The Blame Game: an Axiological Approach to the Doctrine of Doing and Allowing

Total Page:16

File Type:pdf, Size:1020Kb

The Blame Game: an Axiological Approach to the Doctrine of Doing and Allowing THE BLAME GAME: AN AXIOLOGICAL APPROACH TO THE DOCTRINE OF DOING AND ALLOWING A thesis submitted to Kent State University in partial fulfillment of the requirements for the Degree of Master of Arts by Christine Cleary December, 2013 Thesis written by Christine Cleary B.S., Kent State University, 2009 M.A., Kent State University, 2013 Approved by Deborah Barnbaum_________________________, Advisor David Odell-Scott__________________________, Chair, Department of Philosophy Raymond Craig____________________________, Associate Dean, College of Art and Sciences ii TABLE OF CONTENTS ACKNOWLEDGEMENTS ................................................................................................................. v INTRODUCTION ................................................................................................................................ 1 CHAPTER I. DOING AND ALLOWING HARM ..................................................................................... 4 1.1 Introduction ........................................................................................................................ 4 1.2 The Concept of Harm ....................................................................................................... 7 1.3 Contrast Strategy ............................................................................................................... 9 1.4 Rights-based Versions of the DDA ............................................................................. 12 1.4a Philippa Foot’s Version of the DDA ......................................................................... 13 1.4b Warren Quinn’s notion of the DDA .......................................................................... 23 1.4c Kai Draper ....................................................................................................................... 29 1.5 Conclusion ......................................................................................................................... 36 II. AXIOLOGY AND CONSEQUENTIALISM .................................................................... 37 2.1 Introduction ...................................................................................................................... 37 2.2 Recent Trends in Utilitarianism .................................................................................. 38 2.3a Traditional Utilitarianism and Axiology ................................................................. 44 2.3b Objection from Justice ................................................................................................. 49 2.3c Feldman’s Notion of Desert ........................................................................................ 50 2.3d Feldman’s Adjustment Method .................................................................................. 53 2.4 DDA and Consequentialism .......................................................................................... 59 iii iv 2.5 Value Account of the DDA ............................................................................................ 63 2.6 Conclusion ......................................................................................................................... 69 III. A REVISED ACCOUNT OF DOING AND ALLOWING HARM ............................ 71 3.1 Introduction ...................................................................................................................... 71 3.2 Two Pictures of Harms .................................................................................................. 72 3.3 Feldman’s conception of desert and the DDA .......................................................... 75 3.4 Two Sides of Harm .......................................................................................................... 84 3.5 A Sliding-Scale of Badness ............................................................................................ 86 3.6 A Theory of Harm-Doing and Harm-Allowing ........................................................ 88 IV.CASE STUDIES ...................................................................................................................... 92 4.1 Introduction ...................................................................................................................... 92 4.2 Cases .................................................................................................................................... 92 4.2a Case Study One: When the Doctor Gives a Deadly Dose ................................... 93 4.2b Analysis of Deadly Dose Case .................................................................................... 93 4.3a Case Study Two: Does “Do Everything” Include CPR? ....................................... 95 4.3b Analysis of “Doing Everything” Case ....................................................................... 96 4.4a Case Study Three: Two Cardiac Arrests, One Medical Team ............................ 99 4.4b Analysis of the Two Cardiac Arrests Case ............................................................100 4.5 Conclusion .......................................................................................................................103 CONCLUSION ...................................................................................................................................104 BIBLIOGRAPHY ..............................................................................................................................106 ACKNOWLEDGEMENTS I would like to thank my advisor, Dr. Deborah Barnbaum, for her endless dedication and support throughout this process. I could not have done it without you. I would also like to thank my committee members, Dr. Linda Williams, Dr. Kimberly Garchar, and Dr. Manacy Pai, for their support and insightful comments. I would also like to thank my friends and family for their understanding and encouragement as I made this journey. My parents taught me the invaluable lesson of hard work and passion in everything I do. Finally, I would like to thank my philosophy friends who have been instrumental in my development, both as a student and as a person: Elaine Blum, Nathan Radcliffe, Laurence Skirvin, Matthew Dargaj, and Andrew Magrath. v INTRODUCTION The Doctrine of Doing and Allowing (DDA) is a moral principle that holds that harms done are morally worse than harms allowed. The objective of this thesis is to show that the much-disputed DDA is only viable with supplementation. The DDA has been considered a non-consequentialist principle, however, recent attempts to revive the principle have resorted to the use of axiology, the value theory used in consequentialism. The DDA relies on a binary picture of harms. This thesis claims that this binary picture of harms is the primary reason that the DDA is susceptible to objection. Through an axiological approach, the project of this thesis is to develop a sliding-scale theory of harms, which is more robust and less open to criticism. There have been two major approaches to explaining the DDA: deontology and consequentialism. The first chapter will discuss the denontological approach to the DDA. The deontological approach has been used by philosophers like Philippa Foot and Warren Quinn who hold that the DDA is a non-utilitarian principle. Both Foot and Quinn have used rights to explain the moral asymmetry between harm-doings and harm-allowings. Chapter one analyzes the rights-based defenses of the DDA put forth by Foot and Quinn. Both Foot and Quinn explain the DDA by appealing to the precedence of negative rights over positive rights. The precedence of negative rights over positive rights, though, is not immediately clear. Both Foot and Quinn have failed to provide an account of why negative rights are more stringent than positive rights. 1 2 Such incomplete accounts mean either that the DDA should be dropped as a principle or that rights are do not provide the best defense for the DDA. Kai Draper challenges the DDA and provides a rights-based alternative to the DDA. Draper defends his rights-based account of harms with value. His account provides an important development in explaining the DDA: value becomes an essential part of saving the DDA. Though Draper aims to get rid of the DDA, his account opens the door to the possibility of saving it through the use of value. The second chapter discusses the DDA and its relationship with consequentialism. This chapter examines how Fred Feldman responds to an objection from justice to utilitarianism by developing an axiology that is sensitive to desert. Feldman’s approach to this objection provides a methodology, which is useful to saving the DDA. Though Foot objects to consequentialism in general, and utilitarianism in particular, an axiological approach does not rely on strict consequntialism to defend the DDA. Axiology is distinct from consequentialism and can be used to provide a more robust theory of harms. In fact, Xiaofei Liu has recently defended a value-based approach to the DDA in response to Draper’s objection. Liu further develops Draper’s value defense. Liu’s defense, however, still relies on a binary picture of harms. The third chapter incorporates a theory desert to develop a sliding-scale theory of harm-doings and harm-allowings. Feldman’s axiological approach is used to analyze the traditional, binary version of the DDA and explain why it does not work. The next part of the chapter explains how moral responsibility for a harm creates desert of
Recommended publications
  • Introduction to Philosophy. Social Studies--Language Arts: 6414.16. INSTITUTION Dade County Public Schools, Miami, Fla
    DOCUMENT RESUME ED 086 604 SO 006 822 AUTHOR Norris, Jack A., Jr. TITLE Introduction to Philosophy. Social Studies--Language Arts: 6414.16. INSTITUTION Dade County Public Schools, Miami, Fla. PUB DATE 72 NOTE 20p.; Authorized Course of Instruction for the Quinmester Program EDRS PRICE MF-$0.65 HC-$3.29 DESCRIPTORS Course Objectives; Curriculum Guides; Grade 10; Grade 11; Grade 12; *Language Arts; Learnin4 Activities; *Logic; Non Western Civilization; *Philosophy; Resource Guides; Secondary Grades; *Social Studies; *Social Studies Units; Western Civilization IDENTIFIERS *Quinmester Program ABSTRACT Western and non - western philosophers and their ideas are introduced to 10th through 12th grade students in this general social studies Quinmester course designed to be used as a preparation for in-depth study of the various schools of philosophical thought. By acquainting students with the questions and categories of philosophy, a point of departure for further study is developed. Through suggested learning activities the meaning of philosopky is defined. The Socratic, deductive, inductive, intuitive and eclectic approaches to philosophical thought are examined, as are three general areas of philosophy, metaphysics, epistemology,and axiology. Logical reasoning is applied to major philosophical questions. This course is arranged, as are other quinmester courses, with sections on broad goals, course content, activities, and materials. A related document is ED 071 937.(KSM) FILMED FROM BEST AVAILABLE COPY U S DEPARTMENT EDUCATION OF HEALTH. NAT10N41
    [Show full text]
  • Study of Ontology, Epistemology and Axiology on Management
    The Second International Conference on Entrepreneurship STUDY OF ONTOLOGY, EPISTEMOLOGY AND AXIOLOGY ON MANAGEMENT Rahmat Setiawan1 Airlangga University, Surabaya INDONESIA Email: [email protected] ABSTRACT There is still a difference of opinion among experts in the field of management of what is meant by management, namely whether the management is a science, an art or a profession. In addition, the management theory and studies have also experienced rapid growth, especially until the 19th century until the present. These developments have given rise to various groups of schools of thought about the management, which is a group of classical management perspective, a group of behavior management perspective, and a group of quantitative management perspective. Therefore, it is necessary to study on the development of management in terms of the philosophy of science perspective. By doing this assessment, management will be studied ontological, epistemological and axiological. Ontologically, management is the science, art and profession of work done through others. Material object is a behavior management work done through others. In management development, ontologically most experts view reality of social management in management as something objective, not subjective. Epistemologically, in management development, the approach most widely used by management experts is a deductive approach. However, the trend also shows that the inductive approach is also widely used lately. In axiological, largely through the efforts of study and research in the development of management is not value-free because the paradigm used by most bear management experts in developing management are positivist or functionalist paradigm. However, in applying the results of research to take a policy, then the leader of the company must still pay attention to the values of ethics and humanity.
    [Show full text]
  • Formal Axiology and the Philosophy of Social Science; Esp., Political Science
    Formal Axiology and the Philosophy of Social Science; esp., Political Science Introduction In the 22 centuries from Aristotle to Galileo, man’s way of life, and knowledge of nature, changed very little compared to the explosion of invention and discovery in the mere four centuries since Galileo. According to philosopher of science, R.S. Hartman, Galileo empowered humanity to make such progress when he “created the empirico-mathematical world picture;” that is, the worldview of natural science.1 During the Scientific Revolution, the European sense of reality was transformed from a dream-like condition under the control of “God’s Will,” and which only He could fully understand, to sets of processes which could be understood and explained in precise mathematical formulas. Natural philosophy, prior to Galileo, offered “explanations” of natural phenomena, but without much precision. For example, Aristotle defined “movement” as “the transition from potentiality to actuality.” This was accepted and studied for centuries. But Galileo re-defined “motion,” so that it became mathematically measurable. Rather than the vagaries of “realizing potential,” Galileo offered the formula V=s/t. He showed that by measuring the space (s) traversed by an object, and the time (t) it took, a precise measurement of speed, or velocity (V), could be calculated. Now motion was much less a mystery. Hartman notes that “Galileo’s formula led to a multitude of consequences; [eventually including] the systems of Newton and Einstein.”2 Galileo thus changed the way of thinking about nature from vague philosophical speculation to a method applying precise formal analysis and explanation. That shift in the way of thinking made possible all that followed.
    [Show full text]
  • Population Axiology
    Population axiology Hilary Greaves This is the pre-peer reviewed version of this article. The final version is forthcoming in Philosophy Compass; please cite the published version. This ar- ticle may be used for non-commercial purposes in accordance with Wiley Terms and Conditions for Self-Archiving. Abstract Population axiology is the study of the conditions under which one state of affairs is better than another, when the states of affairs in ques- tion may differ over the numbers and the identities of the persons who ever live. Extant theories include totalism, averagism, variable value theories, critical level theories, and \person-affecting” theories. Each of these the- ories is open to objections that are at least prima facie serious. A series of impossibility theorems shows that this is no coincidence: it can be proved, for various sets of prima facie intuitively compelling desiderata, that no axiology can simultaneously satisfy all the desiderata on the list. One's choice of population axiology appears to be a choice of which intuition one is least unwilling to give up. 1 Population ethics and population axiology: The basic questions In many decision situations, at least in expectation, an agent's decision has no effect on the numbers and identities of persons born. For those situations, fixed-population ethics is adequate. But in many other decision situations, this condition does not hold. Should one have an additional child? How should life-saving resources be prioritised between the young (who might go on to have children) and the old (who are past reproductive age)? How much should one do to prevent climate change from reducing the number of persons the Earth is able to sustain in the future? Should one fund condom distribution in the developing world? In all these cases, one's actions can affect both who is born and how many people are (ever) born.
    [Show full text]
  • Axiological Futurism
    View metadata, citation and similar papers at core.ac.uk brought to you by CORE provided by PhilPapers Axiological Futurism The Systematic Study of the Future of Human Values John Danaher, Senior Lecturer NUI Galway [email protected] Abstract: Human values seem to vary across time and space. What implications does this have for the future of human value? Will our human and (perhaps) post-human offspring have very different values from our own? Can we study the future of human values in an insightful and systematic way? This article makes three contributions to the debate about the future of human values. First, it argues that the systematic study of future values is both necessary in and of itself and an important complement to other future-oriented inquiries. Second, it sets out a methodology and a set of methods for undertaking this study. Third, it gives a practical illustration of what this ‘axiological futurism’ might look like by developing a model of the axiological possibility space that humans are likely to navigate over the coming decades. 1. Introduction Axiological change is a constant feature of human history. When we look back to the moral values of our ancestors, we cannot help but notice that they differed from our own. Our grandparents, for example, are quite likely to have harboured moral beliefs that would count as prejudiced and bigoted by modern standards; and we are quite likely to harbour moral beliefs that they would find abhorrent. As we go further back in time, the changes become even more pronounced (Pleasants 2018; Appiah 2010; Buchanan 2004; Pinker 2011).
    [Show full text]
  • A Systematic Framework for Exploring Worldviews and Its Generalization As a Multi-Purpose Inquiry Framework
    systems Article A Systematic Framework for Exploring Worldviews and Its Generalization as a Multi-Purpose Inquiry Framework David Rousseau 1,2,3,4,* and Julie Billingham 5,6 1 Centre for Systems Philosophy, Surrey KTI5 1EL, UK 2 Centre for Systems Studies, University of Hull, Kingston-on-Hull HU6 7RX, UK 3 Alister Hardy Research Centre, University of Wales TSD, Lampeter SA48 7ED, UK 4 Bertalanffy Center for the Study of Systems Science, 1040 Vienna, Austria 5 Centre for Systems Philosophy, Surrey KTI5 1EL, UK; [email protected] 6 Salesforce, Inc., San Francisco, CA 94105, USA * Correspondence: [email protected]; Tel.: +44-(0)-7714-677-687 Received: 31 March 2018; Accepted: 5 July 2018; Published: 10 July 2018 Abstract: Systems science methodologies do not have a consistent way of working with worldviews, even though determining stakeholder perspectives is central to systems thinking. In this paper, we propose a comprehensive “Worldview Inquiry Framework” that can be used across methodologies to govern the process of eliciting, documenting, and comparing the worldviews of stakeholders. We discuss the systemicity of worldviews and explain how this can help practitioners to find the roots of stakeholders’ disagreements about value judgements. We then generalize the structure of the Worldview Inquiry Framework to produce a “General Inquiry Framework” that can be used to govern an inquiry process in other contexts. We show that the presented Worldview Inquiry Framework is a special case of this General Inquiry Framework and show how the General Inquiry Framework can be tailored for other contexts such as problem solving, product design, and fundamental research.
    [Show full text]
  • PHILOSOPHY of EDUCATION Samson Okura Gunga Philosophy of Education
    Education: Education EDU08 PHILOSOPHY OF EDUCATION Samson Okura Gunga Philosophy of Education Foreword The African Virtual University (AVU) is proud to participate in increasing access to education in African countries through the production of quality learning materials. We are also proud to contribute to global knowledge as our Open Educational Resources (OERs) are mostly accessed from outside the African continent. This module was prepared in collaboration with twenty one (21) African partner institutions which participated in the AVU Multinational Project I and II. From 2005 to 2011, an ICT-integrated Teacher Education Program, funded by the African Development Bank, was developed and offered by 12 universities drawn from 10 countries which worked collaboratively to design, develop, and deliver their own Open Distance and e-Learning (ODeL) programs for teachers in Biology, Chemistry, Physics, Math, ICTs for teachers, and Teacher Education Professional Development. Four Bachelors of Education in mathematics and sciences were developed and peer-reviewed by African Subject Matter Experts (SMEs) from the participating institutions. A total of 73 modules were developed and translated to ensure availability in English, French and Portuguese making it a total of 219 modules. These modules have also been made available as Open Educational Resources (OER) on oer.avu.org, and have since then been accessed over 2 million times. In 2012 a second phase of this project was launched to build on the existing teacher education modules, learning from the lessons of the existing teacher education program, reviewing the existing modules and creating new ones. This exercise was completed in 2017. On behalf of the African Virtual University and our patron, our partner institutions, the African Development Bank, I invite you to use this module in your institution, for your own education, to share it as widely as possible, and to participate actively in the AVU communities of practice of your interest.
    [Show full text]
  • Contemporary Philosophical Naturalism: in Concept and Critique
    University of Montana ScholarWorks at University of Montana Graduate Student Theses, Dissertations, & Professional Papers Graduate School 2004 Contemporary philosophical naturalism: In concept and critique James Carlin Watson The University of Montana Follow this and additional works at: https://scholarworks.umt.edu/etd Let us know how access to this document benefits ou.y Recommended Citation Watson, James Carlin, "Contemporary philosophical naturalism: In concept and critique" (2004). Graduate Student Theses, Dissertations, & Professional Papers. 5022. https://scholarworks.umt.edu/etd/5022 This Thesis is brought to you for free and open access by the Graduate School at ScholarWorks at University of Montana. It has been accepted for inclusion in Graduate Student Theses, Dissertations, & Professional Papers by an authorized administrator of ScholarWorks at University of Montana. For more information, please contact [email protected]. Maureen and Mike MANSFIELD LIBRARY The University of Montana Permission is granted by the author to reproduce this material in its entirety, provided that this material is used for scholarly purposes and is properly cited in published works and reports. **Please check "Yes” or "No" and provide signature** Yes, I grant permission No, I do not grant permission Author's Signature: Date: Any copying for commercial purposes or financial gain may be undertaken only with the author's explicit consent. 8/98 Contemporary Philosophical Naturalism: In Concept and Critique by James Carlin Watson B. S. Lee University, Cleveland, TN, 2000 presented in partial fulfillment of the requirements for the degree of Master of Arts' The University of Montana December 2004 Approved by: Chairperson Dean, Graduate School l** I'OS Date UMI Number.
    [Show full text]
  • A. What Is Axiology? 1. Axiology Is the Study of Value, I.E., What Makes Good Things Good and Bad Things Bad 2
    A. What is axiology? 1. Axiology is the study of value, i.e., what makes good things good and bad things bad 2. Recall that the main point is to determine what things are intrinsically good, or good for their own sake 3. So far we have seen one very popular axiological theory, namely hedonism B. Arguments Against Hedonism 1. One objection comes from Robert Nozick 2. Nozick asks: Q: What would the ideal life be like if hedonism were true? A: One in which we always experienced pleasure, and Robert Nozick never experienced pain. (1938-2002) 3. Perhaps this is close to being possible, especially with new advances in virtual reality. 4. Consider an “experience machine” that could give us any experience we desire … or what it’s really called ... B. Arguments Against Hedonism YES, THAT’S RIGHT, THE NEW AND IMPROVED ORGASMATRON 5000 CAN GIVE YOU ANY EXPERIENCE YOU WANT AT ANY TIME! WHILE YOU ARE IN IT, YOU WON’T KNOW YOU ARE IN IT. YOU CAN BE ANYONE. YOU CAN DO ANYTHING. IT WILL SCAN YOUR BRAIN TO MAKE SURE YOU ARE HAPPY. IF YOU START BECOMING UNHAPPY FOR MORE THAN 5 SECONDS, IT WILL CORRECT ITSELF TO BRING YOU PLEASURE ONCE AGAIN. NEVER HAVE A BAD DAY AGAIN -- JUST PLUG IN TO THE ORGASMATRON 5000 TODAY! 1 B. Arguments Against Hedonism 5. Nozick’s argument against hedonism (P1) If hedonism is true, then life plugged in to the Orgasmatron 5000 is better than life not plugged in. (P2) Life plugged in to the Orgasmatron 5000 is not better than life not plugged in.
    [Show full text]
  • Chapter 2. Philosophical Assumptions and Interpretive Frameworks
    2 Philosophical Assumptions and distribute Interpretive Frameworks or hether we are aware of it or not, we always bring certain beliefs and philosophical assumptions to our research. Sometimes these are deeply Wingrained views about the types ofpost, problems that we need to study, what research questions to ask, or how we go about gathering data. These beliefs are instilled in us during our educational training through journal articles and books, through advice dispensed by our advisors, and through the scholarly communities we engage at our conferences and scholarly meetings. The difficulty lies first in becoming aware of these assumptions and beliefs and second in deciding whether we will actively incorporate them into our qualitativecopy, studies. Often, at a less abstract level, these philosophical assumptions inform our choice of theories that guide our research. Theories are more apparent in our qualitative studies than are philosophical assumptions, and researchers, oftennot trained in the use of theories, typically make them explicit in research studies. Qualitative researchers have underscored the importance of not only understanding the beliefs and theories that inform our research but also actively writing about Dothem in our reports and studies. This chapter highlights various philosophical assumptions that have occupied the minds of qualitative researchers for some years and the various theoretical and interpretive frameworks that enact these beliefs. 15 Copyright ©2018 by SAGE Publications, Inc. This work may not be reproduced or distributed in any form or by any means without express written permission of the publisher. 16 Qualitative Inquiry and Research Design A close tie does exist between the philosophy that one brings to the research act and how one proceeds to use a framework to shroud his or her inquiry.
    [Show full text]
  • Pragmatism As a Research Paradigm and Its Implications for Social Work Research
    social sciences $€ £ ¥ Article Pragmatism as a Research Paradigm and Its Implications for Social Work Research Vibha Kaushik * and Christine A. Walsh Faculty of Social Work, University of Calgary, Calgary, AB T2N 1N4, Canada * Correspondence: [email protected] Received: 18 July 2019; Accepted: 3 September 2019; Published: 6 September 2019 Abstract: Debates around the issues of knowledge of, and for, social work and other social justice–oriented professions are not uncommon. More prevalent are the discussions around the ways by which social work knowledge is obtained. In recent years, social work scholars have drawn on the epistemology of pragmatism to present a case for its value in the creation of knowledge for social work and other social justice–oriented professions. The primary focus of this essay is on providing a critical review and synthesis of the literature regarding pragmatism as a research paradigm. In this essay, we analyze the major philosophical underpinnings and methodological challenges associated with pragmatism, synthesize the works of scholars who have contributed to the understanding of pragmatism as a research paradigm, articulate our thoughts about how pragmatism fits within social work research, and illustrate how it is linked to the pursuit of social justice. This article brings together a variety of perspectives to argue that pragmatism has the potential to closely engage and empower marginalized and oppressed communities and provide hard evidence for the macro level discourse. Keywords: pragmatism; pragmatic research; social justice research; social work research 1. Introduction In social research, the term “paradigm” is used to refer to the philosophical assumptions or to the basic set of beliefs that guide the actions and define the worldview of the researcher (Lincoln et al.
    [Show full text]
  • The Axiological Turn in Early Twentieth Century American Philosophy: Alain Locke and José Vasconcelos in Epistemology, Value, and the Emotions Grant J
    Marquette University e-Publications@Marquette Philosophy Faculty Research and Publications Philosophy, Department of 1-1-2010 The Axiological Turn in Early Twentieth Century American Philosophy: Alain Locke and José Vasconcelos in Epistemology, Value, and the Emotions Grant J. Silva Marquette University, [email protected] Published version. "The Axiological Turn in Early Twentieth Century American Philosophy: Alain Locke and José Vasconcelos in Epistemology, Value, and the Emotions" in Philosophic Values and World Citizenship. Eds. Jacoby Adeshei Carter and Leonard Harris. Lanham MD: Rowman & Littlefield 2010: 31-56. Reproduced by permission of Rowman & Littlefield. © 2010 Rowman & Littlefield. Publisher link. All rights reserved. Please contact the publisher for permission to copy, distribute or reprint. Three The Axiological Tum in Early Twentieth Century American Philosophy: Alain Locke and Jose Vasconcelos on Epistemology, Value, and the Emotions Grant Silva Alain Locke (1885- 1954) and Jose Vasconcelos (1882-1959) are philosophical anthropologists.' Philosophical anthropology is the study of the anrhropos from a perspective that not only relies upon history, society, culture, biology and ab­ stract thought, such that humans are believed to be the producers and products of the relationship between these, but philosophical anthropology attempts to for­ mulate holistic understandings of the human as a complex being whose self­ image is part of its own constitution and growth. The possibility of growth, in conjunction with the plasticity of human nature, forces a philosophical anthro­ pologist to explore the subjective dimensions of these potentialities.2 Thus, phi­ losophical anthropology engages the rational aspects of the human mind, the historical dimensions of society and culture, in addition to subjective elements of experience (such as the emotions, values and feelings) in order to arrive at a complete understanding of the human.
    [Show full text]