An Experimental Study of Polysemy and Copredication in Container and Group Nominals

Total Page:16

File Type:pdf, Size:1020Kb

An Experimental Study of Polysemy and Copredication in Container and Group Nominals UNIVERSITY OF CALIFORNIA SANTA CRUZ SORTING A COMPLEX WORLD: AN EXPERIMENTAL STUDY OF POLYSEMY AND COPREDICATION IN CONTAINER AND GROUP NOMINALS A dissertation submitted in partial satisfaction of the requirements for the degree of DOCTOR OF PHILOSOPHY in LINGUISTICS by Karen Duek Silveira Bueno September 2017 The Dissertation of Karen Duek Sil- veira Bueno is approved: Professor Adrian Brasoveanu, Chair Professor Donka Farkas Associate Professor Pranav Anand Tyrus Miller Vice Provost and Dean of Graduate Studies Copyright c by Karen Duek Silveira Bueno 2017 Table of Contents 1 Introduction 1 2 The ambiguity of container phrases is a type of polysemy 13 2.1 Introduction . 13 2.1.1 Defining the class of container nouns . 15 2.2 A basic two-way split: Container vs. Contents . 20 2.2.1 Selection . 21 2.2.2 Contextual plausibility/world knowledge . 28 2.3 The container reading . 32 2.3.1 The containment relation . 32 2.3.2 What is counted . 34 2.3.3 Anaphoric possibilities . 35 2.4 The contents readings: measure vs. concrete portion . 36 2.4.1 The containment relation . 38 2.4.2 What is counted . 41 2.4.3 Anaphoric possibilities . 43 2.5 Co-predication . 46 2.6 Predictions for co-predication from previous accounts . 49 2.7 Conclusion . 58 3 Experimental evidence for the polysemy of container phrases 62 3.1 Experiment 1: establishing the acceptability of co-predication . 62 3.1.1 Experimental design and materials . 66 3.1.2 Predictions . 69 3.1.3 Participants and procedure . 72 3.1.4 Results and analysis. 72 3.1.5 Discussion . 81 3.2 Experiment 2: container nouns in isolation . 84 3.2.1 Participants and procedure . 85 3.2.2 Design and materials: The effect of number . 85 3.2.3 Results and analysis . 86 iii 3.2.4 Design and materials: The source of polysemy . 87 3.2.5 Results . 90 3.2.6 Discussion . 93 3.3 Experiment 3: strengthening selectional requirements . 97 3.3.1 Participants and procedure . 101 3.3.2 Results . 101 3.3.3 Discussion . 105 4 The ambiguity of committee nouns as a type of polysemy 115 4.1 Introduction . 115 4.2 Defining the class of committee nouns . 121 4.3 The social object interpretation of committee nominals . 130 4.3.1 Selection . 130 4.3.2 Contextual plausibility/World knowledge . 131 4.3.3 Anaphoric possibilities . 133 4.4 The members interpretation of committee nominals . 134 4.4.1 Selection . 134 4.4.2 Contextual plausibility/World knowledge . 137 4.4.3 Anaphoric possibilities . 139 4.5 Co-predication: the nature of the ambiguity of committee nominals . 140 4.6 Predictions for co-predication from previous accounts . 142 5 Experimental evidence for the polysemy of committee nouns 153 5.1 Introduction . 153 5.2 Experimental Design and Materials . 154 5.3 Predictions . 161 5.4 Participants and procedure . 162 5.5 Results and analysis . 163 5.5.1 Comparing the effect of sense mismatching across nominal types . 165 5.6 Discussion . 174 6 Theoretical implications of experimental results 182 6.0.1 The updated empirical landscape . 182 6.0.2 Limitations of the experimental data . 184 6.0.3 Desiderata . 187 6.1 Assessing the possibility of applying Asher’s (2011) polysemy framework . 189 6.1.1 Polysemy under Asher(2011) . 191 6.1.2 Container phrases and committee nominals as dot types . 198 6.1.3 Limits to Asher’s (2011) predictive and explanatory power . 212 6.2 Assessing the possibility of applying Dölling (1995)’s polysemy framework . 215 6.2.1 Dölling (1995) . 215 6.2.2 Domain mapping relations . 219 6.2.3 Polysemy and Coercion in Dölling . 221 6.2.4 Revised Dölling on groups . 235 6.2.5 Beyond co-predication: returning to the original data . 239 iv 7 Conclusions 251 8 References 257 v Abstract: Sorting a complex world: An experimental study of polysemy and copredication in container and group nominals Karen Duek Silveira Bueno This dissertation is an investigation of the nature of the ambiguity of two classes of nominal expressions in English: container phrases, such as bottle of wine and box of toys, which are said to be interpreted as primarily a predicate true of the container (Ana broke that bottle of wine) or a predicate true of entity standing in a containment relation to that container (Ana drank that bottle of wine), and committee nominals, such as committee of linguists or gang of clowns, which are said to be interpreted as primarily a predicate true of an abstract social object (That committee was founded last year) or as a predicate true of the individuals standing in a membership relation to that social object (That committee met this morning). Through a series of acceptability judgment experiments, I show that both types of phrases support copredication, being able to enter into multiple predication relations which require, via selectional restrictions, that they make available both types of interpretations simulta- neously (Ana broke the bottle of wine that Lea drank/ The committee that was founded last year met this morning). In this way, they are shown to display behavior similar to well known cases of nominal polysemy (Ana burned the book that Lea translated). Based on these results, I argue that these two cases, previously analyzed in isolation, belong to a broader landscape of meaning flexibility, and that the specialized meaning shift oper- ations previously proposed are both inadequate, because they predict the unacceptability vi of copredication, and unnecessary, if these can be analyzed under general frameworks of polysemy and coercion. The dissertation explores the possibility of doing so under two such frameworks: Asher?s (2011) system of complex types, and Dolling?s (1995) system of meaning shifts between sortal domains, pointing to the ways in which they can be successfully applied to the case of con- tainer and committee nominals, but also their limitations, particularly with regards to their predictive and explanatory power and calling attention to the question of understanding, beyond the question of what formal mechanisms are necessary to account for copredication, what property may characterize the relations, such as containment and membership, which underlie systematic meaning flexibility. vii Chapter 1 Introduction Formal semanticists are not particularly known for their sharp sense of humor, but there is one joke most students that have ever attended a formal semantics class might have heard. It goes like this: "What is the meaning of life? Life’." It is somewhat funny because it is somewhat true. The question semanticists hear is, what is the meaning of the linguistic expression life? The answer seems empty: life’ is a notation indicating, in essence, that the conceptual content of that expression - its intension - is not fleshed out in its linguistic representation. It is to be found elsewhere. In truth, that is only partially the answer formal semantics gives to the general question of what is the meaning of a content nominal. That is, the meaning of cat is not simply cat’, though it includes it. The linguistically relevant parts of the meaning of that expression are seen as those that speak to how this expression is able to combine with others compositionally 1 to yield sentence level meanings. A common view, carried through from Montague’s (1973) work, is that the meaning of common nouns such as cat can be modeled using set theoretic tools: cat is the set of cats that exist in our model of the world - its extension. Equivalently, it can be modeled as a function between two primitive domains: the domain of entities that exist in our model of the world, and the domain of truth values - True or False. The truth values represent an assessment of whether the claim that is being made about the properties of those entities is congruent with our knowledge and beliefs about the world as represented in our model. The two primitives - entities and truth values - form a system of types, that limit the domain of the variables in our functions. An expression can then be of type e, if it denotes an entity, of type t, if it denotes a truth value, or it may be of a type constructed recursively out of those primitives, for instance, of type <e,t> if it denotes a function from entities to truth values, or of type <e<e,t> if it denotes a function from entities to a function from entities to truth values, and so forth. A noun like cat can then be represented as the following function, of type <e,t>. That is, its term x must be of the type e, it must be in the domain of entities, and if the denotation of that variable is also in the set denoted by cat’, the function returns the truth value True. (1) cat: λx.cat’(x) 2 This view of meaning of cat or most other common nouns, therefore assumes that very little about the concept of cat is a relevant part of its linguistic meaning, since it assumes that this plays no role in its combinatoric possibilities beyond driving its type specification. We need to know that cat denotes a one-place function, and that its variable must be of type e, and that is enough. Indeed, this view has proven enough to spring forward an understanding of a number of distinct semantic phenomena in this framework in the past half century or so. This dissertation is an exploration of an area in which some of these assumptions prove to be an obstacle, in particular in what concerns what kind of information about how we common sensically conceive of entities is encoded in the meaning of linguistic expressions.
Recommended publications
  • Degrees As Kinds Vs. Degrees As Numbers: Evidence from Equatives1 Linmin ZHANG — NYU Shanghai
    Degrees as kinds vs. degrees as numbers: Evidence from equatives1 Linmin ZHANG — NYU Shanghai Abstract. Within formal semantics, there are two views with regard to the ontological status of degrees: the ‘degree-as-number’ view (e.g., Seuren, 1973; Hellan, 1981; von Stechow, 1984) and the ‘degree-as-kind’ view (e.g., Anderson and Morzycki, 2015). Based on (i) empirical distinctions between comparatives and equatives and (ii) Stevens’s (1946) theory on the four levels of measurements, I argue that both views are motivated and needed in accounting for measurement- and comparison-related meanings in natural language. Specifically, I argue that since the semantics of comparatives potentially involves measurable differences, comparatives need to be analyzed based on scales with units, on which degrees are like (real) numbers. In contrast, since equatives are typically used to convey the non-existence of differences, equa- tives can be based on scales without units, on which degrees can be considered kinds. Keywords: (Gradable) adjectives, Comparatives, Equatives, Similatives, Levels of measure- ments, Measurements, Comparisons, Kinds, Degrees, Dimensions, Scales, Units, Differences. 1. Introduction The notion of degrees plays a fundamental conceptual role in understanding measurements and comparisons. Within the literature of formal semantics, there are two major competing views with regard to the ontological status of degrees. For simplicity, I refer to these two ontologies as the ‘degree-as-number’ view and the ‘degree-as-kind’ view in this paper. Under the more canonical ‘degree-as-number’ view, degrees are considered primitive objects (of type d). Degrees are points on abstract totally ordered scales (see Seuren, 1973; Hellan, 1981; von Stechow, 1984; Heim, 1985; Kennedy, 1999).
    [Show full text]
  • A Theory of Names and True Intensionality*
    A Theory of Names and True Intensionality? Reinhard Muskens Tilburg Center for Logic and Philosophy of Science [email protected] http://let.uvt.nl/general/people/rmuskens/ Abstract. Standard approaches to proper names, based on Kripke's views, hold that the semantic values of expressions are (set-theoretic) functions from possible worlds to extensions and that names are rigid designators, i.e. that their values are constant functions from worlds to entities. The difficulties with these approaches are well-known and in this paper we develop an alternative. Based on earlier work on a higher order logic that is truly intensional in the sense that it does not validate the axiom scheme of Extensionality, we develop a simple theory of names in which Kripke's intuitions concerning rigidity are accounted for, but the more unpalatable consequences of standard implementations of his theory are avoided. The logic uses Frege's distinction between sense and reference and while it accepts the rigidity of names it rejects the view that names have direct reference. Names have constant denotations across possible worlds, but the semantic value of a name is not determined by its denotation. Keywords: names, axiom of extensionality, true intensionality, rigid designation 1 Introduction Standard approaches to proper names, based on Kripke (1971, 1972), make the following three assumptions. (a) The semantic values of expressions are (possibly partial) functions from pos- sible worlds to extensions. (b) These functions are identified with their graphs, as in set theory. (c) Names are rigid designators, i.e. their extensions are world-independent. In particular, the semantic values of names are taken to be constant functions from worlds to entities, possibly undefined for some worlds.
    [Show full text]
  • EISS 12 Empirical Issues in Syntax and Semantics 12
    EISS 12 Empirical Issues in Syntax and Semantics 12 Edited by Christopher Pinon 2019 CSSP Paris http://www.cssp.cnrs.fr/eiss12/ ISSN 1769-7158 Contents Preface iv Anne Abeillé & Shrita Hassamal 1–30 Sluicing in Mauritian: A Fragment-Based Analysis Aixiu An & Anne Abeillé 31–60 Number Agreement in French Binomials Micky Daniels & Yael Greenberg 61–89 Extreme Adjectives in Comparative Structures and even Emilie Destruel & Joseph P. De Veaugh-Geiss 91–120 (Non-)Exhaustivity in French c’est-Clefts Regine Eckardt & Andrea Beltrama 121–155 Evidentials and Questions Yanwei Jin & Jean-Pierre Koenig 157–186 Expletive Negation in English, French, and Mandarin: A Semantic and Language Production Model Fabienne Martin & Zsófia Gyarmathy 187–216 A Finer-grained Typology of Perfective Operators Vítor Míguez 217–246 On (Un)certainty: The Semantic Evolution of Galician seguramente Emanuel Quadros 247–276 The Semantics of Possessive Noun Phrases and Temporal Modifiers EISS 12 iii Preface This is the twelfth volume of the series Empirical Issues in Syntax and Semantics (EISS), which, like the preceding eleven volumes of the series, is closely related to the conference series Colloque de Syntaxe et Sémantique à Paris (CSSP). The nine papers included in the present volume are based on presentations given at CSSP 2017, which took place on 23–25 November 2017 at École Normale Supérieure (http: //www.cssp.cnrs.fr/cssp2017/index_en.html). CSSP 2017 had a small thematic session entitled Discourse particles, but since the number of papers from the thematic session submitted to the volume was low, they are not grouped separately. I would like to take this opportunity to thank the reviewers, whose comments aided the authors in revising the first drafts of their pa- pers, sometimes substantially.
    [Show full text]
  • Donkey Anaphora Is In-Scope Binding∗
    Semantics & Pragmatics Volume 1, Article 1: 1–46, 2008 doi: 10.3765/sp.1.1 Donkey anaphora is in-scope binding∗ Chris Barker Chung-chieh Shan New York University Rutgers University Received 2008-01-06 = First Decision 2008-02-29 = Revised 2008-03-23 = Second Decision 2008-03-25 = Revised 2008-03-27 = Accepted 2008-03-27 = Published 2008- 06-09 Abstract We propose that the antecedent of a donkey pronoun takes scope over and binds the donkey pronoun, just like any other quantificational antecedent would bind a pronoun. We flesh out this idea in a grammar that compositionally derives the truth conditions of donkey sentences containing conditionals and relative clauses, including those involving modals and proportional quantifiers. For example, an indefinite in the antecedent of a conditional can bind a donkey pronoun in the consequent by taking scope over the entire conditional. Our grammar manages continuations using three independently motivated type-shifters, Lift, Lower, and Bind. Empirical support comes from donkey weak crossover (*He beats it if a farmer owns a donkey): in our system, a quantificational binder need not c-command a pronoun that it binds, but must be evaluated before it, so that donkey weak crossover is just a special case of weak crossover. We compare our approach to situation-based E-type pronoun analyses, as well as to dynamic accounts such as Dynamic Predicate Logic. A new ‘tower’ notation makes derivations considerably easier to follow and manipulate than some previous grammars based on continuations. Keywords: donkey anaphora, continuations, E-type pronoun, type-shifting, scope, quantification, binding, dynamic semantics, weak crossover, donkey pronoun, variable-free, direct compositionality, D-type pronoun, conditionals, situation se- mantics, c-command, dynamic predicate logic, donkey weak crossover ∗ Thanks to substantial input from Anna Chernilovskaya, Brady Clark, Paul Elbourne, Makoto Kanazawa, Chris Kennedy, Thomas Leu, Floris Roelofsen, Daniel Rothschild, Anna Szabolcsi, Eytan Zweig, and three anonymous referees.
    [Show full text]
  • Nominal Anchoring
    Nominal anchoring Specificity, definiteness and article systems across languages Edited by Kata Balogh Anja Latrouite Robert D. Van Valin‚ Jr. language Topics at the Grammar­Discourse science press Interface 5 Topics at the Grammar­Discourse Interface Editors: Philippa Cook (University of Göttingen), Anke Holler (University of Göttingen), Cathrine Fabricius­Hansen (University of Oslo) In this series: 1. Song, Sanghoun. Modeling information structure in a cross­linguistic perspective. 2. Müller, Sonja. Distribution und Interpretation von Modalpartikel­Kombinationen. 3. Bueno Holle, Juan José. Information structure in Isthmus Zapotec narrative and conversation. 4. Parikh, Prashant. Communication and content. 5. Balogh, Kata, Anja Latrouite & Robert D. Van Valin‚ Jr. (eds.) Nominal anchoring: Specificity, definiteness and article systems across languages. ISSN: 2567­3335 Nominal anchoring Specificity, definiteness and article systems across languages Edited by Kata Balogh Anja Latrouite Robert D. Van Valin‚ Jr. language science press Balogh, Kata, Anja Latrouite & Robert D. Van Valin‚ Jr. (eds.). 2020. Nominal anchoring: Specificity, definiteness and article systems across languages (Topics at the Grammar-Discourse Interface 5). Berlin: Language Science Press. This title can be downloaded at: http://langsci-press.org/catalog/book/283 © 2020, the authors Published under the Creative Commons Attribution 4.0 Licence (CC BY 4.0): http://creativecommons.org/licenses/by/4.0/ ISBN: 978-3-96110-284-6 (Digital) 978-3-96110-285-3 (Hardcover) ISSN:
    [Show full text]
  • Individual/Degree Polysemy∗
    individual/degree polysemy∗ The Emergence of Number Conference, OSU Jessica Rett June 29, 2018 1 introduction • historically, several different and distinct phenomena: { amount relatives (Carlson, 1980; Heim, 1987; Grosu and Landman, 1998) (1) a. Jane drank [DP the champagne [CP they bought that evening]] individual b. It will take us the rest of our lives to drink [DP the champagne [CP they spilled that evening]] amount { container/pseudopartitive polysemy (Chierchia, 1998) (2) a. Jane smashed [DP the bottle of wine] container b. Jane drank [DP the bottle of wine] content { measure phrase polysemy (Stavrou, 2003; Landman, 2004; Rothstein, 2009) (3) a. The [two cups of wine] on this tray are blue. substance b. The [two cups of wine] in this soup is overkill. measure noun { the `how many' ambiguity (Cresti, 1995; Romero, 1998) (4) How many books must Jane read? a. Jane was told to read specific books. How many of them? object b. Jane was told to read a specific number of books. What was it? amount • correspondingly, different and distinct formal accounts: { amount relatives (Grosu, 2009; Kotek, 2011) ∗ lots of options, all construction-specific: ∗ syntactic ambiguity from a covert maximality operator in the CP; or ∗ syntactically restricted deferred reference or polysemy { container/pseudopartitive polysemy ∗ from Chierchia 1998: a construction-specific type-shifter C from a container x to its contained substance y (5) a. John smoked two packs of cigarettes. b. rλxpsmoke(John, Cpxqqqs (2(pl(pack(ι cigarettes)))) ∗ informally: `John smoked the contents of two packs of cigarettes.' ∗ elsewhere (in line with what I will propose; Pustejovsky 1995; Pustejovsky and Bouillon 1995): this is a semantic polysemy with syntactic effects ∗The bulk of this talk is based on Rett 2014.
    [Show full text]
  • Similatives and the Argument Structure of Verbs∗
    Similatives and the argument structure of verbs∗ Jessica Rett May 2012 Abstract I begin with the observation in Haspelmath and Buchholz (1998) that languages tend to use the same morpheme to mark the standard of comparison across equation constructions. In English, it is the morpheme as, in similatives like John danced as Sue (did) and equatives like John is as tall as Sue (is). The first goal of this paper is to provide an analysis of as that accounts for its distribution across these constructions. The second goal of this paper is to provide an account of Haspelmath and Buchholz's second observation, which is that while languages can form equatives with parameter markers (the first as in John is as tall as Sue (is)), languages generally do not form similatives with parameter markers. I suggest that equation constructions are a test for lexicalized argumenthood, i.e. that the equation of a non-lexicalized argument prohibits the presence of a PM, and, for English, vice-versa. This leads to the conclusion that, contrary to recent claims (Pi~n´on2008, Bochnak forthcoming), verbs, unlike adjectives, generally do not lexicalize degree arguments. 1 Introduction This paper has a narrow empirical goal and a broader theoretical goal. The former has to do with several con- structions which form a natural morphological and semantic class across languages: equation constructions, exemplified in (1) and (2) in English. (1) a. John read the same book as Sue. same/different construction b. John is as tall as Sue. equative (2) a. John danced as Sue did. (manner) similative b.
    [Show full text]
  • 40.Frana.Concealed Questions
    Forthcoming in L. Matthewson, C. Meier, H. Rullmann and T. E. Zimmermann (eds.), Companion to Semantics, Wiley’s Linguistics Companion Series. Concealed Questions (Pre-final version) Ilaria Frana University of Enna “Kore” [email protected] Abstract Concealed questions (CQs) are determiner phrases that are interpreted as if they were embedded questions. For instance, Eve’s phone number in Adam knows Eve’s phone number is interpreted as having the meaning of the question what Eve’s phone number is. CQs raise two preliminary challenges. First, it is not clear how such cases should be integrated into a uniform analysis of predicates that select for questions, canonically realized by CPs, not DPs. Second, it has to be explained how a definite description, which would normally be used to pick out an entity in the world acquires this question- like meaning. More generally, since it is not obvious how the truth-conditions of CQ- sentences should be computed, this construction raises a challenge for the principle of compositionality, according to which the literal meaning of a sentence is a function of the meanings of its parts and of the way they are syntactically combined. Keywords: attitude ascriptions, individual concepts, questions, selection, type-shifters 1. Introduction When the nominal argument of (certain) question-selecting verbs gives rise to a question- like interpretation, it goes with the name of concealed question (henceforth, CQ); some examples and their paraphrases are given below.1 (1) a. Mary knows Joan’s phone number. b. The X-ray revealed the gender of the baby. c. Your airline ticket price depends on when and where you travel.
    [Show full text]
  • The Semantics of the Czech Demonstrative Ten I Propose A
    The semantics of the Czech demonstrative ten I propose a semantic analysis of the demonstrative ten in Czech, in which ten (i) is a type-flexible and type-preserving operator, (ii) does not involve the presuppositional type-shifter ◆, and (iii) introduces two variables: an index i that “points at” some entity in the discourse (or extra-linguistic reality) and a relational variable Rj, whose value determines the relation between i and the denotation of the NP modified by the demonstrative (henceforth demonstrative NP). Core evidence Ten (glossed as dem) productively modifies NPs without a↵ecting their referential status (e.g., Berger 1993). Readings (a) of (1) and (2) show that the canonical referential reading (of Mirkem in (1)) and the canonical predicative reading (of pr´avn´ık ‘lawyer’ in (2)) can remain una↵ected by the modification by a demonstrative. Readings (b) represent the “expected” case, where the demonstrative appears to shift a predicative nominal (coerced and typically modified by a relative clause in (1)) to a referential one. The existence of readings (a) shows (i) that ten can modify both referential (type e) and predicative (type e, t ) expressions and (ii) that ten need not h i a↵ect the semantic type of the NP it modifies. (1) S t´ım Mirkem jsem nemluvil. (2) Karel je vlastnˇe ten pr´avn´ık. with dem Mirek aux.1sg neg.spoke Karel is part dem lawyer a. ‘I didn’t speak with Mirek.’ a. ‘Karel is a lawyer.’ b. ‘I didn’t speak with that Mirek.’ b. ‘Karel is the lawyer.’ Proposal The facts above could indicate either that ten is (multiply) ambiguous or that it is underspecified.
    [Show full text]
  • Interpreting Questions with Non-Exhaustive Answers
    Interpreting Questions with Non-exhaustive Answers A dissertation presented by Yimei Xiang to The Department of Linguistics in partial fulfillment of the requirements for the degree of Doctor of Philosophy in the subject of Linguistics Harvard University Cambridge, Massachusetts May 2016 © 2016 – Yimei Xiang All rights reserved. iii Dissertation Advisor: Prof. Gennaro Chierchia Yimei Xiang Interpreting Questions with Non-exhaustive Answers Abstract This dissertation investigates the semantics of questions, with a focus on phenomena that challenge the standard views of the related core issues, as well as those that are technically difficult to capture under standard compositional semantics. It begins by re-examining several fundamental issues, such as what a question denotes, how a question is composed, and what a wh-item denotes. It then tackles questions with complex structures, including mention-some questions, multi-wh questions, and questions with quantifiers. It also explores several popular issues, such as variations of exhaustivity, sensitivity to false answers, and quantificational variability effects. Chapter 1 discusses some fundamental issues on question semantics. I pursue a hybrid categorial approach and define question roots as topical properties, which can supply propositional answers as well as nominal short answers. But different from traditional categorial approaches, I treat wh- items as existential quantifiers, which can be shifted into domain restrictors via a BeDom-operator. Moreover, I argue that the live-on set of a plural or number-neutral wh-item is polymorphic: it consists of not only individuals but also generalized conjunctions and disjunctions. Chapter 2 and 3 are centered on mention-some questions. Showing that the availability of mention-some should be grammatically restricted, I attribute the mention-some/mention-all ambi- guity of 3-questions to structural variations within the question nucleus.
    [Show full text]
  • The Semantics and Pragmatics of Perspectival Expressions in English and Bulu: the Case of Deictic Motion Verbs
    The semantics and pragmatics of perspectival expressions in English and Bulu: The case of deictic motion verbs Dissertation Presented in Partial Fulfillment of the Requirements for the Degree Doctor of Philosophy in the Graduate School of The Ohio State University By Jefferson Barlew ∼6 6 Graduate Program in Linguistics The Ohio State University 2017 Dissertation Committee: Professor Craige Roberts, Advisor Professor Judith Tonhauser, Advisor Professor Marie Catherine de Marneffe Professor Zhiguo Xie c Jefferson Barlew, 2017 Abstract Researchers have long had the intuition that interpreting deictic motion verbs involves perspective-taking (see e.g. Fillmore 1965, 1966). In some sense, this perspective-taking is what differentiates deictic motion verbs from other motion verbs. It's what makes them \deictic". In this dissertation, I investigate the role perspective-taking plays in the inter- pretation of two deictic motion verbs in two typologically unrelated languages, the verbs come in English and zu `come' in Bulu, a Bantu language of Cameroon. The investigation reveals that zu `come' represents a previously undocumented type of deictic motion verb and that, differences in meanings notwithstanding, the interpretation of both verbs does involve perspective-taking. Part I of the dissertation consists of detailed investigations of the meanings of come and zu `come'. Conducting detailed investigations of their meanings makes it possible to state precisely the connection between their lexical semantics and pragmatics and perspective taking. Here it is. Interpreting either come or zu `come' requires the retrieval of a con- textually supplied perspective, a body of knowledge that represents the way a particular individual imagines things to be.
    [Show full text]
  • Negation, Questions, and Structure Building in a Homesign System
    Cognition 118 (2011) 398–416 Contents lists available at ScienceDirect Cognition journal homepage: www.elsevier.com/locate/COGNIT Negation, questions, and structure building in a homesign system a, b c Amy Franklin ⇑, Anastasia Giannakidou , Susan Goldin-Meadow a University of Texas Health Science Center Houston, School of Biomedical Informatics, Center for Cognitive Informatics and Decision Making, 7000 Fannin Suite, 600 Houston, Tx 77030, United States b University of Chicago, Department of Linguistics, 1010 E. 59th St.Chicago, IL 60637, United States c University of Chicago, Departments of Psychology and Human Development, 5730 S. Woodlawn Ave. Chicago, IL 60637, United States article info abstract Article history: Deaf children whose hearing losses are so severe that they cannot acquire spoken language, Received 13 October 2009 and whose hearing parents have not exposed them to sign language, use gestures called Revised 9 August 2010 homesigns to communicate. Homesigns have been shown to contain many of the properties Accepted 27 August 2010 of natural languages. Here we ask whether homesign has structure building devices for Available online 19 November 2010 negation and questions. We identify two meanings (negation, question) that correspond semantically to propositional functions, that is, to functions that apply to a sentence Keywords: (whose semantic value is a proposition, /) and yield another proposition that is more com- Negation plex ( for negation; ? for question). Combining with or ? thus involves sentence Questions q/
    [Show full text]