This Thesis Has Been Submitted in Fulfilment of the Requirements for a Postgraduate Degree (E.G. Phd, Mphil, Dclinpsychol) at the University of Edinburgh

Total Page:16

File Type:pdf, Size:1020Kb

This Thesis Has Been Submitted in Fulfilment of the Requirements for a Postgraduate Degree (E.G. Phd, Mphil, Dclinpsychol) at the University of Edinburgh This thesis has been submitted in fulfilment of the requirements for a postgraduate degree (e.g. PhD, MPhil, DClinPsychol) at the University of Edinburgh. Please note the following terms and conditions of use: • This work is protected by copyright and other intellectual property rights, which are retained by the thesis author, unless otherwise stated. • A copy can be downloaded for personal non-commercial research or study, without prior permission or charge. • This thesis cannot be reproduced or quoted extensively from without first obtaining permission in writing from the author. • The content must not be changed in any way or sold commercially in any format or medium without the formal permission of the author. • When referring to this work, full bibliographic details including the author, title, awarding institution and date of the thesis must be given. PLATO’S BOND OF LOVE: ERÔS AS PARTICIPATION IN BEAUTY Lauren Patricia Wenden Ware Thesis submitted for the degree of Doctor of Philosophy Department of Philosophy 2014 ABSTRACT In his dialogues, Plato presents different ways in which to understand the relation between Forms and particulars. In the Symposium, we are presented with yet another, hitherto unidentified Form-particular relation: the relation is Love (Erôs), which binds together Form and particular in a generative manner, fulfilling all the metaphysical requirements of the individual’s qualification by participation. Love in relation to the beautiful motivates human action to desire for knowledge of the Form, resulting in the lover actively cultivating and bringing into being new beauty in the world, and in herself. Chapters 1 and 2 of this thesis offer a survey of the arguments and examples Plato puts forward in the text of the corpus regarding the nature of Forms and the nature of participation, alongside a framework of the traditional interpretations of these two Platonic concepts in the literature. Chapter 3 turns to a close examination of Erôs in the Symposium, arguing that the love Plato presents in this dialogue is of a different sort than appetitive emotion. It is an aesthetic and intellectual attraction, capable of stimulating cognitive achievement. Erôs, however, does not stop there. The lover is led not only to contemplation of beauty, but to the generation of beauty, which is the subject of Chapter 4. The emotive-turn-to-cognitive relation of Erôs, I argue, is the clearest picture Plato paints of how possession of properties can be explained through participation in Forms. Erôs leads the lover to produce beauty in the world and in the soul, which explains how love in relation to the beautiful can lead to becoming beautiful. The object of love is the generation of beauty, the mortal mechanism of participation in the Form by which the lover herself becomes beautiful. Finally, Chapter 5 focusses on beauty itself and its role in moral education. Beauty, for Plato, is required for creative generation and can be understood as a uniquely powerful virtue of soul. DECLARATION I hereby declare that this thesis has been composed by me (the candidate); and that the work of which it is a record is entirely my own, except where otherwise indicated by means of quotation, reference, and acknowledgement. The work has not been accepted in any previous application for any other degree or professional qualification. Signed: Date: 8th April, 2014 TABLE OF CONTENTS ACKNOWLEDGEMENTS INTRODUCTION . 1 I. Aims and methodology of the thesis 6 II. Orientation to the subject 8 III. Orientation to the thesis 12 III.a. Statement of terminology 12 III.b. Limitations 15 IV. Overview of chapters 17 CHAPTER 1: THE NATURE OF FORMS . 19 I. Meno 20 II. Phaedo 21 II.a. Deadly asceticism (65c-67a) 22 II.b. The argument from recollection (72e-78b) 23 II.c. The affinity argument (78b-84b) 26 II.d. The argument from the Form of life (95a-107b) 27 III. Republic 30 III.a. 449a-480a 31 III.b. 484a-511e 33 III.c. 514a-541b 39 IV. Cratylus 41 V. Phaedrus 42 VI. Parmenides 43 VII. Theaetetus 44 VIII. Timaeus 45 IX. Philebus 46 X. Symposium 47 CHAPTER 2: THE NATURE OF PARTICIPATION . 53 I. Review of participation in the Platonic corpus 54 I.a. Phaedo 54 I.b. Parmenides 56 I.c. Phaedrus 57 I.d. Timaeus 57 I.e. Republic 58 I.f. Sophist 59 I.g. Protagoras 60 I.h. Laws 61 II. Review of participation in the literature 61 II.a. Original to copy 64 II.b. Contagion agent to phenomenon 66 II.c. Source to similar image 68 II.d. Binding causal power 69 CHAPTER 3: ERÔS IN THE SYMPOSIUM . 71 I. The truth about Erôs 72 I.a. Diotima and the origin of Love 72 I.b. The ladder of love 78 I.c. Who loves whom? 82 I.c.1. Philosopher loves the Form of beauty, beauty begets 83 I.c.2. Philosopher loves a beautiful particular, begets in the mind of the beloved 86 I.c.3. Philosopher loves a beautiful beloved, begets virtue in herself 92 I.c.4. Philosopher inspired by beauty, begets virtue in the world and in the soul 93 II. Erôs is distinctly cognitive 95 III. Objects and aims of Erôs 102 III.a. Love is not of beauty, but of bringing to birth in beauty 102 III.b. No shifting goalposts: Socrates presents a consistent object of Erôs 104 III.c. Objects of love compared to objects of knowledge 108 IV. In defence of love 111 IV.a. Possessive lovers 111 IV.b. Possession does not entail the exclusivist’s reading 114 V. Chapter conclusion 128 CHAPTER 4: PARTICIPATION IN THE SYMPOSIUM . 130 I. Knowledge leads to generation 132 I.a. The explanatory power of an erotic education 132 I.b. Education grounds generative activity 136 II. Generation: Becoming beautiful by creating beauty 141 II.a. What is generated mirrors its cause 142 II.b. The beauty of virtue 147 III. Participation by generation 150 III.a. Love is a bond, uniting mortal and divine 150 III.b. Love is a bond, uniting different ontological types 154 III.c. The bond of love unites the two through generation 156 IV. Objections 160 V. Mortal immortality is achieved through indissolubility 163 V.a. The rival theories: External immortalities 163 V.b. The sameness of the Form 167 VI. Influence in the tradition: Aristotle on predication, and the PM 171 VII. Chapter conclusion 175 CHAPTER 5: THE VIRTUE OF BEAUTY . 177 I. Beauty’s role in generation 178 I.a. Beauty, Καλλονή, καλός, and κάλλος 178 I.b. Why is generation only in the beautiful? 181 II. Implications for moral education 183 II.a. Engaging the emotions in education 184 II.b. Moral education review 185 II.c. Platonic virtue ethics 187 II.d. Curriculum: Beauty in the classroom 189 III. Chapter conclusion 198 CONCLUSION . 199 APPENDIX . 201 “What good is love?” Analytic Teaching and Philosophical Praxis 34:2 (2014), 57-73 . 202 BIBLIOGRAPHY . 219 ACKNOWLEDGEMENTS My study of Plato’s philosophy is due chiefly to the passion and dedication of brilliant teachers. A profound debt is owed to Cal Townsend and John Dyck, whose instruction and great personal mentorship during my undergraduate honours thesis set the trajectory for this work. Jerry Santas has been incredibly kind to take on the role of external supervisor for my doctoral research; and Don Morrison and Andrew Mason enabled me to bring these ideas to life. I wish further to express my very deep appreciation to Dory Scaltsas, my primary supervisor. His peerless Socratic cross- examinations allowed me to explore and organise my hypotheses under scrutiny, and his faith in me instilled a confidence to take risks in defending them. Material from this thesis has been presented in Ancient Olympia, Asilomar, Athens, Cambridge, Durham, Edmonton, Heraklion, Langley, London, Newcastle, Oxford, Pisa, San Francisco, and St Andrews; for BBC Scotland and educational media; and at numerous workshops and seminars in Edinburgh. I am grateful to the audiences and participants at all these events for invaluable questions and discussions. Special thanks are due to Sarah Broadie, Jamie Dow, Michael Griffin, Jay Kennedy, David Konstan, Alexander Nehamas, and Frisbee Sheffield. Catherine Rowett has been a continuous source of encouragement and inspiration. The Athens of the North lives up to its namesake in the much-loved reading groups of the Philosophy and Classics departments at Edinburgh. My fellow students have greatly challenged and cheered me, and I especially thank Jane Orton for countless hours of dialogue. I wish my own students could know how much they’ve changed my life. Sincere appreciation is due to the following organisations for supporting this project: the Social Sciences and Humanities Research Council of Canada, for a Doctoral Fellowship; the University of Edinburgh, for tuition; the School of Philosophy, Psychology, and Language Sciences, for a Shaw Fellowship/Career Development Scholarship and generous research grants; and the Thomas Weidemann Memorial Fund, for funding my classical research travels. I should note that material from Chapter 5 has been published in Analytic Teaching and Philosophical Praxis, and is reproduced in the Appendix with permission from the publisher. I humbly thank my family and friends—who were continually expected to listen to thoughts on the True, the Just, and the Beautiful—for their encouragement, their humour, and their patience. I am beholden to my sister, Kim, and my parents, Craig and Lynda Hosty, whose unwavering love and support has enabled me to flourish. My enduring gratitude goes to Brandon Ware, my greatest champion. The “great sea of beauty” I’ve witnessed in this endeavour counts among it such love as even the most oceanic of hearts re-reckons its ability to hold.
Recommended publications
  • PLATO's SYMPOSIUM J
    50 ccn~ PLATO'S SYMPOSIUM j - - -- ________j e Library of Liberal Arts PLATO'S SYMPOSIUM Tran lated by BENJAMIN JOWETT With an Introduction by FULTON H. ANDERSON Professor of Philosophy, University of Toronto THE LIBERAL ARTS PRESS NEW YORK CONTENTS SELECTED BIBLIOGRAPHY .. .... ................................... ......... ... ........... 6 EDITOR'S INTRODUCTION ................... ............................................. 7 SYMPOSIUM APOLLODORUS 13 THE SPEECH OF PHAEDRUS ...... .......................... .......................... .. 19 THE SPEECH OF PAU ANIAS ................. ... ................................. ... .. 21 THE SPEECH OF ERYXIMACHUS 27 THE SPEECH OF ARISTOPHAN E .. ............................... .................. 30 THE SPEECH OF AGATHON ............ .............................................. .. 35 THE SPEECH OF SocRATES ................................ .. ................... ..... .. 39 THE SPEECH OF ALCIBIADES ................. ............... ... ........... ...... .... .. 55 8 PLATO INTROD CTION 9 crescendo, and culminates in the report by Socrates on wi dom and epistemology, upon all of which the Symposium ha bearing, learned from the "wi e" woman Diotima. are intertwined, we m ay set down briefly a few of the more general The dialogue i a "reported" one. Plato himself could not have principles which are to be found in it author's many-sided thought. been present at the original party. (What went on there was told The human soul, a cording to Plato, is es entially in motion. time and time again about Athens.) He was a mere boy when it It is li fe and the integration of living functions. A dead soul is a con­ took place. Nor could the narrator Apollodorus have been a guest; _lladiction in terms. Man throughout his whole nature is erotically he was too young at the time. The latter got his report from motivated. His "love" or desire i manifest in three mutually in­ Aristodemus, a guest at the banquet.
    [Show full text]
  • The Roles of Solon in Plato's Dialogues
    The Roles of Solon in Plato’s Dialogues Dissertation Presented in partial fulfillment of the requirements for the Degree Doctor of Philosophy in the Graduate School of The Ohio State University By Samuel Ortencio Flores, M.A. Graduate Program in Greek and Latin The Ohio State University 2013 Dissertation Committee: Bruce Heiden, Advisor Anthony Kaldellis Richard Fletcher Greg Anderson Copyrighy by Samuel Ortencio Flores 2013 Abstract This dissertation is a study of Plato’s use and adaptation of an earlier model and tradition of wisdom based on the thought and legacy of the sixth-century archon, legislator, and poet Solon. Solon is cited and/or quoted thirty-four times in Plato’s dialogues, and alluded to many more times. My study shows that these references and allusions have deeper meaning when contextualized within the reception of Solon in the classical period. For Plato, Solon is a rhetorically powerful figure in advancing the relatively new practice of philosophy in Athens. While Solon himself did not adequately establish justice in the city, his legacy provided a model upon which Platonic philosophy could improve. Chapter One surveys the passing references to Solon in the dialogues as an introduction to my chapters on the dialogues in which Solon is a very prominent figure, Timaeus- Critias, Republic, and Laws. Chapter Two examines Critias’ use of his ancestor Solon to establish his own philosophic credentials. Chapter Three suggests that Socrates re- appropriates the aims and themes of Solon’s political poetry for Socratic philosophy. Chapter Four suggests that Solon provides a legislative model which Plato reconstructs in the Laws for the philosopher to supplant the role of legislator in Greek thought.
    [Show full text]
  • Gorgias, Menexenus, Protagoras Edited by Malcolm Schofield Frontmatter More Information
    Cambridge University Press 978-0-521-54600-3 - Plato: Gorgias, Menexenus, Protagoras Edited by Malcolm Schofield Frontmatter More information CAMBRIDGE TEXTS IN THE HISTORY OF POLITICAL THOUGHT PLATO Gorgias, Menexenus, Protagoras © in this web service Cambridge University Press www.cambridge.org Cambridge University Press 978-0-521-54600-3 - Plato: Gorgias, Menexenus, Protagoras Edited by Malcolm Schofield Frontmatter More information CAMBRIDGE TEXTS IN THE HISTORY OF POLITICAL THOUGHT Series editors R AYMOND GEUSS Professor in Philosophy, University of Cambridge Q UENTIN SKINNER Professor of the Humanities, Queen Mary, University of London Cambridge Texts in the History of Political Thought is now firmly estab- lished as the major student textbook series in political theory. It aims to make available to students all the most important texts in the history of western political thought, from ancient Greece to the early twentieth century. All the familiar classic texts will be included, but the series seeks at the same time to enlarge the conventional canon by incorporating an extensive range of less well-known works, many of them never before available in a modern English edition. Wherever possible, texts are published in complete and unabridged form, and translations are specially commissioned for the series. Each vol- ume contains a critical introduction together with chronologies, biographical sketches, a guide to further reading and any necessary glossaries and text- ual apparatus. When completed the series will aim to offer an outline
    [Show full text]
  • Corrupted Platonism in Astrophil and Stella: the Expression of Desire
    Corrupted Platonism in Astrophil and Stella: The Expression of Desire Sonia Hernández Santano UNIVERSIDAD DE HUELVA [email protected] Astrophil’s love for Stella is not the conventional Platonic love of Petrarchist poems. We cannot fully consider him the romantic lover who aspires to a spiritual enjoying of his lady’s virtues and beauty for, though he attempts to represent his feelings according to the parameters of Platonism, he also makes his basest sexual desire flourish in many of the sonnets or songs of Astrophil and Stella. It is not that his begins by being a pure love that progressively degenerates into a blatant expression of his sexual needs due to an increase of his desire. The material nature of his love as opposed to spiritual love is obvious from the very beginning of the sequence. It is, however, a fact that Astrophil does frequently express his amorous feeling by means of Platonic topics such as the correspondence between physical beauty and spiritual virtue, as in sonnet 48 when he refers to Stella’s eyes as “where Virtue is made strong by Beautie’s might” (l. 2) or that he identifies himself with the agonizing lover of Petrarchist sequences who suffers the wounds of Cupid as in sonnet 20: “Fly, fly, my friends, I have my death wound” (l. 1) or with the slave of his beloved as in sonnet 47: “What, have I thus betrayed my libertie?” (l. 1). But the Platonic representation of his love is continually corrupted by frequent ironic allusions to it and to sexual desire.
    [Show full text]
  • Platonic Love for Persons Vlastos (1973) Raises a Famous Critique of Plato's Account of Love in the Symposium. the Highest
    Platonic Love for Persons Vlastos (1973) raises a famous critique of Plato’s account of love in the Symposium. The highest form of erōs, as it is described in Diotima’s scala amoris, is not for any particular individual but takes as its object the form of beauty itself (211a1-d1). Furthermore, erōs for an individual features in this account purely as stepping-stone to the philosopher’s comprehension of beauty. Not only is it difficult to understand what this impersonal erōs is, but it is difficult to understand why Plato thinks it is such an important part of a life well lived. So puzzled is Vlastos by the impersonality of erōs on this account that he ultimately finds it lacking in “kindness, tenderness, compassion,” and “respect for the integrity of the beloved” (30). What is missing, he claims, is an account of love for “persons who are themselves worthy of love for their own sake.” Since the publication of Vlastos’ critique, many have attempted to save Plato’s account by showing that love of particular individuals is consistent with or important to the philosopher’s pursuit of beauty (i.e. Price 1981, Nehamas 2007, Sheffield 2009, Urstad 2010). In other words, scholars have attempted to show that the impersonal love of the Symposium is not so impersonal after all. This paper takes a somewhat different approach; it argues that the impersonal nature of erōs in the Symposium is consistent with an overarching lack of esteem for personal relationships elsewhere in the dialogues. In the Crito, for example, Socrates appears largely unconcerned with the care of his sons, ranking his obligation to them well behind his duty to the laws (54b2-3).
    [Show full text]
  • The Historicity of Plato's Apology of Socrates
    Loyola University Chicago Loyola eCommons Master's Theses Theses and Dissertations 1946 The Historicity of Plato's Apology of Socrates David J. Bowman Loyola University Chicago Follow this and additional works at: https://ecommons.luc.edu/luc_theses Part of the Classical Literature and Philology Commons Recommended Citation Bowman, David J., "The Historicity of Plato's Apology of Socrates" (1946). Master's Theses. 61. https://ecommons.luc.edu/luc_theses/61 This Thesis is brought to you for free and open access by the Theses and Dissertations at Loyola eCommons. It has been accepted for inclusion in Master's Theses by an authorized administrator of Loyola eCommons. For more information, please contact [email protected]. This work is licensed under a Creative Commons Attribution-Noncommercial-No Derivative Works 3.0 License. Copyright © 1946 David J. Bowman !HE HISTORICITY OP PLATO'S APOLOGY OF SOCRATES BY DA.VID J. BOWJWf~ S.J• .l. !BESIS SUBMITTED Ilf PARTIAL FULFILIJIE.NT OF THB: R}gQUIRE'IIENTS POR THE DEGREE OF IIA.STER OF ARTS Ill LOYOLA UlfiVERSITY JULY 1946 -VI'fA. David J. Bowman; S.J•• was born in Oak Park, Ill1no1a, on Ma7 20, 1919. Atter b!a eleaentar7 education at Ascension School# in Oak Park, he attended LoJola AcademJ ot Chicago, graduat1DS .from. there in June, 1937. On September 1, 1937# he entered the Sacred Heart Novitiate ot the SocietJ ot Jesus at Milford~ Ohio. Por the tour Jear• he spent there, he was aoademicallJ connected with Xavier Univeraitr, Cincinnati, Ohio. In August ot 1941 he tranaterred to West Baden College o.f Lorol& Universit7, Obicago, and received the degree ot Bachelor o.f Arts with a major in Greek in Deo.aber, 1941.
    [Show full text]
  • Plato's Symposium: the Ethics of Desire
    Plato’s Symposium: The Ethics of Desire FRISBEE C. C. SHEFFIELD 1 Contents Introduction 1 1. Ero¯s and the Good Life 8 2. Socrates’ Speech: The Nature of Ero¯s 40 3. Socrates’ Speech: The Aim of Ero¯s 75 4. Socrates’ Speech: The Activity of Ero¯s 112 5. Socrates’ Speech: Concern for Others? 154 6. ‘Nothing to do with Human AVairs?’: Alcibiades’ Response to Socrates 183 7. Shadow Lovers: The Symposiasts and Socrates 207 Conclusion 225 Appendix : Socratic Psychology or Tripartition in the Symposium? 227 References 240 Index 249 Introduction In the Symposium Plato invites us to imagine the following scene: A pair of lovers are locked in an embrace and Hephaestus stands over them with his mending tools asking: ‘What is it that you human beings really want from each other?’ The lovers are puzzled, and he asks them again: ‘Is this your heart’s desire, for the two of you to become parts of the same whole, and never to separate, day or night? If that is your desire, I’d like to weld you together and join you into something whole, so that the two of you are made into one. Look at your love and see if this is what you desire: wouldn’t this be all that you want?’ No one, apparently, would think that mere sex is the reason each lover takes such deep joy in being with the other. The soul of each lover apparently longs for something else, but cannot say what it is. The beloved holds out the promise of something beyond itself, but that something lovers are unable to name.1 Hephaestus’ question is a pressing one.
    [Show full text]
  • The Phaedo by Plato
    Selections from The Phaedo by Plato The Death of Scorates, David, 1787. [The Phaedo tells the story of Socrates’ final moments spent, as one would expect, in philosophical dialogue with his friends. The main subject of the dialogue is the immortality of the soul. The Phaedo is one of Plato’s middle period dialogues and, as such, reveals much of Plato’s own philosophy. In the arguments Socrates puts forth for the immortality of the soul we find a clear exposition of both Plato’s metaphysics as well as his epistemology. In the first section we find Socrates explaining to his friends why a true philosopher does not fear death. Philosophy is here described as a preparation for death.] ECHECRATES: Were you there with Socrates yourself, Phaedo, when he was executed, or 57 did you hear about it from somebody else? PHAEDO: No, I was there myself, Echecrates. ECHECRATES: Then what did the master say before he died, and how did he meet his end? I should very much like to know. None of the people in Phlius go to Athens much in these days, and it is a long time since we had any visitor from there who could give us any definite b information, except that he was executed by drinking hemlock. Nobody could tell us anything more than that. PHAEDO: Then haven't you even heard how his trial went? 58 ECHECRATES: Yes, someone told us about that, and we were surprised because there was obviously a long interval between it and the execution. How was that, Phaedo? PHAEDO: A fortunate coincidence, Echecrates.
    [Show full text]
  • On the Arrangement of the Platonic Dialogues
    Ryan C. Fowler 25th Hour On the Arrangement of the Platonic Dialogues I. Thrasyllus a. Diogenes Laertius (D.L.), Lives and Opinions of Eminent Philosophers 3.56: “But, just as long ago in tragedy the chorus was the only actor, and afterwards, in order to give the chorus breathing space, Thespis devised a single actor, Aeschylus a second, Sophocles a third, and thus tragedy was completed, so too with philosophy: in early times it discoursed on one subject only, namely physics, then Socrates added the second subject, ethics, and Plato the third, dialectics, and so brought philosophy to perfection. Thrasyllus says that he [Plato] published his dialogues in tetralogies, like those of the tragic poets. Thus they contended with four plays at the Dionysia, the Lenaea, the Panathenaea and the festival of Chytri. Of the four plays the last was a satiric drama; and the four together were called a tetralogy.” b. Characters or types of dialogues (D.L. 3.49): 1. instructive (ὑφηγητικός) A. theoretical (θεωρηµατικόν) a. physical (φυσικόν) b. logical (λογικόν) B. practical (πρακτικόν) a. ethical (ἠθικόν) b. political (πολιτικόν) 2. investigative (ζητητικός) A. training the mind (γυµναστικός) a. obstetrical (µαιευτικός) b. tentative (πειραστικός) B. victory in controversy (ἀγωνιστικός) a. critical (ἐνδεικτικός) b. subversive (ἀνατρεπτικός) c. Thrasyllan categories of the dialogues (D.L. 3.50-1): Physics: Timaeus Logic: Statesman, Cratylus, Parmenides, and Sophist Ethics: Apology, Crito, Phaedo, Phaedrus, Symposium, Menexenus, Clitophon, the Letters, Philebus, Hipparchus, Rivals Politics: Republic, the Laws, Minos, Epinomis, Atlantis Obstetrics: Alcibiades 1 and 2, Theages, Lysis, Laches Tentative: Euthyphro, Meno, Io, Charmides and Theaetetus Critical: Protagoras Subversive: Euthydemus, Gorgias, and Hippias 1 and 2 :1 d.
    [Show full text]
  • Constructing Kallipolis: the Political Argument of Plato's Socratic Dialogues
    Constructing Kallipolis: The Political Argument of Plato's Socratic Dialogues The Harvard community has made this article openly available. Please share how this access benefits you. Your story matters Citation Muller, Joe Pahl Williams. 2016. Constructing Kallipolis: The Political Argument of Plato's Socratic Dialogues. Doctoral dissertation, Harvard University, Graduate School of Arts & Sciences. Citable link http://nrs.harvard.edu/urn-3:HUL.InstRepos:33493293 Terms of Use This article was downloaded from Harvard University’s DASH repository, and is made available under the terms and conditions applicable to Other Posted Material, as set forth at http:// nrs.harvard.edu/urn-3:HUL.InstRepos:dash.current.terms-of- use#LAA Constructing Kallipolis: The Political Argument of Plato’s Socratic Dialogues A dissertation presented by Joe Pahl Williams Muller to The Department of Government in partial fulfillment of the requirements for the degree of Doctor of Philosophy in the subject of Political Science Harvard University Cambridge, Massachusetts April 2016 © 2016 Joe Pahl Williams Muller All rights reserved. Dissertation Advisors: Joe Pahl Williams Muller Professor Eric Nelson Professor Rusty Jones Constructing Kallipolis: The Political Argument of Plato’s Socratic Dialogues Abstract This dissertation examines the political argument of Plato’s Socratic dialogues. Common interpretations of these texts suggest, variously: (1) that Socrates does not offer much in the way of a political theory; (2) that Socrates does reflect on politics but ultimately rejects political in- stitutions as irrelevant to his ethical concerns; (3) that Socrates arrives at a political theory that either accepts or even celebrates free and demo- cratic political arrangements.
    [Show full text]
  • Neoplatonism: the Last Ten Years
    The International Journal The International Journal of the of the Platonic Tradition 9 (2015) 205-220 Platonic Tradition brill.com/jpt Critical Notice ∵ Neoplatonism: The Last Ten Years The past decade or so has been an exciting time for scholarship on Neo­ platonism. I ought to know, because during my stint as the author of the “Book Notes” on Neoplatonism for the journal Phronesis, I read most of what was published in the field during this time. Having just handed the Book Notes over to George Boys­Stones, I thought it might be worthwhile to set down my overall impressions of the state of research into Neoplatonism. I cannot claim to have read all the books published on this topic in the last ten years, and I am here going to talk about certain themes and developments in the field rather than trying to list everything that has appeared. So if you are an admirer, or indeed author, of a book that goes unmentioned, please do not be affronted by this silence—it does not necessarily imply a negative judgment on my part. I hope that the survey will nonetheless be wide­ranging and comprehensive enough to be useful. I’ll start with an observation made by Richard Goulet,1 which I have been repeating to students ever since I read it. Goulet conducted a statistical analy­ sis of the philosophical literature preserved in the original Greek, and discov­ ered that almost three­quarters of it (71%) was written by Neoplatonists and commentators on Aristotle. In a sense this should come as no surprise.
    [Show full text]
  • Concepts of Love and Some Implications for Education
    CONCEPTS OF LOVE AND SOME IMPLICATIONS FOR EDUCATION Dina Andersen A thesis submitted in conformity with the requirements for the degree of Doctor of Philosophy of the Department of Theory and Policy Studies in Education, Ontario Institute for Studies in Education of the Universis. of Toronto Copyright 0 Dina Andersen 1998 National Library Bibliothèque nationale of Canada du Canada Acquisitions and Acquisitions et Bibliographie Services services bibliographiques 395 Wellington Street 395, rue Wellington Ottawa ON K1A ON4 Ottawa ON K1A ON4 Canada Canada The author has granted a non- L'auteur a accordé une licence non exclusive licence allowing the exclusive permettant à la National Library of Canada to ~ibliothequenationale du Canada de reproduce, loan, distribute or sell reproduire, prêter, distribuer ou copies of this thesis in microform, vendre des copies de cette thèse sous paper or electronic formats. la forme de rnicrofiche/fïlm, de reproduction sur papier ou sur format électronique. The author retains ownership of the L'auteur conserve la propriété du copyright in this thesis. Neither the droit d'auteur qui protège cette thèse. thesis nor substantial extracts fiom it Ni la thèse ni des extraits substantiels may be printed or otheMrise de celle-ci ne doivent être imprimes reproduced without the author's ou autrement reproduits sans son permission. autorisation. ACKNOWLEDGMENTS When 1 decided to undertake a study of love 1 did not realize that rnany would express hesitations and personal reservations about the topic. 1 am therefore doubly grateful to Dr. Clive Beck, chair, for his continuous support, and to Dr. Grace Feuerverger as well as Dr.
    [Show full text]