianism vegetarianism and veganism in relation to a bloodless culture ideal. It suggests that the movement's repeated anomalies, denial of heritage, privileging of vegetarianism, and other concessions to bloody culture, restrict rather than liberate the full subversionary and revelatory potential of liberationist discourse, and with representation and strategy implications. ‘Only the profoundest cultural needs … initially caused adult man [sic] to continue to drink cow milk through life’.1 In The Social Construction of Nature, Klaus Eder develops a useful concept of two cultures - the bloody and the bloodless. He understands the ambivalence of modernity and the relationship to nature as resulting from the perpetuation of a precarious equilibrium between the ‘bloodless’ tradition from within Judaism and the ‘bloody’ tradition of ancient Greece. In Genesis, killing entered the world after the fall from grace and initiated a complex and hierarchically-patterned system of food taboos regulating distance between nature and culture. But, for Eder, it is in Israel that the reverse process also begins, in the taboo on killing. This ‘civilizing’ process replaces the prevalent ancient world practice of 1 Calvin. W. Schwabe, ‘Animals in the Ancient World’ in Aubrey Manning and James Serpell, (eds), Animals and Human Society: Changing Perspectives (Routledge, London, 1994), p.54. 1 Animal Issues, Vol 4, No. 1, 2000 human sacrifice by animal sacrifice, this by sacrifices of the field, and these by money paid to the sacrificial priests.2 Modern society retains only a very broken connection to the Jewish tradition of the bloodless sacrifice.
    [Show full text]
  • Derogatory Discourses of Veganism and the Reproduction of Speciesism in UK 1 National Newspapers Bjos 1348 134..152
    The British Journal of Sociology 2011 Volume 62 Issue 1 Vegaphobia: derogatory discourses of veganism and the reproduction of speciesism in UK 1 national newspapers bjos_1348 134..152 Matthew Cole and Karen Morgan Abstract This paper critically examines discourses of veganism in UK national newspapers in 2007. In setting parameters for what can and cannot easily be discussed, domi- nant discourses also help frame understanding. Discourses relating to veganism are therefore presented as contravening commonsense, because they fall outside readily understood meat-eating discourses. Newspapers tend to discredit veganism through ridicule, or as being difficult or impossible to maintain in practice. Vegans are variously stereotyped as ascetics, faddists, sentimentalists, or in some cases, hostile extremists. The overall effect is of a derogatory portrayal of vegans and veganism that we interpret as ‘vegaphobia’. We interpret derogatory discourses of veganism in UK national newspapers as evidence of the cultural reproduction of speciesism, through which veganism is dissociated from its connection with debates concerning nonhuman animals’ rights or liberation. This is problematic in three, interrelated, respects. First, it empirically misrepresents the experience of veganism, and thereby marginalizes vegans. Second, it perpetuates a moral injury to omnivorous readers who are not presented with the opportunity to understand veganism and the challenge to speciesism that it contains. Third, and most seri- ously, it obscures and thereby reproduces
    [Show full text]
  • Liberation Survives Early Criticism and Is Pivotal to Public Health
    Deckers J. Why "Animal (De)liberation" survives early criticism and is pivotal to public health. Journal of Evaluation in Clinical Practice 2017, 23(5), 1105-1112. Copyright: © 2017 The Authors. Journal of Evaluation in Clinical Practice published by John Wiley & Sons Ltd. This is an open access article under the terms of the Creative Commons Attribution License, which permits use, distribution and reproduction in any medium, provided the original work is properly cited. DOI link to article: https://doi.org/10.1111/jep.12807 Date deposited: 02/10/2017 This work is licensed under a Creative Commons Attribution 4.0 International License Newcastle University ePrints - eprint.ncl.ac.uk Received: 3 April 2017 Revised: 23 June 2017 Accepted: 27 June 2017 DOI: 10.1111/jep.12807 ORIGINAL ARTICLE Why “Animal (De)liberation” survives early criticism and is pivotal to public health Jan Deckers PhD1 1 Senior Lecturer in Health Care Ethics, School of Medical Education, Newcastle University, Summary Newcastle upon Tyne, UK In 2016, the book Animal (De)liberation: Should the Consumption of Animal Products Be Banned? was published. This article aims to engage with the critique that this book has received and to Correspondence clarify and reinforce its importance for human health. It is argued that the ideas developed in the Jan Deckers, Newcastle University School of book withstand critical scrutiny. As qualified moral veganism avoids the pitfalls of other moral Medical Education, Ridley 1 Building positions on human diets, public health policies must be altered accordingly, subject to adequate Newcastle upon Tyne, NE1 7RU, UK. Email: [email protected] political support for its associated vegan project.
    [Show full text]
  • Animals and Ethics Fall, 2017, P
    Philosophy 174a Ethics and Animals Fall 2017 Instructor: Teaching Fellow: Chris Korsgaard Ahson Azmat 205 Emerson Hall [email protected] [email protected] Office Hours: Mondays 1:30-3:30 Description: Do human beings have moral obligations to the other animals? If so, what are they, and why? Should or could non-human animals have legal rights? Should we treat wild and domestic animals differently? Do human beings have the right to eat the other animals, raise them for that purpose on factory farms, use them in experiments, display them in zoos and circuses, make them race or fight for our entertainment, make them work for us, and keep them as pets? We will examine the work of utilitarian, Kantian, and Aristotelian philosophers, and others who have tried to answer these questions. This course, when taken for a letter grade, meets the General Education requirement for Ethical Reasoning. Sources and How to Get Them: Many of the sources from we will be reading from onto the course web site, but you will need to have copies of Singer’s Animal Liberation, Regan’s The Case for Animal Rights, Mill’s Utilitarianism and Coetzee’s The Lives of Animals. I have ordered all the main books from which we will be reading (except my own book, which is not yet published) at the Coop. The main books we will be using are: Animal Liberation, by Peter Singer. Updated edition, 2009, by Harper Collins Publishers. The Case for Animal Rights, by Tom Regan. University of California Press, 2004. Fellow Creatures: Our Obligations to the Other Animals, by Christine M.
    [Show full text]
  • {PDF} Diet for a Small Planet Ebook, Epub
    DIET FOR A SMALL PLANET PDF, EPUB, EBOOK F. Moore Lappe | 482 pages | 01 Feb 1992 | Random House USA Inc | 9780345321206 | English | New York, United States Diet for a Small Planet PDF Book Our farm economy is fueled by a blind production imperative. Then in late , in my basement library hideaway, I discovered a few facts about the U. In the "capitalist" Philippines, for example, there are very few signs of democratic participation. Jung called it enantiodromia - a shadow racing towards its opposite when pressures are heightened. Guide to Vegan Protein. Well researched but would be out of date in this day and age. Producing a one-pound steak uses up 2, gallons of water. She looks at the economics of the food supply. This text can be changed. Show More. Get A Copy. And although not many people know it, much of the food we're buying from Third World nations is contaminated with dangerous pesticides like DDT. Power, you know, is not a dirty word! Since then it has sold close to two million copies in a half dozen languages. Categories : non-fiction books Vegetarian cookbooks Vegetarian-related mass media Ballantine Books books Dieting books Vegetarianism in the United States. But being a woman has also been a great advantage, because it allowed me to keep from being locked into society's expectations and institutions and enabled me to stand outside, ask the unorthodox questions, and uncover some of the central myths of the hunger issue. Just look back about 25 years ago, to the first introduction of hybrid seeds and modern machinery into Third World agriculture.
    [Show full text]
  • Disaggregating the Scare from the Greens
    DISAGGREGATING THE SCARE FROM THE GREENS Lee Hall*† INTRODUCTION When the Vermont Law Review graciously asked me to contribute to this Symposium focusing on the tension between national security and fundamental values, specifically for a segment on ecological and animal- related activism as “the threat of unpopular ideas,” it seemed apt to ask a basic question about the title: Why should we come to think of reverence for life or serious concern for the Earth that sustains us as “unpopular ideas”? What we really appear to be saying is that the methods used, condoned, or promoted by certain people are unpopular. So before we proceed further, intimidation should be disaggregated from respect for the environment and its living inhabitants. Two recent and high-profile law-enforcement initiatives have viewed environmental and animal-advocacy groups as threats in the United States. These initiatives are the Stop Huntingdon Animal Cruelty (SHAC) prosecution and Operation Backfire. The former prosecution targeted SHAC—a campaign to close one animal-testing firm—and referred also to the underground Animal Liberation Front (ALF).1 The latter prosecution *. Legal director of Friends of Animals, an international animal-rights organization founded in 1957. †. Lee Hall, who can be reached at [email protected], thanks Lydia Fiedler, the Vermont Law School, and Friends of Animals for making it possible to participate in the 2008 Symposium and prepare this Article for publication. 1. See Indictment at 14–16, United States v. Stop Huntingdon Animal Cruelty USA, Inc., No. 3:04-cr-00373-AET-2 (D.N.J. May 27, 2004), available at http://www.usdoj.gov/usao/nj/press/files/ pdffiles/shacind.pdf (last visited Apr.
    [Show full text]
  • 219 No Animal Food
    219 No Animal Food: The Road to Veganism in Britain, 1909-1944 Leah Leneman1 UNIVERSITY OF EDINBURGH There were individuals in the vegetarian movement in Britain who believed that to refrain from eating flesh, fowl, and fish while continuing to partake of dairy products and eggs was not going far enough. Between 1909 and 1912, The Vegetarian Society's journal published a vigorous correspond- ence on this subject. In 1910, a publisher brought out a cookery book entitled, No Animal Food. After World War I, the debate continued within the Vegetarian Society about the acceptability of animal by-products. It centered on issues of cruelty and health as well as on consistency versus expediency. The Society saw its function as one of persuading as many people as possible to give up slaughterhouse products and also refused journal space to those who abjured dairy products. The year 1944 saw the word "vergan" coined and the breakaway Vegan Society formed. The idea that eating animal flesh is unhealthy and morally wrong has been around for millennia, in many different parts of the world and in many cultures (Williams, 1896). In Britain, a national Vegetarian Society was formed in 1847 to promulgate the ideology of non-meat eating (Twigg, 1982). Vegetarianism, as defined by the Society-then and now-and by British vegetarians in general, permitted the consumption of dairy products and eggs on the grounds that it was not necessary to kill the animal to obtain them. In 1944, a group of Vegetarian Society members coined a new word-vegan-for those who refused to partake of any animal product and broke away to form a separate organization, The Vegan Society.
    [Show full text]
  • Charlotte Bronte and the 19Th-Century Health Reformers Author
    View metadata, citation and similar papers at core.ac.uk brought to you by CORE Title: The Good, the healthy and the natural : Charlotte Bronte and the 19th-century health reformers Author: Nina Augustynowicz Citation style: Augustynowicz Nina. (2014). The Good, the healthy and the natural : Charlotte Bronte and the 19th-century health reformers. W: J. Mydla, A.Wilczek, T. Gnat (red.), "Nature(s): environments we live by in literary and cultural discourses" (S. 137- 147). Katowice : Wydawnictwo Uniwersytetu Śląskiego. Nina Augustynowicz University of Silesia The Good, the Healthy, and the Natural: Charlotte Brontë and the 19th-Century Health Reformers The body in Charlotte Brontë’s novels is an arena where ideologies meet and engage in conflict. Various, often contradictory forces operating within the spheres of religion, gender, and class make the body a site of struggle. Thanks to Michel Foucault, the body has been understood as a cultural phenomenon, a corporeality in which the borders between psyche and soma, as well as between the inside and the outside are porous, allowing for these realms to overlap. Consequently, any external disturbances may become internalised, for example as illnesses. In the context of such materializations, the issue of health, both on the personal and national level, must gain primary importance. The moment the physical well- being of individuals is located at the intersection of numerous modes of thinking about the aforementioned matters, it starts to signify outside the strictly physiological domain. In other words, bodily symptoms indicate not only diseases of the flesh, but also ideas about morality, beauty, and the nature-culture opposition.
    [Show full text]
  • Spotlight and Hot Topic Sessions Poster Sessions Continuing
    Sessions and Events Day Thursday, January 21 (Sessions 1001 - 1025, 1467) Friday, January 22 (Sessions 1026 - 1049) Monday, January 25 (Sessions 1050 - 1061, 1063 - 1141) Wednesday, January 27 (Sessions 1062, 1171, 1255 - 1339) Tuesday, January 26 (Sessions 1142 - 1170, 1172 - 1254) Thursday, January 28 (Sessions 1340 - 1419) Friday, January 29 (Sessions 1420 - 1466) Spotlight and Hot Topic Sessions More than 50 sessions and workshops will focus on the spotlight theme for the 2019 Annual Meeting: Transportation for a Smart, Sustainable, and Equitable Future . In addition, more than 170 sessions and workshops will look at one or more of the following hot topics identified by the TRB Executive Committee: Transformational Technologies: New technologies that have the potential to transform transportation as we know it. Resilience and Sustainability: How transportation agencies operate and manage systems that are economically stable, equitable to all users, and operated safely and securely during daily and disruptive events. Transportation and Public Health: Effects that transportation can have on public health by reducing transportation related casualties, providing easy access to healthcare services, mitigating environmental impacts, and reducing the transmission of communicable diseases. To find sessions on these topics, look for the Spotlight icon and the Hot Topic icon i n the “Sessions, Events, and Meetings” section beginning on page 37. Poster Sessions Convention Center, Lower Level, Hall A (new location this year) Poster Sessions provide an opportunity to interact with authors in a more personal setting than the conventional lecture. The papers presented in these sessions meet the same review criteria as lectern session presentations. For a complete list of poster sessions, see the “Sessions, Events, and Meetings” section, beginning on page 37.
    [Show full text]
  • The Sexual Politics of Meat by Carol J. Adams
    THE SEXUAL POLITICS OF MEAT A FEMINISTVEGETARIAN CRITICAL THEORY Praise for The Sexual Politics of Meat and Carol J. Adams “A clearheaded scholar joins the ideas of two movements—vegetari- anism and feminism—and turns them into a single coherent and moral theory. Her argument is rational and persuasive. New ground—whole acres of it—is broken by Adams.” —Colman McCarthy, Washington Post Book World “Th e Sexual Politics of Meat examines the historical, gender, race, and class implications of meat culture, and makes the links between the prac tice of butchering/eating animals and the maintenance of male domi nance. Read this powerful new book and you may well become a vegetarian.” —Ms. “Adams’s work will almost surely become a ‘bible’ for feminist and pro gressive animal rights activists. Depiction of animal exploita- tion as one manifestation of a brutal patriarchal culture has been explored in two [of her] books, Th e Sexual Politics of Meat and Neither Man nor Beast: Feminism and the Defense of Animals. Adams argues that factory farming is part of a whole culture of oppression and insti- tutionalized violence. Th e treatment of animals as objects is parallel to and associated with patriarchal society’s objectifi cation of women, blacks, and other minorities in order to routinely exploit them. Adams excels in constructing unexpected juxtapositions by using the language of one kind of relationship to illuminate another. Employing poetic rather than rhetorical techniques, Adams makes powerful connec- tions that encourage readers to draw their own conclusions.” —Choice “A dynamic contribution toward creating a feminist/animal rights theory.” —Animals’ Agenda “A cohesive, passionate case linking meat-eating to the oppression of animals and women .
    [Show full text]
  • Catharine J. Cadbury Papers HC.Coll.1192
    William W. Cadbury and Catharine J. Cadbury papers HC.Coll.1192 This finding aid was produced using the Archivists' Toolkit February 23, 2012 Describing Archives: A Content Standard Haverford College Quaker & Special Collections 2011 370 Lancaster Ave Haverford, PA, 19041 610-896-1161 [email protected] William W. Cadbury and Catharine J. Cadbury papers HC.Coll.1192 Table of Contents Summary Information ................................................................................................................................. 3 William Warder Cadbury (1877-1959)......................................................................................................... 6 Catharine J. Cadbury (1884-1970)................................................................................................................ 6 Administrative Information .........................................................................................................................7 Related Materials ........................................................................................................................................ 7 Controlled Access Headings..........................................................................................................................7 Related Finding Aids.....................................................................................................................................9 Collection Inventory...................................................................................................................................
    [Show full text]
  • A Cultural Study of Gendered Onscreen
    VEG-GENDERED: A CULTURAL STUDY OF GENDERED ONSCREEN REPRESENTATIONS OF FOOD AND THEIR IMPLICATIONS FOR VEGANISM by Paulina Aguilera A Thesis Submitted to the Faculty of The Dorothy F. Schmidt College of Arts & Letters In Partial Fulfillment of the Requirements for the Degree of Master of Arts Florida Atlantic University Boca Raton, FL August 2014 Copyright by Paulina Aguilera, 2014 11 VEG-GENDERED: A STUDY OF GENDERED ONSCREEN REPRESENTATIONS OF FOOD AND THEIR IMPLICATIONS FOR VEGANISM by Paulina Aguilera This thesis was prepared under the direction of the candidate's thesis advisor, Dr. Christine Scodari, School of Communication and Multimedia Studies, and has been approved by the members of her supervisory committee. It was submitted to the faculty of The Dorothy F. Schmidt College of Arts and Letters and was accepted in partial fulfillment of the requirements for the degree of Master of Arts. SUPERVISORY COMMITTEE: ~t~;,~ obe, Ph.D. David C. Williams, Ph.D. Interim Director, School of Communication and Multimedia Studies Heather Coltman, DMA Dean, ;~~of;candLetters 0'7/0 /:fdf4 8 ~T.Fioyd, Ed.D~ -D-at_e _ _,__ ______ Interim Dean, Graduate College 111 ACKNOWLEDGEMENTS The author wishes to acknowledge Dr. Christi ne Scodari for her incredible guidance and immeasurable patience during the research and writing of this thesis. Acknowledgements are also in order to the participating committee members, Dr. Chris Robe and Dr. Fred Fejes, who provided further feedback and direction. Lastly, a special acknowledgement to Chandra Holst-Maldonado is necessary for her being an amazing source of moral support throughout the thesis process.
    [Show full text]