The Deleuzian Virtual Image Versus the Derridean Trace

Total Page:16

File Type:pdf, Size:1020Kb

The Deleuzian Virtual Image Versus the Derridean Trace A N G E L A K I journal of the theoretical humanitie s volume 5 number 2 august 2000 n the commemorative essay written on the Ioccasion of Deleuze’s death, Derrida spoke of a “nearly total affinity” between the philosophi- cal content of his own work and that of Deleuze.2 In what follows, I am going to argue that there is only a nearly total affinity. In fact, I am going to argue that there is a difference between the philo- sophical content of Derrida and Deleuze because each develops his most basic concepts from different philosophical inspirations: Deleuze with len lawlor Bergson and Derrida with Husserl. So what follows is basically a comparison of Derrida’s 1967 Voice and Phenomenon3 and Deleuze’s 1966 Bergsonism.4 These two early books are not A NEARLY TOTAL insignificant since, on the one hand, Deleuze AFFINITY (with Guattari) says, as late as 1991 that only Bergson was mature enough for the Spinozist the deleuzian virtual inspiration of immanence,5 and, on the other, Derrida says as late as 1993 that his new concept image versus the of the specter is based on Husserl’s concept of derridean trace1 the noema.6 So, what we are going to see is that, in Voice and Phenomenon, on the basis of Husserl’s phenomenology, Derrida develops the priority of tendency and intuition. We shall even concept of the trace, which he associates with the see a difference in the relation of life and death simulacrum (and which is the basis for his in Derrida and Deleuze. concept of the specter); in Bergsonism, on the It goes without saying that in the examination basis of Bergson’s evolutionism, Deleuze devel- which follows I have exaggerated certain claims ops the concept of the virtual image which he made by Derrida and Deleuze in order to make also associates with the simulacrum (and which is the difference between them stand out as the basis for his concept of the concept). While clearly as possible. I believe that, if we want to my primary focus is going to be these two see “the philosophy of difference” continue, we concepts, the trace and the virtual image, I am need to determine as clearly as possible the going to examine both of these seminal books by different versions of this philosophy: distinguish following four trajectories: destruction versus Derrida from Deleuze; Deleuze from Foucault; deconstruction; purity versus contamination; Derrida from Levinas; Deleuze from Lyotard; fiction understood as the virtual image versus Foucault from Derrida, etc. Without the preci- fiction understood as the trace; and, intuition sion that such a process of distinguishing versus language. On the basis of this comparison provides, “the philosophy of difference” will of Voice and Phenomenon and Bergsonism, we die out with its founders or, worse yet, it will shall see two major differences between Derrida continue as a set of interchangeable cliches. So, I and Deleuze emerge: in Derrida, there is a prior- believe the exaggeration of positions is essential ity of form and language; in Deleuze, there is a today. ISSN 0969-725X print/ISSN 1469-2899 online/00/020059-13 © 2000 Taylor & Francis Ltd and the Editors of Angelaki DOI: 10.1080/09697250020012197 5 9 a nearly total affinity I then the conditions themselves must be charac- terized in new ways. So, in Ideas I, section 70, Before we turn to these trajectories, three Husserl says that essences are clarified through preliminary comments are in order. First, we “free phantasies”; indeed, he says, “fiction makes must recall some of the crucial basic concepts of up the vital element of phenomenology.”14 In phenomenology and Bergsonism. According to Bergson, the virtual is not the possible;15 it is Husserl, there can be no phenomenology without defined by being “real without being actual, ideal the phenomenological reduction;7 in “Philosophy without being abstract,”16 which means that the as a Rigorous Science,” Husserl describes the virtual too can be called a sort of fiction. reduction in this way: in order to return to an Besides these basic concepts of phenomenology “actual beginning,” “all expressions that imply and Bergsonism, we need to keep in mind that thetic existential positings of things in the frame- both the Deleuzian virtual image and the work of space, time, causality, etc. … must in Derridean trace are both memory-images. This is principle be excluded.”8 In Bergsonism, the the case because Deleuze develops the virtual concept parallel to the reduction is “the turn of image on the basis of Bergsonian duration, which experience”; in Matter and Memory, Bergson is essentially defined as memory, and because says, philosophy must return to “experience at its Derrida develops the trace on the basis of the source … above that decisive turn where … it Husserlian living present, in particular, on the becomes properly human experience.”9 Both the basis of the retentional phase or the primary phenomenological reduction and the turn of expe- memory phase of the living present. So, both the rience imply the reduction of transcendence to virtual image and the trace refer to a past and immanence. If transcendence traditionally means more precisely to a past which has never been atemporal truth, then the return to immanence present. The analysis of the four trajectories means a return to temporal experience. Thus, in therefore really amount to comparison of memory phenomenology we have the living present as the in Derrida and Deleuze. absolute form of all experience10 and in The third preliminary comment concerns Bergsonism we have duration as the absolute Heidegger. While everyone knows that Derrida tendency of life.11 If duration and the living has maintained a continuous debate with present insofar as absolute are the transcendental Heidegger’s philosophy since at least 1968 with (but not transcendent) conditions of all experi- the publication of “Ousia and Gramme,” no one ence, they cannot be identical to the experiences even seems to associate Deleuze with Heidegger. they condition. So, they must somehow be differ- I think this is a mistake. On the one hand, if ent. In his lectures on phenomenological psychol- anything the last century – the twentieth – will ogy, Husserl differentiates between psychological probably not be known as Deleuzian or Derridean experience and transcendental experience in or Foucaultian, but as Heideggerian. It is impos- terms of what he calls a “parallelism,” but this sible to underestimate the influence that parallelism is such that there is a perfect “conceal- Heidegger has exerted in all areas including, and ment” of the transcendental in the psychologi- especially, analytic philosophy. So, to refuse to cal.12 The Bergsonian concept equivalent to this bring Deleuze’s thought into confrontation with is difference in nature; in Time and Free Will, that of Heidegger will almost certainly diminish Bergson establishes a difference in nature his greatness. On the other hand – just to take one between psychological life and matter, but example – if one charts the occurrences of psychological life itself differs in nature with itself Heidegger’s name in Difference and Repetition, to the point where it evolves into matter.13 one will see that it occurs within the most impor- Compared to the philosophical tradition, the tant discussions. Indeed the first proper name concepts of parallelism and difference in nature mentioned in Difference and Repetition is that of are new kinds of differences. So, if transcendental Heidegger. With Heidegger in mind, let us now conditions can only be differentiated from the turn to the first trajectory: destruction versus experiences they condition in these new ways, deconstruction. 6 0 lawlor II coincide with what Deleuze calls a simulacrum which is related to the virtual image. Already Both “deconstruction” and “destruction” come they seem to form a sort of opposition because from Heidegger. “Deconstruction,” however, has Derrida’s deconstruction contaminates the meta- become synonymous with Derrida.17 In contrast, physics of presence with the non-presence of the Deleuze never uses the term “deconstruction”; trace, while Deleuze’s destruction purifies but, he uses occasionally the term “destruc- Platonism with the presence of the virtual tion.”18 The issue between Derridean decon- image.23 struction and Deleuzian destruction lies in the target of these practices. When Deleuze speaks of III destruction, he never uses Derrida’s phrase, “the metaphysics of presence”; instead, he speaks of This opposition between contamination and “the destruction of Platonism.” These two terms purity is the second trajectory I would like to – “the metaphysics of presence” and “Platonism” follow. When Deleuze qualifies certain terms as – coincide in that both terms refer to the tradi- “pure,”24 he is using the word “pure” in a sense tional philosophical conception of the origin of which derives from Bergson. Deleuze explains the world, ideas for example, as atemporal; “the Bergson’s well-known “obsession” with the pure destruction of Platonism” or “the deconstruction (BER 12/22) in terms of Bergson’s appropriation of the metaphysics of presence” then would be a of Plato’s method of division (BER 11/22).25 For critique of this conception of ideas, which places Bergson, it is the job of philosophy to divide the them back into temporal experience. But, the badly composed mixtures with which experience coincidence between the terms does not extend presents us in fact (BER 11–12/22). We divide a beyond this temporal critique.19 On the one factual mixture badly, for Bergson, if we make a hand, Derrida defines presence as proximity (VP quantitative difference between time and space, 83–84/75); this definition of presence as proxim- which thereby turns time into a difference of ity implies that the deconstruction of the meta- degree of space.
Recommended publications
  • Ontotheology? Understanding Heidegger’S Destruktion of Metaphysics* Iain Thomson
    T E D U L G O E R · Internationa l Journal o f Philo sophical Studies Vol.8(3), 297–327; · T a p y u lo o r Gr & Fr ancis Ontotheology? Understanding Heidegger’s Destruktion of Metaphysics* Iain Thomson Abstract Heidegger’s Destruktion of the metaphysical tradition leads him to the view that all Western metaphysical systems make foundational claims best understood as ‘ontotheological’. Metaphysics establishes the conceptual parameters of intelligibility by ontologically grounding and theologically legitimating our changing historical sense of what is. By rst elucidating and then problematizing Heidegger’s claim that all Western metaphysics shares this ontotheological structure, I reconstruct the most important components of the original and provocative account of the history of metaphysics that Heidegger gives in support of his idiosyncratic understanding of metaphysics. Arguing that this historical narrative generates the critical force of Heidegger’s larger philosophical project (namely, his attempt to nd a path beyond our own nihilistic Nietzschean age), I conclude by briey showing how Heidegger’s return to the inception of Western metaphysics allows him to uncover two important aspects of Being’s pre-metaphysical phenomeno- logical self-manifestation, aspects which have long been buried beneath the metaphysical tradition but which are crucial to Heidegger’s attempt to move beyond our late-modern, Nietzschean impasse. Keywords: Heidegger; ontotheology; metaphysics; deconstruction; Nietzsche; nihilism Upon hearing the expression ‘ontotheology’, many philosophers start looking for the door. Those who do not may know that it was under the title of this ‘distasteful neologism’ (for which we have Kant to thank)1 that the later Heidegger elaborated his seemingly ruthless critique of Western metaphysics.
    [Show full text]
  • A Critique of the Metaphysics of Presence Peter Eisenman
    Lateness: A Critique of the Metaphysics of Presence Peter Eisenman Colin Rowe used to say that one of the problems with architectural thought was that it saw itself in a state of perpetual crisis. Always focusing on the latest problem or issue, architecture was said to obey a crisis mentality, an attitude partly fueled by nostalgia for an impossible avant-garde and partly by the received notion that archi- tecture was actually about solving problems. But as Rowe also would have said, permanent crisis is no crisis at all. For many historians, crisis is part of an historical cycle. In his book Krisis. Saggio sulla crisi del pensiero negativo da Nietzsche a Wittgenstein (1976), the philoso- pher Massimo Cacciari suggests that a crucial change had taken place in the way modernity was perceived. This rupture, he argued, was a "crisis of foundations," which signaled the end of classical rationality and dialectics in philosophy. He suggested that a crisis of dialectical problem of the limit; it projects the crisis of techniques synthesis in fact underlay the history of the modern already given." "The real problem is how to project a phase of contemporary development. Cacciari's crisis of criticism capable of putting itself into crisis by putting dialectical synthesis opens architecture to the synthetic into crisis the real." In his terms, the historical "project" project. In another interpretation, Manfredo Tafuri saw is an open discursive construct. Rather than producing a the idea of crisis as productive. Tafuri considered history linear narrative of history, the crisis provoked by criticism as a project of crisis, in that historical work, i.e.
    [Show full text]
  • 5 Derrida's Critique of Husserl and the Philosophy
    5 DERRIDA’S CRITIQUE OF HUSSERL AND THE PHILOSOPHY OF PRESENCE David B. Allison* Now would be the time to reject the myths of inductivity and of the Wesenschau, which are transmitted, as points of honor, from generation to generation. ...Am I primitively the power to contemplate, a pure look which fixes the things in their temporal and local place and the essences in an invisible heaven; am I this ray of knowing that would have to 1 arise from nowhere? SÍNTESE – O autor reexamina a crítica de Derrida ABSTRACT – The author reexamines Derrida’s à fenomenologia de Husserl de forma a mostrar critique of Husserl’s phenomenology, so as to como a sua coerência estrutural emerge não show how its structural coherency arises not so tanto de uma redução a uma doutrina particular, much from the reduction to a particular doctrine, mas antes das exigências de uma concepção but rather from the demands of a unitary concep- unitária, especificamente impostas pelas deter- tion, specifically from the demands imposed by minações epistemológicas e metafísicas da the epistemological and metaphysical determina- presença. tions of presence. PALAVRAS-CHAVE – Desconstrução. Derrida. KEY WORDS – Deconstruction. Derrida. Husserl. Fenomenologia. Husserl. Presença. Significado. Meaning. Phenomenology. Presence. * Doutor. Professor, State University of New York, Stony Brook, EUA. 1 Maurice Merleau-Ponty, Le Visible et l’invisible (Paris: Editions Gallimard, 1964), Eng. tr., Alphonso Lingis, The Visible and the Invisible (Evanston: Northwestern University Press, 1968). pp. 113-116. VERITAS Porto Alegre v. 50 n. 1 Março 2005 p. 89-99 It is practically a truism to say that most of Husserl’s commentators have in- sisted on the rigorously systematic character of his writings.
    [Show full text]
  • 2012 SPEP Program (Rochester
    SOCIETY FOR PHENOMENOLOGY AND EXISTENTIAL PHILOSOPHY Executive Co-Directors Anthony Steinbock, Southern Illinois University Carbondale Amy Allen, Dartmouth College Executive Committee Amy Allen, Dartmouth College Alia Al-Saji, McGill University Fred Evans, Duquesne University Brian Schroeder, Rochester Institute of Technology Anthony Steinbock, Southern Illinois University Carbondale Shannon Mussett, Utah Valley University, Secretary-Treasurer Graduate Assistant Christopher C. Paone, Southern Illinois University Carbondale Advisory Book Selection Committee Shannon Winnubst, The Ohio State University, Chair Ann V. Murphy, Fordham University Brad Elliott Stone, Loyola Marymount University Adrian Johnston, University of New Mexico David Carr, Emory University Brent Adkins, Roanoke College Daniela Vallega-Neu, Univeristy of Oregon James D. Hatley, Salisbury University Advocacy Committee Robin James, University of North Carolina Charlotte, Chair Peter Gratton, Memorial University of Newfoundland Gail Weiss, George Washington University Committee on the Status of Women Laura Hengehold, Case Western Reserve University, Chair Shannon Sullivan, The Pennsylvania State University Elaine Miller, Miami University of Ohio Racial and Ethnic Diversity Committee Falguni Sheth, Hampshire College, Chair Hernando Estévez, John Jay College/CUNY Devonya Havis, Canisius College LGBTQ Advocacy Committee Robert Vallier, Institut d’Études Politiques, Chair William Wilkerson, University of Alabama Huntsville Mary Bloodsworth-Lugo, Washington State University Webmaster Christopher P. Long, The Pennsylvania State University Local Arrangements Contacts Brian Schroeder, local contact and organizer, [email protected] Scott Campbell, book exhibit coordinator, [email protected] Lindsey Johnson, student volunteer coordinator, [email protected] All SPEP sessions will be held at the Rochester Riverside Convention Center (RRCC) on 123 East Main St., Rochester, NY. The RRCC is adjacent to the host hotel, the Hyatt Regency Rochester, to which it is connected by an enclosed skyway.
    [Show full text]
  • Postmodernist Gibberish: Derrida Dumbfounds the Positivists
    New York Journal of Sociology, 2008, Vol. 1, pp. 187-206 NY JS POSTMODERNIST GIBBERISH: DERRIDA DUMBFOUNDS THE POSITIVISTS Ben Agger University of Texas Arlington Jacques Derrida (1978), the enfant terrible of Continental philosophy who passed away recently, made many mad: analytical philosophers, positivists in the sciences and social sciences, the right, stupid people generally. That Derrida was brilliant is somewhat beside the point. What is on point is the way he read—texts and indeed the whole western philosophical tradition— aggressively, so much so that we could conclude that Derrida meant that reading is a form of writing. That is one of the main things I take away from his oeuvre. Another is that every text is ‘undecidable,’ that is, it cannot perfectly clarify and ex- haust its topic. This is because every definition needs to be defined, ad infi- nitum. There is no vantage outside of writing from which one can achieve that Archimedean insight about the truth or essence of the world. This rebut- tal of absolutism is extremely maddening to those who pretend apodictic knowledge, especially the gang we sometimes call positivists. To be sure, positivism died within physics by 1905, with Einstein’s first papers on the special theory of relativity. Newton was overthrown, except in the largely American social sciences, where it still prevails, even though there are challengers nibbling at the edges of the mainstream social-science disciplines. Newton only survives in sociology, political science, economics and parts of psychology. It is in these disciplines that Derrida is especially scandalous, although rear-guard actions are also being fought in English by those who dislike ‘the- ory’ and want the great books instead.
    [Show full text]
  • TED TOADVINE Curriculum Vitae Department of Philosophy 1247 W
    TED TOADVINE Curriculum Vitae Department of Philosophy 1247 W. 14th Avenue University of Oregon Eugene, OR 97402 Eugene, OR 97403-1295 Phone: (541) 731-7984 Phone: (541) 346-5554 Email: [email protected] Fax: (541) 346-5544 Revised 27 May 2016 SPECIALIZATION Contemporary continental philosophy, especially phenomenology and post-structuralism Philosophy of nature and environment COMPETENCE Aesthetics, philosophy of ecology, nineteenth-century philosophy, ancient Greek philosophy EDUCATION • Brevet d’Études Françaises, 5ème degré, Institut de Touraine, Tours, France, 2002 • Ph.D. in Philosophy, The University of Memphis, 1996 Contradiction, Expression, and Chiasm: The Development of Intersubjectivity in Maurice Merleau-Ponty Committee: Leonard Lawlor (Director), Robert Bernasconi, Tina Chanter, Mark Timmons, Fred Evans (Duquesne) • M.A. in Philosophy, The University of Memphis, 1995 • B.A. in Philosophy with General Honors, Salisbury University, 1990 ACADEMIC POSITIONS • Professor of Philosophy & Environmental Studies, University of Oregon, 2015– • Research Associate, Environmental Studies Program, Oberlin College, 2015–2016 • Associate Professor of Philosophy and Environmental Studies, University of Oregon, 2009–2015 • Visiting Associate Professor of Environmental Studies, Oberlin College, 2010–2011 • Assistant Professor of Philosophy and Environmental Studies, University of Oregon, 2003–2009 • Assistant Professor of Philosophy, Emporia State University, 1998–2003 • Visiting Professor of Philosophy, Kalamazoo College, 1997–1998 ADMINISTRATIVE
    [Show full text]
  • An Introduction to Philosophy
    An Introduction to Philosophy W. Russ Payne Bellevue College Copyright (cc by nc 4.0) 2015 W. Russ Payne Permission is granted to copy, distribute and/or modify this document with attribution under the terms of Creative Commons: Attribution Noncommercial 4.0 International or any later version of this license. A copy of the license is found at http://creativecommons.org/licenses/by-nc/4.0/ 1 Contents Introduction ………………………………………………. 3 Chapter 1: What Philosophy Is ………………………….. 5 Chapter 2: How to do Philosophy ………………….……. 11 Chapter 3: Ancient Philosophy ………………….………. 23 Chapter 4: Rationalism ………….………………….……. 38 Chapter 5: Empiricism …………………………………… 50 Chapter 6: Philosophy of Science ………………….…..… 58 Chapter 7: Philosophy of Mind …………………….……. 72 Chapter 8: Love and Happiness …………………….……. 79 Chapter 9: Meta Ethics …………………………………… 94 Chapter 10: Right Action ……………………...…………. 108 Chapter 11: Social Justice …………………………...…… 120 2 Introduction The goal of this text is to present philosophy to newcomers as a living discipline with historical roots. While a few early chapters are historically organized, my goal in the historical chapters is to trace a developmental progression of thought that introduces basic philosophical methods and frames issues that remain relevant today. Later chapters are topically organized. These include philosophy of science and philosophy of mind, areas where philosophy has shown dramatic recent progress. This text concludes with four chapters on ethics, broadly construed. I cover traditional theories of right action in the third of these. Students are first invited first to think about what is good for themselves and their relationships in a chapter of love and happiness. Next a few meta-ethical issues are considered; namely, whether they are moral truths and if so what makes them so.
    [Show full text]
  • Looking for the Political Good: a “Friendly” Encounter Between Aristotle and Jacques Derrida
    Looking for the Political Good: A “Friendly” Encounter Between Aristotle and Jacques Derrida By Pamela Huber BA, MA A thesis submitted to the Faculty of Graduate Studies and Research in partial fulfillment of the requirements for the degree of Doctorate of Philosophy Department of Political Science Carleton University Ottawa, Ontario Canada © 2006 by Pamela Huber Reproduced with permission of the copyright owner. Further reproduction prohibited without permission. Library and Bibliotheque et Archives Canada Archives Canada Published Heritage Direction du Branch Patrimoine de I'edition 395 Wellington Street 395, rue Wellington Ottawa ON K1A 0N4 Ottawa ON K1A 0N4 Canada Canada Your file Votre reference ISBN: 978-0-494-16669-7 Our file Notre reference ISBN: 978-0-494-16669-7 NOTICE: AVIS: The author has granted a non­ L'auteur a accorde une licence non exclusive exclusive license allowing Library permettant a la Bibliotheque et Archives and Archives Canada to reproduce,Canada de reproduire, publier, archiver, publish, archive, preserve, conserve,sauvegarder, conserver, transmettre au public communicate to the public by par telecommunication ou par I'lnternet, preter, telecommunication or on the Internet,distribuer et vendre des theses partout dans loan, distribute and sell theses le monde, a des fins commerciales ou autres, worldwide, for commercial or non­ sur support microforme, papier, electronique commercial purposes, in microform,et/ou autres formats. paper, electronic and/or any other formats. The author retains copyright L'auteur conserve la propriete du droit d'auteur ownership and moral rights in et des droits moraux qui protege cette these. this thesis. Neither the thesis Ni la these ni des extraits substantiels de nor substantial extracts from it celle-ci ne doivent etre imprimes ou autrement may be printed or otherwise reproduits sans son autorisation.
    [Show full text]
  • Overturning the Paradigm of Identity with Gilles Deleuze's Differential
    A Thesis entitled Difference Over Identity: Overturning the Paradigm of Identity With Gilles Deleuze’s Differential Ontology by Matthew G. Eckel Submitted to the Graduate Faculty as partial fulfillment of the requirements for the Master of Arts Degree in Philosophy Dr. Ammon Allred, Committee Chair Dr. Benjamin Grazzini, Committee Member Dr. Benjamin Pryor, Committee Member Dr. Patricia R. Komuniecki, Dean College of Graduate Studies The University of Toledo May 2014 An Abstract of Difference Over Identity: Overturning the Paradigm of Identity With Gilles Deleuze’s Differential Ontology by Matthew G. Eckel Submitted to the Graduate Faculty as partial fulfillment of the requirements for the Master of Arts Degree in Philosophy The University of Toledo May 2014 Taking Gilles Deleuze to be a philosopher who is most concerned with articulating a ‘philosophy of difference’, Deleuze’s thought represents a fundamental shift in the history of philosophy, a shift which asserts ontological difference as independent of any prior ontological identity, even going as far as suggesting that identity is only possible when grounded by difference. Deleuze reconstructs a ‘minor’ history of philosophy, mobilizing thinkers from Spinoza and Nietzsche to Duns Scotus and Bergson, in his attempt to assert that philosophy has always been, underneath its canonical manifestations, a project concerned with ontology, and that ontological difference deserves the kind of philosophical attention, and privilege, which ontological identity has been given since Aristotle.
    [Show full text]
  • Derrida's Objection to the Metaphysical Tradition
    CORE Metadata, citation and similar papers at core.ac.uk Provided by Scholarship@Claremont Claremont Colleges Scholarship @ Claremont CMC Senior Theses CMC Student Scholarship 2015 Derrida's Objection To The etM aphysical Tradition Christopher A. Wheat Claremont McKenna College Recommended Citation Wheat, Christopher A., "Derrida's Objection To The eM taphysical Tradition" (2015). CMC Senior Theses. Paper 1188. http://scholarship.claremont.edu/cmc_theses/1188 This Open Access Senior Thesis is brought to you by Scholarship@Claremont. It has been accepted for inclusion in this collection by an authorized administrator. For more information, please contact [email protected]. Claremont McKenna College Derrida’s Objection to the Metaphysical Tradition Submitted to Prof. James Kreines And Dean Nicholas Warner By Christopher Wheat For Senior Thesis Spring 2015 4/27/15 Table of Contents: Acknowledgements……………………………………………………………………2 Abstract………………………………………………………………………………..3 Introduction……………………………………………………………………………4 The Metaphysical Tradition…………………………………………………………...6 Derrida’s Objection…………………………………………………………………..16 Metaphysics Given the Abandonment of the Metaphysical Tradition………………26 Conclusion………………………………………………….………………………..31 Bibliography…………………………………………………………..……………..33 1 Acknowledgements: I would like to thank Professor Kreines for his generous assistance in my thesis and initial research of deconstruction, and for helping to nurture my interest in philosophy over the course of my college career. I would also like to thank Professor Rajczi, Professor Schroeder, Professor Kind, Professor Kincaid, and Professor Gaitskill. In addition to my professors, my friends and family have supported and influenced me in ways I could never begin to repay them for, and hope that this thesis is only a small reflection of what they have taught me. 2 Abstract Derrida’s deconstruction of the philosophic tradition shows us not only the importance of pursuit of knowledge, but also the importance of questioning the assumptions on which such a pursuit is based.
    [Show full text]
  • Jacques Derrida and the End of Christianity
    Open Theology 2019; 5: 116–124 Phenomenology of Religious Experience III: Visuality, Imagination, and the Lifeworld Martin Koci* Transforming Representation: Jacques Derrida and the End of Christianity https://doi.org/10.1515/opth-2019-0018 Received March 15, 2019; accepted June 12, 2019 Abstract: The central question of this paper revolves around the problem of representation. Following Jacques Derrida and his critique of representation, this paper will interconnect two, at first sight distinct, topics: Christianity and the world of media. For Derrida, Christianity stands behind our common understanding of representation, whereas the media are the major driving force of any representation today. The central argument of this paper is to unfold this link between Christianity and representation and thus to elaborate on the idea of representation in relation to the end of Christianity announced by Derrida. Firstly, I will review Derrida’s account on the logic of representation. Derrida deems Christianity to be responsible for the logic of representation discernible in today’s media world and offers a devastating critique of the concept. Secondly, I will contextualize Derrida’s approach by pointing out the tension between the modern and postmodern perspectives on representation. Thirdly, I will return to a close reading of Derrida. Fourthly, I will offer a critique of Derrida’s critique and will look further at the possible meanings of ‘the end of Christianity.’ Keywords: Jacques Derrida; Christianity; Representation; Modernity; Postmodernity; Media The central problem of this paper is the crisis of representation. This crisis can take many forms and the concept of representation as such can be used in various contexts.
    [Show full text]
  • Habermas's Politics of Rational Freedom: Navigating the History Of
    This is a repository copy of Habermas’s politics of rational freedom: Navigating the history of philosophy between faith and knowledge. White Rose Research Online URL for this paper: https://eprints.whiterose.ac.uk/162100/ Version: Accepted Version Article: Verovšek, P.J. (2020) Habermas’s politics of rational freedom: Navigating the history of philosophy between faith and knowledge. Analyse & Kritik, 42 (1). pp. 191-218. ISSN 0171-5860 https://doi.org/10.1515/auk-2020-0008 © 2020 Walter de Gruyter GmbH. This is an author-produced version of a paper subsequently published in Analyse and Kritik. Uploaded in accordance with the publisher's self-archiving policy. Reuse Items deposited in White Rose Research Online are protected by copyright, with all rights reserved unless indicated otherwise. They may be downloaded and/or printed for private study, or other acts as permitted by national copyright laws. The publisher or other rights holders may allow further reproduction and re-use of the full text version. This is indicated by the licence information on the White Rose Research Online record for the item. Takedown If you consider content in White Rose Research Online to be in breach of UK law, please notify us by emailing [email protected] including the URL of the record and the reason for the withdrawal request. [email protected] https://eprints.whiterose.ac.uk/ Habermas’s Politics of Rational Freedom: Navigating the History of Philosophy between Faith and Knowledge* Peter J. Verovšek† Department of Politics & International Relations University of Sheffield Elmfield, Northumberland Road Sheffield, S10 2TU United Kingdom [email protected] ABSTRACT Despite his hostility to religion in his early career, since the turn of the century Habermas has devoted his research to the relationship between faith and knowledge.
    [Show full text]