<<

chapter 8 Wittgenstein’s Paganism

Kevin Cahill

Our form of government has no sense unless it is founded in a deeply felt religious faith, and I don’t care what it is. dwight eisenhower, Address at the Freedoms Foundation, New York City, 12/22/52

Religion was a of great philosophical and personal significance for Wittgenstein, yet his relation to it is difficult to pin down. The of the place of in Wittgenstein’s and his ambivalent attitude towards it comes out nowhere more succinctly than in Maurice O’Connor Drury’s oft discussed recounting of Wittgenstein’s telling him that “I am not a religious man but I cannot help seeing every problem from a religious point of view.”1 This paper concerns how Wittgenstein’s well-known respect for and tolerance of religious tradition and his reticence, even revulsion, at rendering judgments of religious systems, is related to issues of and and to his of the significance of . In three recent papers has attacked arguments by Ilham Dil- man and that make purportedly Wittgensteinian impossibility arguments that try to limit logically what can and cannot be said about alien systems of thought and practice.2 She shows how, in quite similar ways, these

1 , ed., Recollections of Wittgenstein (Totowa, nj: Rowman and Littlefield, 1981), 94. This ambivalence is noted by many who knew Wittgenstein well. See for example G.H. von Wright in , , a Memoir (: Oxford Uni- versity Press, 1962), 19 and Malcolm op. cit., 72. 2 See Cora Diamond, “The Skies of Dante and Our Skies: A Response to Ilham Dilman,” ­Philosophical Investigations 35 (2012): 187–204; Cora Diamond, “Criticising from ‘Outside,’” Philosophical Investigations 36 (2013): 114–132; Cora Diamond, “Putnam and Wittgensteinian Baby-Throwing: Variations on a Theme,” in The Philosophy of , eds. R.E. Auxier, D.R. Anderson, L.E. Hahn (LaSalle: Open Court, 2015), 603–639. See also Cora Diamond, “How Old Are These Bones? Wittgenstein, Putnam and Verification,” Proceedings of the , Supplementary Volume 73 (1999): 99–134, where she criticizes a related, verification- ist style argument in . See also Peter Winch, The of a Social and Its Relation to Philosophy (London: , 1958); Peter Winch, “Understanding a Primitive Society,” American Philosophical Quarterly 1 (1964): 307–324; Ilham Dilman, Wittgenstein’s Co- pernican Revolution: The Question of Linguistic (Basingstoke: Palgrave, 2002).

© koninklijke brill nv, leiden, ���6 | doi 10.1163/9789004324107_009

Wittgenstein’s Paganism 175 argue that one must be moving within the grammar or on the inside of a particular conceptual or cultural system or domain of discourse in order to criticize it. Diamond criticizes Dilman and Winch for, in effect, trying to (use the later Wittgenstein to) lay down what she calls “supergrammatical” laws for what can and can’t be done with , in particular with reference to criticisms of social systems of thought and practice in which one is not a participant. A “supergrammtical law” as Diamond is using this term would be in effect be a law that delimits the domain of what is logically thinkable. Such laying down of supergrammatical laws would have the result that criticizing certain elements of social and intellectual systems of thought and practice from the “outside” deprives these elements of the very they have only within the “inside” of a particular social context. Because such criticism would violate the purported boundaries of intelligible speech, someone who engaged in it could be met with the relativist response “you can’t say that.” Diamond argues that this kind of argument is not necessarily to be found in the later Wittgenstein’s work and moreover that it is wrong. She writes:

[I]t is possible to have a grammar of social and intellectual things, such that what counts as the same in relation to such things depends upon the ways in which the people whose social and intellectual things are in question understand what is the same as what, what they are willing to identify as the same as such-and-such. It then counts as depriving an ­intellectual or social thing of its character as an intellectual or social thing if you impose in your thinking about it criteria of identity that would be rejected by those whose intellectual or social thing it is. But it is instead possible to have a grammar of social and intellectual things, in which such things have as it were two sides, the understandings of those things within the culture whose social and intellectual things they are, and un- derstandings by people who think about those intellectual and social things, using terms which are not limited to those available to, or accept- able by, the people whose intellectual and social things they are. This side of those things may in various ways involve and criteria of identity that would be rejected by those whose intellectual and social things the things in question are, as might reject the claim that their hope of a Messiah can be identified with the Christian hope that is taken to be fulfilled by Jesus. My argument here is: if you say that the second sort of approach deprives the intellectual and social things in question of their character as intellectual and social things, all that this comes to is that it is ruled out by the first grammar of intellectual and social things. It is not ruled out by the second. What counts as depriving an intellectual or