An Essay on Inferential Knowledge

Total Page:16

File Type:pdf, Size:1020Kb

An Essay on Inferential Knowledge KNOWLEDGE FROM KNOWLEDGE: AN ESSAY ON INFERENTIAL KNOWLEDGE BY RODRIGO MARTINS BORGES A dissertation submitted to the Graduate School|New Brunswick Rutgers, The State University of New Jersey in partial fulfillment of the requirements for the degree of Doctor of Philosophy Graduate Program in Philosophy Written under the direction of Peter D. Klein and approved by New Brunswick, New Jersey October, 2015 ABSTRACT OF THE DISSERTATION Knowledge from Knowledge: An Essay on Inferential Knowledge by Rodrigo Martins Borges Dissertation Director: Peter D. Klein Under what conditions do we have inferential knowledge? I propose and defend the following principle: S knows that p via inference only if S knows all the premises essentially involved in her inference in support of p - \KFK" for short. Even though KFK is at least tacitly endorsed by many figures in the history of philosophy, from Aristotle through Descartes, and Kant to Bertrand Russell { and, more recently, by David Armstrong { KFK has fallen into disfavor among epistemologists over the past fifty years. In response to Edmund Gettier's leg- endary paper, many have proposed views according to which one's reasoning is a source of knowledge even if one fails to know some or all premises essentially involved in one's reasoning, while others have given up offering a theory of in- ferential knowledge and have focused on reasoning as a source of justified belief instead. Unfortunately, these accounts that deal with inferential knowledge are problematic; they cannot, for example, fully explain our common practice of eval- uating negatively inferences with unknown premises. They also seem to rely on ii an overly narrow understanding of the so-called \Gettier Problem". This dis- sertation aims at updating the approach to reasoning that was popular before Gettier by building on the framework of Timothy Williamson's \knowledge-first” epistemology. The aim is to carefully elaborate the view that reasoning yields knowledge only if all the premises essentially involved are also known. iii Acknowledgements My work has benefited immensely from my exchanges with a great number of peo- ple. First and foremost, Peter Klein has been not only the best advisor anyone could hope for (supportive, patient, challenging), but he is also the best philoso- pher with whom I have ever discussed philosophy. Suffice it to say that, if I were to give full credit to Peter's supervision, I would probably have to thank him in a footnote to virtually every paragraph in this dissertation. Needless to say, he does not agree with everything I say here and I am also fully responsible for any mistakes in the text below. I would also like to thank the other members of my committee, Ernie Sosa, Duncan Pritchard and Claudio de Almeida. They all read different versions of some or most of the material in this dissertation and they have all contributed to making it a much better work than I could have by myself. Finally, I list (in no particular order), other people who, through conversations, written comments, emails or even facebook posts helped me write this dissertation: Luis Rosa, David Black, Tiegue Vieira, Daniel Rubio, Lisa Mirachi, Tobias Wilsch, Marcello Antosh, Bob Beddor, Thomas Blanchard, Tim Campbell, Will Fleisher, Georgi Gardiner, Luvell Anderson, Matthew Benton, Simon Goldstein, Ricardo Mena, Alex Morgan, Pamela Robinson, David Rose, Mary Salvaggio, Justin Sharber, Kurt Sylvan, Guido Melchior, Carlotta Pavese, Martha Bolton, Ruth Chang, Andy Egan, Branden Fitelson, Anthony Gillies, Alvin Goldman, Doug Husak, Jeff King, Howard McGary, Brian McLaughlin, Jeff McMahan, Jonathan Schaffer, Susanna Schellenberg, Steve Stich, Larry Temkin, Michael Veber, Linda Zagzebski, Jonathan Vogel, Anthony Brueckner, Sherri Roush, Jennifer Lackey, Juan Comesa~na,E.J Coffman, John Hawthorne, Fred iv Adams, Timothy Williamson, Peter Baumann, Stephen Hetherington, Ram Neta and Stephen Grimm. I also need to acknowledge the institutional support I re- ceived from Rutgers, particularly, from the staff in the Philosophy Department. In the very practical sense of the word \possible", this dissertation would not have been possible without the hard work and competence of Pauline Mitchell, Jean Urteil and, especially, the incomparable Mercedes Diaz. At home, my wife Lizette Nieves has been the most supportive and encouraging partner anyone can ask for. She has been very patient, and for that I will be forever grateful. I am indebted also to my father Jo~aoT. Borges, for his unconditional support all the way from Brazil. My gratitude also to Melanie Crisfield for proofreading the dissertation. The research for this dissertation was partially funded by the CAPES/Fulbright Commission through a four-year fellowship (2007-2011). I am very grateful for their support. v Dedication In loving memory of Norma Martins Borges (1942-2012). vi Table of Contents Abstract ::::::::::::::::::::::::::::::::::: ii Acknowledgements ::::::::::::::::::::::::::::: iv Dedication :::::::::::::::::::::::::::::::::: vi 1. Introduction :::::::::::::::::::::::::::::::: 1 1.1. What Knowledge Is . 2 1.2. What Is To Come . 15 2. Knowledge from Knowledge :::::::::::::::::::::: 16 2.1. Clarifying KFK . 24 3. KFK, E=K, and The Knowledge Norm of Inference :::::: 38 3.1. From E=K to KFK . 38 3.2. Objection: No Gettier Problem . 40 3.3. Objection: Dogmatism . 52 3.3.1. Dogmatism: Synchronic and Diachronic . 54 3.3.2. Harman's Argument for Diachronic Dogmatism . 57 The Junk Knowledge Response to Diachronic Dogmatism 60 3.3.3. Kripke's Argument for Synchronic Dogmatism . 66 A Failed Response to Synchronic Dogmatism . 69 3.3.4. Dogmatism Depuzzled . 74 3.3.5. A new argument for dogmatism? . 83 3.3.6. Taking Stock . 85 3.4. The Knowledge Norm of Inference . 86 vii 3.4.1. Knowledge Norms: Assertion, Action and Inference . 91 4. KFK and the Gettier Problem :::::::::::::::::::: 106 4.1. The Gettier Conjecture . 107 4.2. What counts as a Gettier case? . 109 4.3. Two Gettier Problems . 115 4.4. Some Caveats . 116 4.5. A recent ancestor of the Gettier Conjecture . 118 5. Epistemic Luck :::::::::::::::::::::::::::::: 123 5.1. Anti-Luck Epistemology . 123 5.2. The Appeal To The Concept Of Epistemic Luck . 125 5.3. Precisifying The Anti-Luck View . 129 5.4. Against Anti-Luck Epistemology . 131 5.4.1. Lucky But Safe True Belief: Against Epistemic Luck . 131 5.4.2. Lucky But Counterfactually Robust Events: Against Generic Luck . 133 5.5. Gettier-Lucky Knowledge? . 134 5.5.1. The Argument for \Gettierism" . 135 5.5.2. An Alleged case of Gettier-Lucky Knowledge . 136 5.5.3. What is lucky about Gettier-Lucky belief? . 140 viii 1 Chapter 1 Introduction The main goal of the following essay is to defend the principle about inferential knowledge that I call \Knowledge from knowledge": (KFK) S knows that p via inference or reasoning only if S knows all the premises essentially involved in her inference in support of p. I explain how this principle helps solve the Gettier Problem; I argue that it is entailed by the defeasibility account of knowledge and Williamson's E=K; and I show how it can motivate a plausible norm of appropriate inference. As far as I know, this thesis amounts to the most extensive exploration of KFK in the literature today. Since an essay is not a philosophical work without disputing other philoso- pher's views, I also argue against the most popular account of epistemic and non-epistemic luck. The discussion of this issue is related to KFK to the extent that KFK provides a competing explanation of the Gettier phenomenon. I argue that, on grounds independent of KFK, anti-luck epistemology does not provide an adequate account of luck, epistemic or not. In the remainder of this introduction, I will do two things. First, in the follow- ing section, I will establish some criteria for what knowledge is. Like knowledge- first epistemologists, I am suspicious of the project of analyzing \knowledge", and I take knowledge that p to entail probability 1 of p. I end the introduction with an overview of the chapters that follow. 2 An important characteristic of this thesis (some will say \an important short- coming") is that it assumes a certain form of externalism about evidence and justification (and, consequently, knowledge). So, for example, I assume that ev- idence and justification are not luminous states (i.e., in some circumstances e is evidence for h for S, or S is justified in believing that p, but S is not in a position to know that e is evidence for h, or that S is justified in believing that p). I do not directly argue in favor of this claim. Even though I discuss how I understand evidence and justification in chapters 3 and 4, for the most part I simply assume that those states are not luminous, and I use those notions to try to understand the Gettier Problem and the Dogmatist Paradox, amongst others. So, for the most part, I ask you, the reader, to accept (at least provisionally) this mild form of externalism, and to explore with me some of its consequences. If I am right, this exercise will yield important theoretical dividends we may want to use in the purchase of those assumptions. 1.1 What Knowledge Is Epistemologists traditionally answer the question \What is knowledge?" by offer- ing a definition of the concept \knowledge". I, like others,1 am suspicious of the claim that the most theoretically fruitful answer to the question \What is knowl- edge?" will take the form of a definition. In this section, I will offer the sketch of an argument in support of this suspicion, and later try to answer this central question in philosophy by arguing for plausible criteria something deserving of the name \knowledge" should satisfy. I do not have anything exceptionally deep to say about why attempting to define \knowledge" might not be the best strategy to adopt when trying to give an account of what knowledge is.
Recommended publications
  • The Search for the Source of Epistemic Good Linda
    © Metaphilosophy LLC and Blackwell Publishing Ltd. 2003. Published by Blackwell Publishing, 9600 Garsington Road, Oxford OX4 2DQ, UK and 350 Main Street, Malden, MA 02148, USA METAPHILOSOPHY Vol. 34, Nos. 1/2, January 2003 0026–1068 THE SEARCH FOR THE SOURCE OF EPISTEMIC GOOD LINDA ZAGZEBSKI ABSTRACT: Knowledge has almost always been treated as good, better than mere true belief, but it is remarkably difficult to explain what it is about knowledge that makes it better. I call this “the value problem.” I have previously argued that most forms of reliabilism cannot handle the value problem. In this article I argue that the value problem is more general than a problem for reliabilism, infecting a host of different theories, including some that are internalist. An additional problem is that not all instances of true belief seem to be good on balance, so even if a given instance of knowing p is better than merely truly believing p, not all instances of knowing will be good enough to explain why knowledge has received so much attention in the history of philosophy. The article aims to answer two questions: (1) What makes knowing p better than merely truly believing p? The answer involves an exploration of the connection between believing and the agency of the knower. Knowing is an act in which the knower gets credit for achieving truth. (2) What makes some instances of knowing good enough to make the investigation of knowledge worthy of so much attention? The answer involves the connection between the good of believing truths of certain kinds and a good life.
    [Show full text]
  • The Moral Gap: Kantian Ethics, Human Limits, and God's Assistance
    Philosophical Review The Moral Gap: Kantian Ethics, Human Limits, and God's Assistance. by John E. Hare Review by: Linda Zagzebski The Philosophical Review, Vol. 108, No. 2 (Apr., 1999), pp. 291-293 Published by: Duke University Press on behalf of Philosophical Review Stable URL: http://www.jstor.org/stable/2998307 . Accessed: 21/03/2014 15:30 Your use of the JSTOR archive indicates your acceptance of the Terms & Conditions of Use, available at . http://www.jstor.org/page/info/about/policies/terms.jsp . JSTOR is a not-for-profit service that helps scholars, researchers, and students discover, use, and build upon a wide range of content in a trusted digital archive. We use information technology and tools to increase productivity and facilitate new forms of scholarship. For more information about JSTOR, please contact [email protected]. Duke University Press and Philosophical Review are collaborating with JSTOR to digitize, preserve and extend access to The Philosophical Review. http://www.jstor.org This content downloaded from 129.15.14.53 on Fri, 21 Mar 2014 15:30:07 PM All use subject to JSTOR Terms and Conditions BOOK REVIEWS ThePhilosophical Review, Vol. 108, No. 2 (April 1999) THE MORAL GAP: KANTIANETHICS, HUMAN LIMITS, AND GOD'S AS- SISTANCE. ByJOHN E. HARE. Oxford: Oxford UniversityPress, Claren- don Press, 1996. Pp. x, 292. The titleof Hare's book refersto the gap between the demand that mo- ralityplaces on us and our natural capacity to live by it. Such a gap is paradoxical if we accept the "'ought' implies 'can"' principle. The solu- tion, Hare argues, is that the gap is filled by the Christian God.
    [Show full text]
  • Knowledge Is Closed Under Analytic Content
    Knowledge is Closed Under Analytic Content Samuel Z. Elgin July 2019 Abstract I defend the claim that knowledge is closed under analytic content: that if an agent S knows that p and q is an analytic part of p, then S knows that q. After identifying the relevant notion of analyticity, I argue that this principle correctly diagnoses challenging cases and that it gives rise to novel and plausible necessary and sufficient conditions for knowledge. I close by arguing that contextualists who maintain that knowledge is closed under classical entailment within|but not between|linguistic contexts are tacitly committed to this principle's truth. Knowledge of some propositions requires knowledge of others. All those who know that p ^ q also know that p|as do those who know that p. Agents ignorant of the truth of p lack the epistemic resources to know either the conjunction or the double negation. When does this hold? Is it a feature of conjunction and negation in particular, or are they instances of a more general pattern? Why does this hold? What makes it the case that knowledge of some propositions requires knowledge of others? This is the interpretive question of epistemic closure. The most basic formulation of the closure principle is the following: Na¨ıve Closure: If an agent S knows that p and p entails q, then S knows that q.1 Na¨ıve Closure is transparently false. S may fail to realize that p entails q, and perhaps even disbelieve that q. And, surely, if S does not even believe that q, then S does not know that q.
    [Show full text]
  • PHILOSOPHY of RELIGION Philosophy 185 Spring 2016
    PHILOSOPHY OF RELIGION Philosophy 185 Spring 2016 Dana Kay Nelkin Office: HSS 8004 Office Hours: Monday 11-12, Friday 11-12, and by appointment Phone: (858) 822-0472 E-mail: [email protected] Web site: www.danakaynelkin.com Course Description: We will explore five related and hotly debated topics in the philosophy of religion, and, in doing so, address the following questions: (i) What makes something a religion? (ii) Is it rational to hold religious beliefs? Should we care about rationality when it comes to religious belief? (iii) Could different religions be different paths to the same ultimate reality, or is only one, at most, a “way to God”? (iv) What is the relationship between science and religion? (v) What is the relationship between morality and religion? Must religious beliefs be true in order for morality to exist? As we will see, the philosophy of religion leads naturally into just about every other area of philosophy, including epistemology, metaphysics, ethics, and the history of philosophy, and into particular central philosophical debates such as the debate over the nature of free will. This means that you will gain insight into many fundamental philosophical issues in this course. At the same time, the subject matter can be difficult. To do well in the course and to benefit from it, you must be willing to work hard and to subject your own views (whatever they may be) to critical evaluation. Evaluating our conception of ourselves and of the world is one of the distinguishing features of philosophy. Requirements: Short reading responses/formulations of questions (150-200 words for each class meeting; 20 out of 28 required) 30% 1 paper in two drafts (about 2200 words) o first draft 10% (Due May 13) o second draft, revised after comments 25% (Due May 23) 1 take-home final exam (35%) (Due June 4, 11 am) up to 5% extra credit for participation in class group assignments and discussion.
    [Show full text]
  • A Critical Survey of Some Recent Philosophical Research in China
    Philosophia DOI 10.1007/s11406-016-9768-x A Critical Survey of Some Recent Philosophical Research in China Xingming Hu1 Received: 12 January 2016 /Revised: 23 March 2016 /Accepted: 16 September 2016 # Springer Science+Business Media Dordrecht 2016 Abstract In this paper, I survey some recent literature produced by the established Chinese philosophers who regularly publish in Chinese philosophy journals and work in Mainland China. Specifically, I review the recent research of these philosophers in two areas: Chinese Philosophy and epistemology. In each area, I focus on two topics that have caught the attention of a lot of Chinese philosophers. I argue that the Chinese philosophers’ research on these topics has two prevalent problems: (i) a lot of argu- ments they make are weak; (ii) they tend not to critically engage with others. I discuss a metaphilosophical objection that weak argumentation and disengagement are not vices of philosophical research. I also try to make sense of (i) and (ii) in terms of some cultural factors. Keywords The goal of philosophy. Chinese philosophy. The legitimacy problem . Confucian ethics . Epistemology . The Gettier Problem . External World Skepticism 1 Introduction How has the philosophical research been done in Mainland China? In this paper, I survey some recent literature produced by the established Chinese philosophers who regularly publish in Chinese philosophy journals and work in Mainland China. Specifically, I review the recent research of these philoso- phers in two areas: Chinese Philosophy and epistemology. In each area, I focus on two topics that have caught the attention of a lot of Chinese philosophers. I argue that the Chinese philosophers’ research on these topics has some preva- lent problems, which might be explained in terms of some metaphilosophical commitments and cultural factors.
    [Show full text]
  • 1 Epistemic Closure in Folk Epistemology James R. Beebe And
    Epistemic Closure in Folk Epistemology* James R. Beebe and Jake Monaghan (University at Buffalo) Forthcoming in Joshua Knobe, Tania Lombrozo, and Shaun Nichols (eds.), Oxford Studies in Epistemology We report the results of four empirical studies designed to investigate the extent to which an epistemic closure principle for knowledge is reflected in folk epistemology. Previous work by Turri (2015a) suggested that our shared epistemic practices may only include a source-relative closure principle—one that applies to perceptual beliefs but not to inferential beliefs. We argue that the results of our studies provide reason for thinking that individuals are making a performance error when their knowledge attributions and denials conflict with the closure principle. When we used research materials that overcome what we think are difficulties with Turri’s original materials, we found that participants did not reject closure. Furthermore, when we presented Turri’s original materials to non- philosophers with expertise in deductive reasoning (viz., professional mathematicians), they endorsed closure for both perceptual and inferential beliefs. Our results suggest that an unrestricted closure principle—one that applies to all beliefs, regardless of their source—provides a better model of folk patterns of knowledge attribution than a source-relative closure principle. * This paper has benefited greatly from helpful comments and suggestions from John Turri, Wesley Buckwalter, two anonymous reviewers from Oxford Studies in Experimental Philosophy, an anonymous reviewer for the Second Annual Minds Online Conference, and audiences at the 2015 Experimental Philosophy Group UK conference, the 2016 Southern Society for Philosophy and Psychology conference, and University College Dublin. 1 Keywords: epistemic closure, folk epistemology, experimental philosophy, knowledge, expertise 1.
    [Show full text]
  • European Journal for Philosophy of Religion
    EUROPEAN JOURNAL FOR PHILOSOPHY OF RELIGION VOLUME 6 NUMBER 4 WINTER 2014 ARTICLES C.A.J. COADY Communal and Institutional Trust: Authority in Religion and Politics 1 John COTTINGHAM Authority and Trust: Reflections on Linda Zagzebski’s Epistemic Authority 25 Duncan PRITCHARD & Shane RYAN Zagzebski on Rationality 39 Trent DOUGHERTY Zagzebski, Authority, and Faith 47 Arnon KEREN Zagzebski on Authority and Preemption in the Domain of Belief 61 Jacek WOJTYSIAK Zagzebski on Models of Revelation 77 Charity ANDERSON Epistemic Authority and Conscientious Belief 91 Benjamin MCMYLER Epistemic Authority, Preemption, and Normative Power 101 John SCHWENKLER Tradition as Transmission: A Partial Defense 121 Matthew A. BENTON Believing on Authority 133 Damian LESZCZYŃSKI Inconsistency, Uncertainty and Epistemic Authority 145 Joshue OROZCO & Nathan L. KING Conscientious Self-reflection to the Rescue? 155 Linda ZAGZEBSKI Epistemic Authority and Its Critics 169 BOOK REVIEWS AND NOTICES Paolo Diego Bubbio & Philip Andrew Quadrio (eds). The Relationship of Philosophy to Religion Today Reviewed by Mark Manolopoulos 189 Justin Barrett. Born Believers: The Science of Children’s Religious Belief Reviewed by Aku Visala 193 Charles Taliaferro, Dialogues about God Reviewed by Ulrich Schmidt 199 Fraser Watts (ed.). Creation: Law and Probability Reviewed by Graham Wood 205 COMMUNAL AND INSTITUTIONAL TRUST: AUTHORITY IN RELIGION AND POLITICS C.A.J. COADY University of Melbourne Linda Zagzebski’s book on epistemic authority is an impressive and stimulating treatment of an important topic.1 I admire the way she manages to combine imagination, originality and argumentative control. Her work has the further considerable merit of bringing analytic thinking and abstract theory to bear upon areas of concrete human concern, such as the attitudes one should have towards moral and religious authority.
    [Show full text]
  • 1 Knowledge and the Motive for Truth Linda Zagzebski 1. the Motive For
    Knowledge and the Motive for Truth Linda Zagzebski 1. The motive for truth in our epistemic lives I assume that a self-conscious being is both conscious of the world and conscious of itself being conscious of the world. Because we are self-conscious, we reflect upon our own conscious states, not because we are especially interested in ourselves, but because we think that in doing so we can monitor and improve the connection between those states and their objects in the world. The material upon which we reflect is what we find in our pre- reflective consciousness--our memories, pre-reflective beliefs, and emotions. It also includes trust in the natural attunement of our faculties to reality. Trust is as much a part of our basic endowment as our faculties of perception and reasoning. Our pre-reflective trust is one of the things upon which we reflect when we attempt to monitor the relation between our conscious states and the world. When we reflect, we realize that we have no non-circular way to tell that our faculties have anything to do with the way the world is, so either we turn our pre-reflective trust into reflective trust, or we become skeptics. My view is that the right response to epistemic circularity is to trust reflectively. The point of reflection is to increase the trustworthiness of our faculties, but we can only do that by using those same faculties in an especially careful and directed way. Reflection makes the connection between our faculties and the world more accurate by increasing the coherence of the outputs of those faculties.
    [Show full text]
  • Hereafter, Closure
    Erkenntnis (2006) Ó Springer 2006 DOI 10.1007/s10670-006-9009-y PETER MURPHY A STRATEGY FOR ASSESSING CLOSURE ABSTRACT. This paper looks at an argument strategy for assessing the epistemic closure principle. This is the principle that says knowledge is closed under known entailment; or (roughly) if S knows p and S knows that p entails q, then S knows that q. The strategy in question looks to the individual conditions on knowledge to see if they are closed. According to one conjecture, if all the individual conditions are closed, then so too is knowledge. I give a deductive argument for this conjecture. According to a second conjecture, if one (or more) condition is not closed, then neither is knowledge. I give an inductive argument for this conjecture. In sum, I defend the strategy by defending the claim that knowledge is closed if, and only if, all the conditions on knowledge are closed. After making my case, I look at what this means for the debate over whether knowledge is closed. According to the epistemic closure principle (hereafter, Closure), if someone knows that P, knows that P entails Q, goes on to infer Q, and in this way bases their belief that Q on their belief that P and their belief that P entails Q, then they know that Q. Similar principles cover proposed conditions on knowledge. Call the conditions on knowledge, whatever they might be, k-conditions. A k-condition, C, is closed if and only if the following is true: if S meets C with respect to P and S meets C with respect to P entails Q, and S goes on to infer from these to believe Q thereby basing her belief that Q on these other beliefs, then S meets C with respect to Q.1 On one view about the relationship between knowledge and its conditions, Closure is true just in case all k-conditions are closed.
    [Show full text]
  • Does Ethics Need God?
    DOES ETHICS NEED GOD? Linda Zagzebski ntis essay presents a moral argument for the rationality of theistic belief. If all I have to go on morally are my own moral intuitions and reasoning and those of others, I am rationally led to skepticism, both about the possibility of moral knowledge and about my moral effectiveness. This skepticism is extensive, amounting to moral despair. But such despair cannot be rational. It follows that the assumption of the argument must be false and I must be able to rely on more than my own human powers and those of others in attempting to live a moral life. The Christian God has such a function. Hence, if it is rational to attempt a moral life, it is rational to believe in the Christian God. Whenever anyone begins a study of ethics, a natural question to ask is why should we undertake such a study at all. I am satisfied with the answer that ethics teaches us how to be moral and anyone who understands what morality is will thereby want to live by it, just as anyone who understands the meaning of an analytic proposition will thereby see its truth. But wanting to be moral, I believe, is not sufficient to justify either the study of ethics or the attempt to practice morality. The question, "Should I try to be moral?" is not the same as the classic question, "Why be moral?" The latter question is sufficiently answered by the response that morality is its own justification. Morality aims at the good and anyone who understands what good means will see that its pursuit is justified.
    [Show full text]
  • Evidence, Epistemic Luck, Reliability, and Knowledge
    Acta Analytica https://doi.org/10.1007/s12136-021-00490-0 Evidence, Epistemic Luck, Reliability, and Knowledge Mylan Engel Jr.1 Received: 8 August 2020 / Accepted: 5 August 2021 © Springer Nature B.V. 2021 Abstract In this article, I develop and defend a version of reliabilism – internal reasons relia- bilism – that resolves the paradox of epistemic luck, solves the Gettier problem by ruling out veritic luck, is immune to the generality problem, resolves the internal- ism/externalism controversy, and preserves epistemic closure. Keywords Epistemic luck · Reliabilism · Generality problem · Internalism/ externalism debate · Personal and doxastic justifcation · Analysis of knowledge 1 A Modest Goal My goal is to develop and defend a version of reliabilism—internal reasons reliabi- lism—that resolves the paradox of epistemic luck, solves the Gettier problem by rul- ing out veritic luck, is immune to the generality problem, resolves the internalism/ externalism controversy, and preserves epistemic closure. Let’s begin! 2 The Epistemic Luck Paradox Epistemic luck is a generic notion used to describe various ways in which it is some- how accidental, coincidental, or fortuitous that a person has a true belief that p. The phenomenon of epistemic luck gives rise to an epistemological paradox. The para- dox is generated by three extremely plausible theses. 2.1 The Knowledge Thesis We know a lot. We possess all sorts of knowledge about the world around us. You know that you are currently reading an article on epistemology. I know that I am looking at a computer screen. You know what city you are currently in. I know that * Mylan Engel Jr.
    [Show full text]
  • Truth Analysis of the Gettier Argument
    TRUTH ANALYSIS OF THE GETTIER ARGUMENT YUSSIF YAKUBU Published in: METAPHILOSOPHY Vol. 47, No. 3, July 2016, 449-466 Abstract: Gettier (1963) presented the now famous Gettier problem as a challenge to epistemology. The methods Gettier used to construct his challenge, however, utilized certain principles of formal logic that are actually inappropriate for the natural language discourse of the Gettier cases. In that challenge to epistemology, Gettier also makes truth claims that would be considered controversial in analytic philosophy of language. The Gettier challenge has escaped scrutiny in these other relevant academic disciplines, however, because of its fac¸adeas an epistemological analysis. This article examines Gettiers methods with the analytical tools of logic and analytic philosophy of language. Keywords: definite description, Russellian quantification, Edmund Gettier, referents and truth, classical logic. Introduction Gettier cases are hypothetical scenarios that purport to demonstrate, contrary to the standard epistemological view, that justified true belief (JTB) is not a sufficient condition for knowledge. In a typical Gettier- type case, a premise that “justifiably” leads an agent to a belief turns out to be false, but the belief the agent derives turns out “by coinci- dence to be true.” The believing agent in question is thus deemed to have a true belief that is justifiably reached, and he therefore, while satisfying the conditions for knowledge, nevertheless does not have knowledge, because the premise upon which he formed his belief is false. Epistemologists have generally taken Gettiers arguments against JTB to be successful, and have been trying, for the five decades since Gettiers paper, to come up with a definition or conception of knowl- edge that would not be undermined by the Gettier-challenge (Zagzeb- ski 1994; Shope 2002, 33; Sosa 2007; see also Kvanvig 2011, 29).
    [Show full text]