Vagueness and Learning: a Type-Theoretic Approach

Total Page:16

File Type:pdf, Size:1020Kb

Vagueness and Learning: a Type-Theoretic Approach Vagueness and Learning: A Type-Theoretic Approach Raquel Fernandez´ Staffan Larsson Institute for Logic, Language Department of Philosophy, Linguistics and Computation and Theory of Science University of Amsterdam University of Gothenburg [email protected] [email protected] Abstract expressions (Kelleher et al., 2005; Reiter et al., 2005; Portet et al., 2009) and, perhaps even more We present a formal account of the mean- strongly, on the field of robotics, where ground- ing of vague scalar adjectives such as ‘tall’ ing language on perceptual information is critical formulated in Type Theory with Records. to allow artificial agents to autonomously acquire Our approach makes precise how percep- and verify beliefs about the world (Siskind, 2001; tual information can be integrated into Steels, 2003; Roy, 2005; Skocaj et al., 2010). the meaning representation of these pred- Most of these approaches, however, do not build icates; how an agent evaluates whether an on theories of formal semantics for natural lan- entity counts as tall; and how the proposed guage. Here we choose to formalise our account semantics can be learned and dynamically in a theoretical framework known as Type Theory updated through experience. with Records (TTR), which has been shown to be suitable for formalising classic semantic aspects 1 Introduction such as intensionality, quantification, and nega- tion (Cooper, 2005a; Cooper, 2010; Cooper and Traditional semantic theories such as those de- Ginzburg, 2011) as well as less standard phenom- scribed in Partee (1989) and Blackburn and ena such as linguistic interaction (Ginzburg, 2012; Bos (2005) offer precise accounts of the truth- Purver et al., 2014), perception and action (Dob- conditional content of linguistic expressions, but nik et al., 2013), and semantic coordination and do not deal with the connection between meaning, learning (Larsson, 2009). In this paper we use perception and learning. One can argue, however, TTR to put forward an account of the semantics of that part of getting to know the meaning of lin- vague scalar predicates like ‘tall’ that makes pre- guistic expressions consists in learning to identify cise how perceptual information can be integrated the individuals or the situations that the expres- into their meaning representation; how an agent sions can describe. For many concrete words and evaluates whether an entity counts as tall; and how phrases, this identification relies on perceptual in- the proposed semantics for these expressions can formation. In this paper, we focus on characteris- be learned and dynamically updated through lan- ing the meaning of vague scalar adjectives such guage use. as ‘tall’, ‘dark’, or ‘heavy’. We propose a for- We start by giving a brief overview of TTR and mal account that brings together notions from tra- explaining how it can be used for classifying en- ditional formal semanticswith perceptual informa- tities as being of particular types integrating per- tion, which allows us to specify how a logic-based ceptual information. After that, in Section 3, we interpretation function is determined and modified describe the main properties of vague scalar pred- dynamically by experience. icates. Section 4 presents a probabilistic TTR for- The need to integrate language and percep- malisation of the meaning of ‘tall’, which captures tion has been emphasised by researchers work- its context-dependence and its vague character. In ing on the generation and resolution of referring Section 5, we then offer an account of how that This work is licensed under a Creative Commons Attribution meaning representation is acquired and updated 4.0 International Licence. Page numbers and proceedings footer are added by the organisers. Licence details: http: with experience. Finally, in Section 6 we discuss //creativecommons.org/licenses/by/4.0/ related work, before concluding in Section 7. 151 Proceedings of the Third Joint Conference on Lexical and Computational Semantics (*SEM 2014), pages 151–159, Dublin, Ireland, August 23-24 2014. 2 Meaning as Classification in TTR way of constructing ptypes where the arguments of a predicate are entities that have been intro- In this section we give a brief and hence inevitably duced before in the record type. A sample record partial introduction to Type Theory with Records. and record type are shown in (2). For more comprehensive introductions, we refer the reader to Cooper (2005b) and Cooper (2012). x = a x : Ind (2) c = prf(man(a)) : c : man(x) man man 2.1 Type Theory with Records: Main Notions crun = prf(run(a)) crun : run(x) As in any type theory, the most central notion in In (2), a is an entity of type individual and prf(P ) TTR is that of a judgement that an object a is is used as a placeholder for proofs of ptypes P . of type T , written as a : T . In TTR judgements In the record type above, the ptypes man(x) and are seen as fundamentally related to perception, in run(x) constructed from predicates are dependent the sense that perceiving inherently involves cate- on x (introduced earlier in the record type). gorising what we perceive. Some common basic types in TTR are Ind (the type of individuals) and 2.2 Perceptual Meaning + R (the type of positive real numbers). All basic Larsson (2013) proposes a system formalised in types are members of a special type Type. Given TTR where some perceptual aspects of meaning types T1 and T2, we can create the function type are represented using classifiers. For example, the T T 2 whose domain are objects of type T 1 → 1 meaning of ‘right’ (as in ‘to the right of ’) involves and whose range are objects of type T2. Types a two-input perceptron classifier κright(w, t, r), can also be constructed from predicates and ob- specified by a weight vector w and a threshold jects P (a1, . , an). Such types are called ptypes t, which takes as input a context r including an and correspond roughly to propositions in first or- object x and a position-sensor reading srpos. The der logic. In TTR, propositions are types of proofs, sensor reading consists of a vector containing two where proofs can be a variety of things, from situ- real numbers representing the space coordinates of ations to sensor readings (more on this below). x. The classifier classifies x as either being to the Next, we introduce records and record types. right on a plane or not.1 These are structured objects made up of pairs l, v h i x : Ind of labels and values that are displayed in a matrix: (3) if r : , then sr : RealVector (1) a. A record type: pos right(r.x) if (r.srpos w) > t `1 : T1 κ (w, t, r) = · right right(r.x) otherwise `2 : T2(`1) ¬ ... As output we get a record type containing either a `n : Tn(`1, `2, . , `n 1) ptype right(x) or its negation, right(x). Larsson − ¬ (2013) proposes that readings from sensors may `1 = a1 count as proofs of such ptypes. A classifier can `2 = a2 b. A record: r = ... be used for judging x as being of a particular type `n = an on the grounds of perceptual information. A per- ... ceptual proof for right(x) would thus include the Record r in (1b) is of the record type in (1a) if output from the position sensor that is directed to- and only if a1 : T1, a2 : T2(a1), . , and an : wards x. Here, this output would be the space co- Tn(a1, a2, . , an 1). Note that the record may − ordinates of x. contain more fields but would still be of type (1a) if the typing condition holds. Records and record 3 Vague Scalar Predicates types can be nested so that the value of a label is Scalar predicates such as ‘tall’, ‘long’ and ‘ex- itself a record (or record type). We can use paths pensive’, also called “relative gradable adjectives” within a record or record type to refer to specific (Kennedy, 2007), are interpreted with respect to a bits of structure: for instance, we can use r.`2 to refer to a2 in (1b). 1We are here assuming that we have a definition of dot product for TTR vectors a:RealVectorn and b:RealVectorn As can be seen in (1a), the labels `1, . `n in a n such that a b = Σi=1aibi = a1b1 + a2b2 + ... + anbn. We record type can be used elsewhere to refer to the also implicitly· assume that the weight vector and the sensor values associated with them. This is a common reading vector have the same dimensionality. 152 scale, i.e., a dimension such as height, length, or 2002; Kennedy and McNally, 2005; Kennedy, cost along which entities for which the relevant di- 2007; Solt, 2011; Lassiter, 2011). mension is applicable can be ordered. This makes We build on degree approaches but adopt a scalar predicates compatible with degree morphol- perception-based perspective and take a step fur- ogy, like comparative and superlative morphemes ther to formalise how the meaning of these pred- (‘taller than’, ‘the longest’) and intensifier mor- icates can be learned and constantly updated phemes such as ‘very’ or ‘quite’. In this pa- through language use. per, our focus is on the so-called positive form of these adjectives (e.g. ‘tall’ as opposed to ‘taller’ 4 A Perceptual Semantics for ‘Tall’ or ‘tallest’). To exemplify our approach, we will use the scalar A property that distinguishes the positive form predicate ‘tall’ throughout. from the comparative and the superlative forms is its context-dependance. To take a common exam- 4.1 Context-sensitivity ple: If Sue’s height is 180cm, she may be appro- We first focus on capturing the context- priately described as a tall woman, but probably dependence of relative scalar predicates.
Recommended publications
  • How to Do Things with Types⇤
    Joint Proceedings NLCS’14 & NLSR 2014, July 17-18, 2014, Vienna, Austria How to do things with types⇤ Robin Cooper University of Gothenburg Abstract We present a theory of type acts based on type theory relating to a general theory of action which can be used as a foundation for a theory of linguistic acts. Contents 1 Introduction 1 2 Type acts 2 3 Coordinating interaction in games 5 4 Conclusion 9 1 Introduction The title of this paper picks up, of course, on the seminal book How to do things with words by J.L. Austin [Aus62], which laid the foundation for speech act theory. In recent work on dialogue such as [Gin12] it is proposed that it is important for linguistic analysis to take seriously a notion of linguistic acts. To formulate this, Ginzburg uses TTR (“Type Theory with Records”) as developed in [Coo12]. The idea was also very much a part of the original work on situation semantics [BP83] which has also served as an inspiration for the work on TTR. TTR was also originally inspired by work on constructive type theory [ML84, NPS90] in which there is a notion of judgement that an object a is of a type T , a : T .1 We shall think of judgements as a kind of type act and propose that there are other type acts in addition to judgements. We shall also follow [Ran94] in including types of events (or more generally, situations) in a type theory suitable for building a theory of action and of linguistic meaning. ⇤The work for this paper was supported in part by VR project 2009-1569, SAICD.
    [Show full text]
  • Department of Philosophy, Linguistics and Theory of Science on 2018-01-25 to Be Valid from 2018-01-25
    DEPARTMENT OF PHILOSOPHY, LINGUISTICS AND THEORY OF SCIENCE Type Theory with Records: From Perception to Communication, 7,5 higher education credits Type Theory with Records: Från perception till kommunikation, 7,5 högskolepoäng Third Cycle/Forskarnivå Confirmation The course syllabus was confirmed by the Department of Philosophy, Linguistics and Theory of Science on 2018-01-25 to be valid from 2018-01-25. Entry requirements General and specific entry requirements for third-cycle education according to Admissions Regulations and the general syllabus for the subject area at hand. Learning outcomes After completion of the course the doctoral student is expected to be able to : Knowledge and understanding demonstrate enhanced knowledge and understanding of the subject areas of the course, discuss in detail key theories and issues in one or more of the subject areas of the course, Skills and abilities offer a detailed analysis of issues, lines of arguments or methods from the literature, select and define issues, lines of arguments or methods from the literature that are suitable for a short critical essay or a conference paper, Judgement and approach critically discuss, orally or in writing, questions, lines of arguments or methods that are used in the literature, critically assess the validity of the studied lines of argument. Course content The course introduces TTR, a Type Theory with Records, as a framework for natural language grammar and interaction. We are taking a dialogical view of semantics. The course covers the formal foundations of TTR as well as TTR accounts of perception, intensionality, information exchange, grammar (syntax and semantics), quantification, modality and other linguistic phenomena.
    [Show full text]
  • Witness-Loaded and Witness-Free Demonstratives
    Witness-loaded and Witness-free Demonstratives Andy Lücking Goethe University Frankfurt, Germany To Appear 2017 Prefinal draft, cite only full chapter Abstract According to current theories of demonstratives, both discourse referentially (en- dophoric) and real-world referentially (exophoric) uses of demonstrative noun phrases (DemNPs) obey the same mode of reference. Based on the clarification potential of DemNPs and on data on bridging and deferred reference it is argued that only ex- ophoric DemNPs allow for the identification of a demonstratum, while endophoric ones do not. Furthermore, the view that discourse reference does not involve a demonstration act is taken and, hence, contrary to standard assumption, the claim is made that both uses follow different modes of reference. In order to maintain a unified analysis of DemNPs, it is argued to spell out their semantics in terms of a grammar-dialog interface, where demonstratives and demonstration acts contribute to processing instructions for reference management. In this system, exophoric Dem- NPs are modeled as witness-loaded referential expressions, while endophoric Dem- NPs remain witness-free. A final claim is that the witness gives rise to manifold perceptual classifications, which in turn license indirect reference. The analysis is implemented in Type Theory with Records (which provides the notion of a witness) within Ginzburg’s dialog framework called KoS. The dynamics of demonstratives is captured by a set of rules that govern their processing in dialog. Keywords: demonstratives, demonstration, reference, deferred reference, wit- nesses, dialog 1 Introduction Demonstrative noun phrases (DemNPs) like this painting can be used in two ways: exophorically and endophorically (the latter can be further distinguished into anaphoric and cataphoric).
    [Show full text]
  • Theoretical Linguistics, Vol
    Edinburgh Research Explorer Action-based grammar Citation for published version: Kempson, R, Cann, R, Gregoromichelaki, E & Chatzikyriakidis, S 2017, 'Action-based grammar', Theoretical Linguistics, vol. 43, no. 1-2, pp. 141-167. https://doi.org/10.1515/tl-2017-0012 Digital Object Identifier (DOI): 10.1515/tl-2017-0012 Link: Link to publication record in Edinburgh Research Explorer Document Version: Publisher's PDF, also known as Version of record Published In: Theoretical Linguistics General rights Copyright for the publications made accessible via the Edinburgh Research Explorer is retained by the author(s) and / or other copyright owners and it is a condition of accessing these publications that users recognise and abide by the legal requirements associated with these rights. Take down policy The University of Edinburgh has made every reasonable effort to ensure that Edinburgh Research Explorer content complies with UK legislation. If you believe that the public display of this file breaches copyright please contact [email protected] providing details, and we will remove access to the work immediately and investigate your claim. Download date: 29. Sep. 2021 Theoretical Linguistics 2017; 43(1-2): 141–167 Ruth Kempson, Ronnie Cann, Eleni Gregoromichelaki and Stergios Chatzikyriakidis Action-Based Grammar DOI 10.1515/tl-2017-0012 1 Competence-performance and levels of description First of all we would like to thank the commentators for their efforts that resulted in thoughtful and significant comments about our account.1 We are delighted that the main thesis we presented – the inclusion of interactive language use within the remit of grammars – seems to have received an unexpected consensus from such diverse perspectives.
    [Show full text]
  • Modelling Language, Action, and Perception in Type Theory with Records
    Modelling Language, Action, and Perception in Type Theory with Records Simon Dobnik, Robin Cooper, and Staffan Larsson Department of Philosophy, Linguistics and Theory of Science University of Gothenburg, Box 200, 405 30 G¨oteborg, Sweden [email protected], {staffan.larsson,robin.cooper}@ling.gu.se http://www.flov.gu.se Abstract. Formal models of natural language semantics using TTR (Type Theory with Records) attempt to relate natural language to per- ception, modelled as classification of objects and events by types which are available as resources to an agent. We argue that this is better suited for representing the meaning of spatial descriptions in the context of agent modelling than traditional formal semantic models which do not relate spatial concepts to perceptual apparatus. Spatial descriptions in- clude perceptual, conceptual and discourse knowledge which we represent all in a single framework. Being a general framework for modelling both linguistic and non-linguistic cognition, TTR is more suitable for the mod- elling of situated conversational agents in robotics and virtual environ- ments where interoperability between language, action and perception is required. The perceptual systems gain access to abstract conceptual meaning representations of language while the latter can be justified in action and perception. Keywords: language, action, perception, formal semantics, spatial de- scriptions, learning and classification. 1 Introduction Classical model-theoretic semantics [1] does not deal with the connection be- tween linguistic meaning and perception or action. It does not provide a theory of non-linguistic perception and it is not obvious how to extend it to take account of this. Another feature of classical approaches to model theory is that they treat natural language as being essentially similar to formal languages in, among other things, assuming that there is a fixed interpretation function which mediates be- tween natural language and the world.
    [Show full text]
  • Reference and Perceptual Memory in Situated Dialog
    Referring to the recently seen: reference and perceptual memory in situated dialog John D. Kelleher Simon Dobnik ADAPT Research Centre CLASP and FLOV ICE Research Institute University of Gotenburg, Sweden Technological University Dublin [email protected] [email protected] Abstract From theoretical linguistic and cognitive perspectives, situated dialog systems are interesting as they provide ideal test-beds for investigating the interaction between language and perception. At the same time there are a growing number of practical applications, for example robotic systems and driver-less cars, where spoken interfaces, capable of situated dialog, promise many advantages. To date, however much of the work on situated dialog has focused resolving anaphoric or exophoric references. This paper, by con- trast, opens up the question of how perceptual memory and linguistic refer- ences interact, and the challenges that this poses to computational models of perceptually grounded dialog. 1 Introduction Situated language is spoken from a particular point of view within a shared per- ceptual context [6]. In an era where we are witnessing a proliferation of sensors that enable computer systems to perceive the world, effective computational mod- els of situated dialog have a growing number of practical applications, consider applications in human-robot interaction in personal assistants, driver-less car inter- faces that allow interaction with a passenger in language , and so on. From a more fundamental science perspective, computational models of situated dialog provide arXiv:1903.09866v1 [cs.HC] 23 Mar 2019 a test-bed for theories of cognition and language, in particular those dealing with the binding/fusion of language and perception in the interactive setting involving human conversational partners and ever-changing environment.
    [Show full text]
  • Mass/Count Variation: a Mereological, Two-Dimensional Semantics
    Baltic International Yearbook of Cognition, Logic and Communication Volume 11 Number: Cognitive, Semantic and Crosslinguistic Approaches Article 11 2016 Mass/Count Variation: A Mereological, Two-Dimensional Semantics Peter R. Sutton Heinrich Heine University Düsseldorf, Germany Hana Filip Heinrich Heine University Düsseldorf, Germany Follow this and additional works at: https://newprairiepress.org/biyclc Part of the Semantics and Pragmatics Commons This work is licensed under a Creative Commons Attribution-Noncommercial-No Derivative Works 4.0 License. Recommended Citation Sutton, Peter R. and Filip, Hana (2016) "Mass/Count Variation: A Mereological, Two-Dimensional Semantics," Baltic International Yearbook of Cognition, Logic and Communication: Vol. 11. https://doi.org/ 10.4148/1944-3676.1110 This Proceeding of the Symposium for Cognition, Logic and Communication is brought to you for free and open access by the Conferences at New Prairie Press. It has been accepted for inclusion in Baltic International Yearbook of Cognition, Logic and Communication by an authorized administrator of New Prairie Press. For more information, please contact [email protected]. Mass/Count Variation 2 The Baltic International Yearbook of The other index is a precisification index (inspired by Chierchia 2010). Cognition, Logic and Communication At some precisifications, the set of entities that count as ‘one’ can be excluded from a noun’s denotation leading to mass encoding. We com- December 2016 Volume 11: Number: Cognitive, Semantic and bine these indices into a two dimensional semantics that not only mod- Crosslinguistic Approaches els the semantics of a number of classes of nouns, but can also explain pages 1-45 DOI: http://dx.doi.org/10.4148/1944-3676.1110 and predict the puzzling phenomenon of mass/count variation.
    [Show full text]
  • Indexicals As Weak Descriptors
    Indexicals as Weak Descriptors Andy Lücking Goethe University Frankfurt Abstract Indexicals have a couple of uses that are in conflict with the traditional view that they directly refer to indices in the utterance situation. But how do they refer instead? It is argued that indexicals have both an indexical and a descriptive aspect – why they are called weak descriptors here. The indexical aspect anchors them in the actual situation of utterance, the weak descriptive aspect sin- gles out the referent. Descriptive uses of “today” are then attributed to calendric coercion which is triggered by qunatificational elements. This account provides a grammatically motivated formal link to descriptive uses. With regard to some uses of “I”, a tentative contiguity rule is proposed as the reference rule for the first person pronoun, which is oriented along recent hearer-oriented accounts in philosophy, but finally has to be criticized. 1 Descriptive Indexicals Indexicals have descriptive uses as exemplified in (1a) (taken from Nunberg, 2004, p. 265): (1) a. Today is always the biggest party day of the year. b. *November 1, 2000 is always the biggest party day of the year. According to Nunberg (2004), today in (1a) is interpreted as picking out a day type or day property instead of referring to a concrete day, since “[. ] the interpretations of these uses of indexicals are the very things that their linguistic meanings pick out of the context.” (p. 272). The full date in (1b), to the contrary, refers to a particular day and has no such type or property reading. The interpretations of both sentences in (1) diverge, even if both sentences are produced on November 1, 2000.
    [Show full text]
  • Semantic Theories of Questions∗
    Semantic theories of questions∗ Floris Roelofsen October 17, 2018 Summary This survey article discusses two basic issues that semantic theories of ques- tions face. The first is how to conceptualise and formally represent the semantic content of questions. This issue arises in particular because the standard truth-conditional notion of meaning, which has been fruitful in the analysis of declarative statements, is not applicable to questions. The second issue is how questions, when embedded in a declarative statement (e.g., in Bill wonders who called) contribute to the truth-conditional content of that state- ment. Several ways in which these issues have been addressed in the literature are discussed and compared. Keywords semantics of questions, alternative semantics, partition semantics, inquisitive semantics, interrogative complements, clause-embedding predicates. 1 Introduction Formal semantic theories traditionally construe the meaning of a sentence in terms of its truth-conditions: to know the meaning of a sentence is to know the conditions under which the sentence is true, and those under which it is false. This notion of meaning has been very fruitful in the analysis of declarative statements, but it does not straightforwardly apply to questions, which are not naturally thought of as being true or false in a given situation. Thus, the most basic issue that semantic theories of questions need to address is the following: • Issue 1: How should the semantic content of a question be conceptualised, and how should it be represented formally? Questions are not only of interest in their own right. They can also be part of declarative statements and as such contribute to the truth-conditional content of such statements.
    [Show full text]
  • Implementingperceptuals
    View metadata, citation and similar papers at core.ac.uk brought to you by CORE provided by Göteborgs universitets publikationer - e-publicering och e-arkiv DEPARTMENT OF PHILOSOPHY, LINGUISTICS AND THEORY OF SCIENCE IMPLEMENTING PERCEPTUAL SEMANTICS IN TYPE THEORY WITH RECORDS (TTR) Arild Matsson Master’s Thesis 30 credits Programme Master’s Programme in Language Technology Level Advanced level Semester and year Spring, 2018 Supervisors Simon Dobnik and Staffan Larsson Examiner Peter Ljunglöf Keywords type theory, image recognition, perceptual semantics, visual question answering, spatial relations, artificial intelligence Abstract Type Theory with Records (TTR) provides accounts of a wide range of semantic and linguistic phenomena in a single framework. This work proposes a TTR model of perception and language. Utilizing PyTTR, a Python implementation of TTR, the model is then implemented as an executable script. Over pure Python programming, TTR provides a transparent formal specification. The implementation is evaluated in a basic visual question answering (VQA) use case scenario. The results show that an implementation of a TTR model can account for multi-modal knowledge representation and work in a VQA setting. Acknowledgements Huge thanks to my supervisors and to professor Robin Cooper, all of whom have provided significant help through this process. Contents 1 Introduction ............................................ 1 1.1 Contribution of this thesis ................................. 1 2 Background ............................................ 2 2.1 Image recognition and object detection ........................... 2 2.2 Computational semantics .................................. 2 2.2.1 Type theory in linguistics .............................. 3 2.3 Perceptual semantics .................................... 3 2.4 Type Theory with Records (TTR) ............................. 4 2.4.1 Overview of TTR .................................. 4 2.5 Visual question answering (VQA) ............................
    [Show full text]
  • Types Theory and Lexical Semantics Robin Cooper, Christian Retoré
    Extended abstracts of the ESSLLI 2015 workshop TYTLES: Types Theory and Lexical Semantics Robin Cooper, Christian Retoré To cite this version: Robin Cooper, Christian Retoré. Extended abstracts of the ESSLLI 2015 workshop TYTLES: Types Theory and Lexical Semantics. Aug 2015, Barcelona, Spain. 2015. hal-01584832v2 HAL Id: hal-01584832 https://hal.archives-ouvertes.fr/hal-01584832v2 Submitted on 24 Sep 2017 HAL is a multi-disciplinary open access L’archive ouverte pluridisciplinaire HAL, est archive for the deposit and dissemination of sci- destinée au dépôt et à la diffusion de documents entific research documents, whether they are pub- scientifiques de niveau recherche, publiés ou non, lished or not. The documents may come from émanant des établissements d’enseignement et de teaching and research institutions in France or recherche français ou étrangers, des laboratoires abroad, or from public or private research centers. publics ou privés. Extended abstracts of the ESSLLI 2015 workshop TYTLES: Types Theory and Lexical Semantics Workshops organizers / programme committee co-chairs: Robin Cooper & Christian Retoré Barcelona, 3-7 August 2015 Those are the extended abstracts of the TYTLES (Barcelona, August 3-7 2015) workshop together with the slides that were projected during the introduction and the conclusion. Some authors may publish alternative versions later on elsewhere. Program committee: • Robin Cooper (University of Gothenburg, Co-Chair), • Christian Retoré (Université de Montpellier, & LIRMM Co-Chair) • Alexandra Arapinis (CNR,
    [Show full text]
  • Ellipsis in Head-Driven Phrase Structure Grammar
    Ellipsis in Head-Driven Phrase Structure Grammar Jonathan Ginzburg and Philip Miller∗ Universite´ Paris Diderot, Laboratoire de Linguistique Formelle (UMR 7110) and EA 3697 CLILLAC-ARP June 16, 2017 1 Introduction 1.1 General properties of ellipsis The characterizing feature of ellipsis is that elements of semantic content are obtained in the absence of any corresponding syntactic form. The syntax thus appears to be incomplete. More specifically, the implicit semantic content is recovered from elements of the linguistic and non-linguistic context. In this sense, ellipsis is similar to anaphora, except that there is no overt anaphoric element involved. The elements present in an elliptical clause are predicates, arguments or adjuncts of what is omitted. It is the presence of these elements that makes it possible to recognize the ellipsis. It is in principle always possible to reanalyse any elliptical phenomenon as a case of anaphora, either by hypothesizing an unpronounced pro-form in the elliptical site (zero-anaphora) or by considering the licenser to be anaphoric (e.g., considering the pre-elliptical auxiliary to be an anaphor in Verb Phrase ellipsis (VPE), cf., Schachter 1978; ∗This piece is dedicated to the memory of our friend, teacher, and collaborator, Ivan Sag. Ivan was originally intended as a co-author of this piece, but died before it was drafted. His inspiration and many ideas are evident, though the chapter is much the poorer due to his absence. We would like to thank Doug Arnold, Bob Borsley, Rui Chaves, Jong-Bok Kim, Jason Merchant, Franc¸ois Mouret, Stefan Muller,¨ Enric Vallduv´ı, and Tom Wasow, as well as two anonymous reviewers for comments on the first version.
    [Show full text]