Galois Theory Master's Dissertation

Total Page:16

File Type:pdf, Size:1020Kb

Galois Theory Master's Dissertation Galois Theory Master's Dissertation Victor Summers 9th May 2013 Contents Introduction 2 1 Rings, Irreducible Polynomials and Field Extensions 5 2 Separable Polynomials and the Cyclotomic Extensions 26 3 Automorphisms, Galois Groups and the Fundamental Theorem 34 4 General Polynomials and the Discriminant 50 5 Algebraic Closures and Composite Extensions 57 6 Solvability by Radicals and Galois’ Great Theorem 63 7 Solvability of the Symmetric Groups 68 Bibliography 72 1 Introduction Galois theory is generally considered to be the birth of modern algebra. Unlike some areas of mathematics, it is motivated by a simple clear cut question. Most secondary school children are familiar with the so-called ”quadratic formula” which expresses the two complex roots of b pb2 4ac a polynomial of degree 2; the formula λ = − ± − is instilled in us by the end of 1,2 2a high school. So why isn’t a similar looking formula for cubic polynomials also pushed into our brains as well? Does such a thing even exist? The answers to these questions are 1. yes, there does exist an analogous cubic formula and even a quartic formula, and 2. the cubic and quartic formulas are wildly complicated in comparison. Nevertheless, such formulas do exist; cubics and quartics are ”solvable by radicals”. The question arises, are there also such formulas for expressing the roots of quintics? or more generally of polynomials of degree higher than 4? The quadratic formula has been known in one form or another for thousands of years but it was as late as circa 1550 when the cubic formula was first discovered, with the quartic formula coming to light shortly after that. The methods for arriving at such general formulas seemed very much like they might generalise to polynomials of degree 5 and above, yet for almost 200 years mathematicians tried and tried but got precisely nowhere. It was only when a select few mathematicians in the 18th and 19th centuries, most notably Joseph-Louis Lagrange, Niels Henrik Abel and E´variste Galois (pictured below), began to investigate the true underlying structure of the problem in its full abstraction that significant developments in algebra were made. Lagrange introduced entirely new ways of approaching the problem. For instance, instead of trying to find clever tricks for producing explicit formulas for the roots of polynomials, he would ask what kind of structure a solution must have if it were to exist. Also, he would refer to a solution as being “known” if he could prove it to exist. This type of existential thinking is, in my opinion, the true birth of modern algebra. Galois built greatly upon the ground work put in place by Lagrange and is generally credited as the inventor of the notion of a group which, although they can be seen lurking in the background in earlier works, were not brought 2 into the light and recognised for their profound nature until then. As it turns out, there can exist no such analogous formulas for the general quintic and above! This fact is known as the Abel-Ruffini theorem, named after Paolo Ruffini and Niels Henrik Abel. Ruffini produced many proofs between 1799 and 1813 all of which were rejected by the mathematical community due to his use of overly awkward and unsatisfying personal notations and conventions. Abel produced a proof of the unsolvability of the general quintic and polynomials of higher degree in 1823, which in fact turned out to be slightly incomplete, but nevertheless was deemed satisfactory. The problem with the Abel-Ruffini theorem is that it says very little about why this is the case and gives no information about when a particular polynomial may or may not be solvable by radicals. Galois’ brilliance was in shedding light on the answer to these questions, giving a nec- essary and sufficient condition under which a given polynomial is solvable by radicals! Galois’ beautiful method can be summarised as follows: ”Give me any polynomial and I will assign a group to that polynomial in such a way that the possible forms of its roots are reflected in the structure of the group. This then enables us to transform the problem to a group theoretical question which is simpler to answer”. In this project I aim to display the foundations upon which modern Galois theory stands, illustrating the core concepts with worked examples and culminating in a rigorous proof of what has been dubbed Galois great theorem. Throughout the project I assume a knowledge of the basic terminology and concepts from ring theory. For example, I will not provide formal definitions of a ring, Euclidean rings, prin- cipal ideal domains and polynomial rings, and I will take for granted some minor theorems and lemmas such as Euclid’s lemma and ”zero divisors if and only if the cancellation law holds”. However, in the construction of objects which are of crucial importance to the end goal I will give full formal definitions, theorems and proofs. The only rings considered in this project are assumed to be commutative rings with a multiplicative identity. 3 Chapter 1 Rings, Irreducible Polynomials and Field Extensions Our first discussion is motivated by the following question. The polynomial x2 +1 Q[x] has 2 no roots in Q, so is there some larger field E containing Q in which it does have a root? More generally we may ask, given an arbitrary polynomial f(x) F [x] which has no roots in the 2 field F , is there some field E containing F in which f(x) has a root? The answer is yes and we begin here by drawing upon some tools from ring theory which enable us to construct such objects, as well as other tools which will be of great use to us throughout. Let R be a ring and I R be an ideal. Define a relation on R by ⇢ a b a b I. ⇠ () − 2 We see that is an equivalence relation. Indeed, ⇠ i) Reflexivity: a a =0 I for each a R so a a for each a R; − 2 2 ⇠ 2 ii) Symmetry: a b a b I b a = (a b) I b a; ⇠ () − 2 () − − − 2 () ⇠ iii) Transitivity: a b and b c a b, b c I = a c =(a b)+(b c) I ⇠ ⇠ () − − 2 ) − − − 2 () a c. ⇠ Let us denote the equivalence class of a R by [a]; note that b [a] b = a + i for some 2 2 () i I so that [a]= a + i i I .LetR/I denote the set of all equivalence classes of , i.e 2 { | 2 } ⇠ R/I = [a] a R , equipped with the operations of addition, multiplication and negation { | 2 } defined for each a, b R by 2 [a]+[b]=[a + b] 5 [a][b]=[ab] [a]=[ a]. − − We call R/I the quotient ring of I in R. Of course we need to validate the use of the word ”ring” in this definition: Since the operations are defined on equivalence classes, in order for them to be well-defined we require the definitions to be independent of representatives. Suppose a0 a and b0 b, then ⇠ ⇠ ( ) a0 = a + i and b0 = b + j for some i, j I. Therefore, a0 + b0 = a + b +(i + j) and i + j I ⊕ 2 2 so that a0 + b0 a + b = [a0]+[b0]=[a + b]. ⇠ ) ( ) a0b0 =(a + i)(b + j)=ab +(aj + ib + ij) and aj + ib + ij I. Therefore, a0b0 ab = 2 ⇠ ) [a0][b0]=[ab]. ( ) a0 = (a + i)= a i and i I. Therefore, a0 a = [a0]=[ a]. − − − − − 2 − ⇠ ) − All the axioms of a ring follow immediately from the corresponding properties of the ring R itself. In particular, observe that the zero element is 0 := [0] = 0+i i I = I. { | 2 } Important pieces of machinery are those maps between rings which preserve certain algebraic relations. Definition 1.1. Let R and S be rings. A function σ : S is called a ring homomorphism ! (or ring map for short) if it preserves the ring operations. That is, for each a, b R 2 i) σ(1R)=1S ii) σ(ab)=σ(a)σ(b) iii) σ(a + b)=σ(a)+σ(b), where 1R and 1S denote the multiplicative identities of R and S respectively. In general, a ring map needn’t be injective or surjective. In the case where a ring map is both injective and surjective, we call it an isomorphism and say that the rings R and S are isomorphic; write R ⇠= S. In this sense we identify rings which are isomorphic to one another; although the two rings may be very di↵erent in appearance and their respective operations may even appear dissimilar, they share all ring theoretic properites and are thus the same up to relabelling of elements. We will use this mode of identification throughout this project. These isomorphisms also provide a way of assigning the afore mentioned group to a polynomial! 6 Theorem 1.2 (The first ring isomorphism theorem). Let R and S be rings amd let σ : R S ! be a ring map. Then, R ker(σ) ⇠= Im(σ) . and an isomorphism is given by the map h : R ker(σ) Im(σ) with ! . h([a]) := σ(a). Proof. We first need to show that the definition of h is independent of representatives as it is defined on equivalence classes. To this end, suppose a0 a so that a0 = a + i for some ⇠ i ker(σ)=: I. 2 Then, h([a0]) = σ(a0) = σ(a + i) = σ(a)+σ(i) = σ(a)(asi ker(σ)) 2 = h([a]) as required. h is a ring map: h([a]+[b]) = h([a + b]) = σ(a + b)=σ(a)+σ(b)=h([a]) + h([b]) • h([a][b]) = h([ab]) = σ(ab)=σ(a)σ(b)=h([a])h([b]) • h(1 = [1]) = σ(1) = 1.
Recommended publications
  • Section V.1. Field Extensions
    V.1. Field Extensions 1 Section V.1. Field Extensions Note. In this section, we define extension fields, algebraic extensions, and tran- scendental extensions. We treat an extension field F as a vector space over the subfield K. This requires a brief review of the material in Sections IV.1 and IV.2 (though if time is limited, we may try to skip these sections). We start with the definition of vector space from Section IV.1. Definition IV.1.1. Let R be a ring. A (left) R-module is an additive abelian group A together with a function mapping R A A (the image of (r, a) being × → denoted ra) such that for all r, a R and a,b A: ∈ ∈ (i) r(a + b)= ra + rb; (ii) (r + s)a = ra + sa; (iii) r(sa)=(rs)a. If R has an identity 1R and (iv) 1Ra = a for all a A, ∈ then A is a unitary R-module. If R is a division ring, then a unitary R-module is called a (left) vector space. Note. A right R-module and vector space is similarly defined using a function mapping A R A. × → Definition V.1.1. A field F is an extension field of field K provided that K is a subfield of F . V.1. Field Extensions 2 Note. With R = K (the ring [or field] of “scalars”) and A = F (the additive abelian group of “vectors”), we see that F is a vector space over K. Definition. Let field F be an extension field of field K.
    [Show full text]
  • Section X.51. Separable Extensions
    X.51 Separable Extensions 1 Section X.51. Separable Extensions Note. Let E be a finite field extension of F . Recall that [E : F ] is the degree of E as a vector space over F . For example, [Q(√2, √3) : Q] = 4 since a basis for Q(√2, √3) over Q is 1, √2, √3, √6 . Recall that the number of isomorphisms of { } E onto a subfield of F leaving F fixed is the index of E over F , denoted E : F . { } We are interested in when [E : F ]= E : F . When this equality holds (again, for { } finite extensions) E is called a separable extension of F . Definition 51.1. Let f(x) F [x]. An element α of F such that f(α) = 0 is a zero ∈ of f(x) of multiplicity ν if ν is the greatest integer such that (x α)ν is a factor of − f(x) in F [x]. Note. I find the following result unintuitive and surprising! The backbone of the (brief) proof is the Conjugation Isomorphism Theorem and the Isomorphism Extension Theorem. Theorem 51.2. Let f(x) be irreducible in F [x]. Then all zeros of f(x) in F have the same multiplicity. Note. The following follows from the Factor Theorem (Corollary 23.3) and Theo- rem 51.2. X.51 Separable Extensions 2 Corollary 51.3. If f(x) is irreducible in F [x], then f(x) has a factorization in F [x] of the form ν a Y(x αi) , i − where the αi are the distinct zeros of f(x) in F and a F .
    [Show full text]
  • Math 545: Problem Set 6
    Math 545: Problem Set 6 Due Wednesday, March 4 1. Suppose that K is an arbitrary field, and consider K(t), the rational function field in one variable over K. Show that if f(X) 2 K[t][X] is reducible over K(t), then in fact f(X) is reducible over K[t]. [Hint: Note that just as Q is the fraction field of Z, so is K(t) the fraction field of K[t]. Carefully adapt the proof given in class for the analogous statement concerning f(X) 2 Z[X]. You will need to define the notion of a primitive polynomial in this new context, and prove a version of Gauss's Lemma.] 2. (A Generalized Eisenstein Criterion) Let R be an integral domain, and p ⊂ R a prime ideal. Suppose that n n−1 p(X) = X + rn−1X + ··· + r1X + r0 2 R[X] 2 satisfies r0; r1; : : : ; rn−1 2 p, and r0 2= p (i.e. p(X) is Eisenstein for p). Prove that p(X) is irreducible in R[X]. 3. This problem is designed to convince you that the Primitive Element Theorem fails in characteristic p > 0. Let K = Fp(S; T ) be the field of rational functions in two variables S; T with coefficients in the finite field with p elements. a) Prove that Xp −S is irreducible in K[X]. [Hint: Use the previous two problems and the fact that K = Fp(T )(S).] Hence p p p Fp( S; T ) = K[X]=(X − S) pp is a field extension of K of degree p (here S denotes thep coset p p p X+(X −S)).
    [Show full text]
  • MATH 4140/MATH 5140: Abstract Algebra II
    MATH 4140/MATH 5140: Abstract Algebra II Farid Aliniaeifard April 30, 2018 Contents 1 Rings and Isomorphism (See Chapter 3 of the textbook) 2 1.1 Definitions and examples . .2 1.2 Units and Zero-divisors . .6 1.3 Useful facts about fields and integral domains . .6 1.4 Homomorphism and isomorphism . .7 2 Polynomials Arithmetic and the Division algorithm 9 3 Ideals and Quotient Rings 11 3.1 Finitely Generated Ideals . 12 3.2 Congruence . 13 3.3 Quotient Ring . 13 4 The Structure of R=I When I Is Prime or Maximal 16 5 EPU 17 p 6 Z[ d], an integral domain which is not a UFD 22 7 The field of quotients of an integral domain 24 8 If R is a UDF, so is R[x] 26 9 Vector Spaces 28 10 Simple Extensions 30 11 Algebraic Extensions 33 12 Splitting Fields 35 13 Separability 38 14 Finite Fields 40 15 The Galois Group 43 1 16 The Fundamental Theorem of Galois Theory 45 16.1 Galois Extensions . 47 17 Solvability by Radicals 51 17.1 Solvable groups . 51 18 Roots of Unity 52 19 Representation Theory 53 19.1 G-modules and Group algebras . 54 19.2 Action of a group on a set yields a G-module . 54 20 Reducibility 57 21 Inner product space 58 22 Maschke's Theorem 59 1 Rings and Isomorphism (See Chapter 3 of the text- book) 1.1 Definitions and examples Definition. A ring is a nonempty set R equipped with two operations (usually written as addition (+) and multiplication(.) and we denote the ring with its operations by (R,+,.)) that satisfy the following axioms.
    [Show full text]
  • Galois Theory of Cyclotomic Extensions
    Galois Theory of Cyclotomic Extensions Winter School 2014, IISER Bhopal Romie Banerjee, Prahlad Vaidyanathan I. Introduction 1. Course Description The goal of the course is to provide an introduction to algebraic number theory, which is essentially concerned with understanding algebraic field extensions of the field of ra- tional numbers, Q. We will begin by reviewing Galois theory: 1.1. Rings and Ideals, Field Extensions 1.2. Galois Groups, Galois Correspondence 1.3. Cyclotomic extensions We then discuss Ramification theory: 1.1. Dedekind Domains 1.2. Inertia groups 1.3. Ramification in Cyclotomic Extensions 1.4. Valuations This will finally lead to a proof of the Kronecker-Weber Theorem, which states that If Q ⊂ L is a finite Galois extension whose Galois group is abelian, then 9n 2 N such that th L ⊂ Q(ζn), where ζn denotes a primitive n root of unity 2. Pre-requisites A first course in Galois theory. Some useful books are : 2.1. Ian Stewart, Galois Theory (3rd Ed.), Chapman & Hall (2004) 2.2. D.J.H. Garling, A Course in Galois Theory, Camridge University Press (1986) 2.3. D.S. Dummit, R.M. Foote, Abstract Algebra (2nd Ed.), John Wiley and Sons (2002) 2 3. Reference Material 3.1. M.J. Greenberg, An Elementary Proof of the Kronecker-Weber Theorem, The American Mathematical Monthly, Vol. 81, No. 6 (Jun.-Jul. 1974), pp. 601-607. 3.2. S. Lang, Algebraic Number Theory, Addison-Wesley, Reading, Mass. (1970) 3.3. J. Neukrich, Algebraic Number Theory, Springer (1999) 4. Pre-requisites 4.1. Definition: (i) Rings (ii) Commutative Ring (iii) Units in a ring (iv) Field 4.2.
    [Show full text]
  • Field Theory, Part 1: Basic Theory and Algebraic Extensions Jay Havaldar 1.1 Introduction
    Field Theory, Part 1: Basic Theory and Algebraic Extensions Jay Havaldar 1.1 Introduction Recall that a field is a commutative ring in which every nonzero element has a multiplicative inverse. Definition: The characteristic of a field is the additive order of 1. For example, if 1 + 1 + 1 = 0, then we say the field has characteristic 3. If 1 + 1 + ::: is never equal to 0, we say the field has characteristic 0. The characteristic of a field is either 0 or a prime. Denote 1 + 1 + ··· + 1, added n times, we denote this element n · 1. For each field F , we have a natural homomorphism Z ! F , which maps n to n · 1. Note that a homomomorphism into a field is either zero identically or an isomorphism; thus the image of this map can be realized as a subfield of F . The kernel of this homomorphism is exactly (charF )Z. By the isomorphism theorems, then, F contains either a subring isomorphic to Z (in which case F contains Q) or else F contains a subring isomorphic to Z/pZ (in which case Fp, the finite field of p elements, is a subfield). Definition: The prime subfield of a field F is the subfield generated by 1 additively. It is either Q or Fp, the finite field of p elements. Definition: If K is a field containing a subfield F , then K is an extension of F . The prime subfield is called the base field of an extension. Definition: The degree of K/F , the extension K over F , is the dimension of K as a vector space over F .
    [Show full text]
  • Galois Theory: the Proofs, the Whole Proofs, and Nothing but the Proofs
    GALOIS THEORY: THE PROOFS, THE WHOLE PROOFS, AND NOTHING BUT THE PROOFS MARK DICKINSON Contents 1. Notation and conventions 1 2. Field extensions 1 3. Algebraic extensions 4 4. Splitting fields 6 5. Normality 7 6. Separability 7 7. Galois extensions 8 8. Linear independence of characters 10 9. Fixed fields 13 10. The Fundamental Theorem 14 I’ve adopted a slightly different method of proof from the textbook for many of the Galois theory results. For your reference, here’s a summary of the main results and their proofs, without any of that pesky history and motivation—or distracting examples—to get in the way. Just the proofs1. Almost all of the hard work lies in three main theorems: Corollary 7.9 (a splitting field of a separable polynomial is Galois), Theorem 8.1 (linear independence of characters), and Theorem 9.1 (the degree of K over KH is bounded by the order of H). 1. Notation and conventions For groups H and G, we write H < G to mean that H is a (not necessarily proper) subgroup of G. Similarly, for sets S and T , we write S ⊂ T to indicate that S is a (not necessarily proper) subset of T . 2. Field extensions Definition 2.1. A field extension K/F is a triple (F, K, i) consisting of fields F and K together with a field homomorphism i : F → K. When there is no danger of confusion F will be identified with its image i(F ) under i, and so regarded as a subfield of K.
    [Show full text]
  • FIELD THEORY Contents 1. Algebraic Extensions 1 1.1. Finite And
    FIELD THEORY MATH 552 Contents 1. Algebraic Extensions 1 1.1. Finite and Algebraic Extensions 1 1.2. Algebraic Closure 5 1.3. Splitting Fields 7 1.4. Separable Extensions 8 1.5. Inseparable Extensions 10 1.6. Finite Fields 13 2. Galois Theory 14 2.1. Galois Extensions 14 2.2. Examples and Applications 17 2.3. Roots of Unity 20 2.4. Linear Independence of Characters 23 2.5. Norm and Trace 24 2.6. Cyclic Extensions 25 2.7. Solvable and Radical Extensions 26 Index 28 1. Algebraic Extensions 1.1. Finite and Algebraic Extensions. Definition 1.1.1. Let 1F be the multiplicative unity of the field F . Pn (1) If i=1 1F 6= 0 for any positive integer n, we say that F has characteristic 0. Pp (2) Otherwise, if p is the smallest positive integer such that i=1 1F = 0, then F has characteristic p. (In this case, p is necessarily prime.) (3) We denote the characteristic of the field by char(F ). 1 2 MATH 552 (4) The prime field of F is the smallest subfield of F . (Thus, if char(F ) = p > 0, def then the prime field of F is Fp = Z/pZ (the filed with p elements) and if char(F ) = 0, then the prime field of F is Q.) (5) If F and K are fields with F ⊆ K, we say that K is an extension of F and we write K/F . F is called the base field. def (6) The degree of K/F , denoted by [K : F ] = dimF K, i.e., the dimension of K as a vector space over F .
    [Show full text]
  • Ring Theory (Math 113), Summer 2014
    Ring Theory (Math 113), Summer 2014 James McIvor University of California, Berkeley August 3, 2014 Abstract These are some informal notes on rings and fields, used to teach Math 113 at UC Berkeley, Summer 2014. We go through the basic stuff: rings, homomorphisms, isomorphisms, ideals and quotient rings, division and (ir)reducibility, all heavy on the examples, mostly polynomial rings and their quotients. Some allusions to basic ideas from algebraic geometry are made along the way. Then we get into fields, culminating in a brief exposure to the basic ideas of galois theory. Contents 1 Basic Examples and Definitions 3 1.1 Preliminary Examples . .3 1.2 Definition of a Ring . .4 1.3 Special elements in a ring . .5 2 Subrings; Homomorphisms 7 2.1 Subrings; Adjoining Elements . .7 2.2 Products of Rings . .7 2.3 Homomorphisms . .8 2.4 Isomorphisms . 10 3 Kernels and Ideals 12 3.1 The kernel of a homomorphism . 12 3.2 Ideals . 12 3.3 Operations on Ideals . 14 4 Quotient Rings 15 4.1 Review: Cosets . 15 4.2 Quotient Rings . 15 4.3 The easy way to think about quotients of a polynomial ring . 16 4.4 The Isomorphism Theorem . 17 5 Factorization; Reducibility; Roots 19 5.1 Division and Factorization in Z ............................... 19 5.2 Division and Factorization of Polynomials . 19 6 Special Classes of Rings 23 6.1 Fields . 23 6.2 Integral Domains (\Domains") . 23 6.3 Principal Ideal Domains . 23 6.4 Euclidean Domains . 23 6.5 Unique Factorization Domains . 24 6.6 Relationships Between the Types of Rings .
    [Show full text]
  • Galois Theory Lecture Summary
    GALOIS THEORY: LECTURE 21 LEO GOLDMAKHER 1. SIMPLE GROUPS AND THE JORDAN-HOLDER¨ THEOREM Recall that at the end of last class we stated the Jordan-Holder¨ Theorem. Here’s the setup. Given any finite nontrivial group G, we have a normal series G B feg. We refine this normal series by inserting proper normal subgroups in between G and feg one at a time. Eventually we obtain a maximally refined normal series of the form G = G0 B G1 B G2 B ··· B Gn = feg; where no more intermediate normal subgroups can be inserted. Any such maximally refined normal series is called a composition series of G; the adjacent quotients Gi=Gi+1 are called the composition factors of G. Jordan-Holder¨ Theorem (Jordan 1869-70, Holder¨ 1889). Fix any finite group G. Then every composition series of G has the same length, and the list of composition factors is unique up to order and isomorphism. What can we say about the composition factors of a given group? Writing a given composition factor in the form Gi=Gi+1, we know by definition that there are no intermediate normal subgroups between Gi and Gi+1. This implies that the quotient group Gi=Gi+1 has no normal subgroups. A group with this property has a special name: Definition. A group is called simple if and only if its only normal subgroups are itself and the trivial group. Thus all the composition factors of G are simple. According to our analogy between groups and whole numbers from last time, we see that simple groups are the natural analogues of prime numbers, since their only proper ‘divisor’ is the trivial group feg.
    [Show full text]
  • Mathematics 6310 the Primitive Element Theorem Ken Brown, Cornell University, October 2010
    Mathematics 6310 The Primitive Element Theorem Ken Brown, Cornell University, October 2010 Given a field extension K=F , an element α 2 K is said to be separable over F if it is algebraic over F and its minimal polynomial over F is separable. Recall that this is automatically true in characteristic 0. Theorem 1. Suppose K = F (α1; : : : ; αn), with each αi algebraic over F and α2; : : : ; αn separable. Then K is a simple extension of F , i.e., K = F (γ) for some γ 2 K. In particular, every finite extension is simple in characteristic 0. Any γ as in the theorem is said to be a primitive element for the extension. You can find a proof of the theorem (or a slightly weaker version of it) in Section 14.4 of your text (Theorem 25 on p. 595), but this proof uses the full machinery of Galois theory. What follows is a more elementary proof, taken from van der Waerden. Proof. If F is finite, then so is K, and we can take γ to be any generator of the cyclic group K×. So we may assume that F is infinite. We may also assume that n = 2, since an easy induction reduces the general case to this case. So let K = F (α; β), with α and β algebraic over F and β separable. We will show that a random linear combination of α and β is primitive. More precisely, fix λ 2 F , and let γ := α+λβ. We will show that γ is primitive for all but finitely many choices of λ.
    [Show full text]
  • Extension Fields
    Extension Fields Throughout these notes, the letters F , E, K denote fields. 1 Introduction to extension fields Let F , E be fields and suppose that F ≤ E, i.e. that F is a subfield of E. We will often view F as the primary object of interest, and in this case refer to E as an extension field or simply extension of F . For example, R is an extension field of Q and C is an extension field of R. Now suppose that E is an extension field of F and that α 2 E. We have the evaluation homomorphism evα : F [x] ! E, whose value on a polynomial f(x) 2 F [x] is f(α). By definition, the image Im evα = F [α] is a subring of E. It is the smallest subring of E containing both F and α, and it is an integral domain as it is a subring of a field. Note that, by definition, F [α] = Im evα = ff(α): f(x) 2 F [x]g: There are now two cases: Case I: Ker evα = f0g. In other words, if f(x) 2 F [x] is a nonzero poly- nomial, then f(α) 6= 0, i.e. α is not the root of any nonzero polynomial in f(x). In this case, we say that α is transcendental over F . If α is tran- scendental over F , then evα : F [x] ! E is injective, and hence evα is an isomorphism from F [x] to F [α] ⊆ E. In particular, F [α] is not a field, since F [x] is not a field.
    [Show full text]