Rush Rhees: Main Publications

Total Page:16

File Type:pdf, Size:1020Kb

Rush Rhees: Main Publications Rush Rhees: Main Publications Books Without Answers, London: Routledge & Kegan Paul, 1%9. Discussions of Wittgenstein, London: Routledge & Kegan Paul, 1970. Contributions to Books Introduction to George Boole, Studies in Logic and Probability, London, 1952. ' "Ontology" and Identity in the Tractatus', in Studies in the Philosophy of Wittgenstein, ed. Peter Winch, London: Routledge & Kegan Paul, 1969. 'Postscript', in Ludwig Wittgenstein: Personal Recollections, Oxford: Basil Blackwell, 1981. 'Wittgenstein on Language and Ritual', in Wittgenstein and His Times, ed. Brian McGuiness, Oxford: Basil Blackwell, 1982. Introduction to Jakob Friedrich Fries, Dialogues on Morality and Religion, trans. David Walford, ed. D. Z. Phillips, Oxford: Basil Blackwell, 1982. Editorial work etc. Ludwig Wittgenstein, Philosophical Investigations, ed. G. E. M. Anscombe and R. Rhees, trans. G. E. M. Anscombe, Oxford: Basil Blackwell, 1953. Ludwig Wittgenstein, The Blue and Brown Books, ed. with an Introduction by R. Rhees, Oxford: Basil Blackwell, 1958. Ludwig Wittgenstein, 'A Lecture on Ethics', ed. R. Rhees, Philosophical Review, Vol. 74, 1965. Ludwig Wittgenstein, Lectures and Conversations on Aesthetics, Psychology and Religious Belief, ed. C. Barrett, from notes taken by Yorick Smythies, Rush Rhees and James Taylor, Oxford: Basil Blackwell, 1966. 'Wittgenstein's Notes for Lectures on "Private Experience" and "Sense Data"', ed. R. Rhees, Philosophical Review, Vol. 77, 1968. Ludwig Wittgenstein, Eine Philosophische Betrachtung, ed. R. Rhees, in Ludwig Wittgenstein: Schriften 5, Frankfurt: Suhrkamp, 1970. Ludwig Wittgenstein, 'Remarks on Frazer's "Golden Bough"', trans. A. C. Miles and R. Rhees, ed. R. Rhees, The Human World, No. 3, May 1971. Ludwig Wittgenstein, Philosophical Grammar, ed. R. Rhees, trans. A. J.P. Kenny, Oxford: Basil Blackwell, 1974. 201 202 Rush Rhees: Main Publications Ludwig Wittgenstein, Philosophical Remarks, ed. R. Rhees, trans. R. Har­ greaves and R. White, Oxford: Basil Blackwell, 1975. Wittgenstein's Lectures on the Foundation of Mathematics, Cambridge 1939, ed. C. Diamond, from notes by R. G. Bosanquet, Norman Malcolm, Rush Rhees and Yorick Smythies, New York: Cornell University Press, 1976. Ludwig Wittgenstein, 'Cause and Effect: Intuitive Awareness', ed. R. Rhees, trans. Peter Winch, Philosophia, Vol. 6, Nos 3 and 4, Sept.-Dec. 1976. Ludwig Wittgenstein, Remarks on the Foundations of Mathematics, ed. G. H. von Wright, R. Rhees, G. E. M. Anscombe, trans. G. E. M. Anscombe, Oxford: Basil Blackwell, 1978. Ludwig Wittgenstein, Bemerkungen uber Frazers Golden Bough, ed. R. Rhees, Brynmill Press, 1979. 'Remarks on Frazer's "Golden Bough"', ed. R. Rhees, trans. A. C. Miles, revised by Rush Rhees, The Human World, No. 3, 1971. Ludwig Wittgenstein: Personal Recollections, ed. R. Rhees, Oxford: Basil Blackwell, 1981. Comentarios sobre La Rama Dorada, trans. Javier Esquivel, ed. R. Rhees, National University of Mexico, 1985. Remarques sur le Rameau d'Or de Frazer, trans. Jean Lacoste, Lausanne, Switzerland: Edition L' Age d'Homme, 1982. Ludwig Wittgenstein, 'The Language of Sense Data and Private Experi­ ences I and ll', ed. R. Rhees, Philosophical Investigations, Vol. 7, Nos 1 and 2, Jan. and April 1984. Papers 'Social Engineering', Mind, Vol. LVI, 1947. Critical Notice of Maurice Cornforth, Science versus Idealism: An Examination of 'Pure Empiricism and Modern Logic', Mind, Vol. LVI, 1947. 'Politics and Society', Proceedings of the Aristotelian Society, Supp. Vol. XXIII, 1949. 'Can there be a private language?', Proceedings of the Aristotelian Society, Supp. Vol. XXVIII, 1954. 'Wittgenstein's Builders', Proceedings of the Aristotelian Society, 1959-60. 'Miss Anscombe on the Tractatus', Philosophical Quarterly, Vol. 10, Jan. 1960. 'The Tractatus: Seeds of Some Misunderstandings', Philosophical Review, Vol. LXXVII, April 1963. 'Some Developments in Wittgenstein's View of Ethics', Philosophical Review, Vol. LXXIV, Jan. 1965. 'The Tree of Nebuchadnezzar', The Human World, No. 4, Aug. 1971. 'Comment on ''The Tree of Nebuchadnezzar'' ', The Human World, No. 6, Feb. 1972. 'Language and Reality', The Gadfly, Vol. 5, No.2, May 1982. 'Ethical Punishment', in Value and Understanding, Essays for Peter Winch, ed. Raimond Gaita, London: Routledge & Kegan Paul, 1990. Index addition, 27-30 deliberation, 7, 126-33, 155 admirableness, 112-23 depth, 7, 14, 85-6, 135-51, 179-90 advice, 128-9, 130, 136-40 Descartes, Rene, 135 agreement, 1, &-7, 19, 27-30, 33, 92-4, desert, 157, 162-3 99, 11&-17, 124 Diamond/ Cora, 1-2 analogy, argument from, 145 Dilman, Ilham, 6-7, 110 Anderson, John, 4--5, 11, 61-73 Dinesen, Isak (Baroness Blixen), 129 Anscombe, G. E. M., 46, 48-51 disagreement, see agreement Arendt, Hannah, 141 dogma, 9-10, 195, 197-9 Armstrong, David, 109 Donagan, Alan, 135-6, 146, 147 aspect, 102 Dostoevsky, Fyodor, 134 assertion-condition, 14--16, 29 dualism, 6, 94--7 Augustine, Saint (of Hippo), 19&-7 Dummett, Michael, 14 Austin, J. L., 14, 47 awareness, animal, 3, 54--6 Eichmann, Adolf, 141, 143 ethics, see morality Baker, A. J., 61-5, 73 evidence, 10, 94, 99-100, 102-4, 108-9, Baker, Gordon, 17-19 19s-9 behaviourism, 98 example, see particular belief, 197 existence, 3, 53-9 blame, 151-M, 171-4, 179 Buber, Martin, 144 Flanagan, Owen, 188 Frege, Gottlob, 135 Callicles, 141, 144 cause, 69-73, 153-4, 158-9 Cavell, Stanley, 16, 30, 145 Gaita, Raimond, 7-8 certainty, 92-110, 195, 197-8 generality, 4, 13, 61-73, 112, 188 Cockburn, David, 5-6 Golding, William, 103 cognitivism, 125, 128, 147-8 Gorgias, 141-4 commitment, 5, 74-89 grammar, 12, 14, 16-17, 1s-20, 22, completeness, 13 23-6, 30, 31-2, 46, 115, 136, 146, 147, Conrad, Joseph, 11s-21 198 consequences, 16&-7 grief, 76-7, 81-4, 86, 88, 117 contradiction, 47 guilt, 129 Cook, John, 16, 20 critical enquiry, 69 Hare, R. M., 125 Heath, A. E., 11 Dareste, Camille, 46 Heath, Peter, 170 deception, 7-8, 112-23 Hegel, G. W. F., 164 203 204 Index heroism, 118-21 Nagel, Thomas, 126-8, 139, 165-71, Hertzberg, Lars, 6 173, 174-9 hiddenness, 93-9, 106-9 Nietzsche, Friedrich, 183 Hitler, Adolf, 191 Nominalism, 61-6 Holland, R. F., 3, 191 Holmer, Paul, 10 objectivity, 64, 125, 160 hubris, 178 Oedipus, 171-3 Hume, David, 5, 53-4, 69-73, 84-5, 87, opinion, 13, 18 161 pain, 1, 22-4, 26, 41, 76, 81, 83-5, 92, identity, 72, 74-5 107-8, 157-8, 160-2 indeterminacy, 6 Parfit, Derek, 75-8, 82-3, 85, 86, 87 Parkin, Molly, 171 Jones, J. R., 191 particular, 1-10, 61-73, 74, 78-80, 112, justification, 5, 8, 9, 10, 151-3, 159-64 138, 156-7, 162 perceptual judgements, 95-6 person, 5-8, 74-89, 99-109, 115-23, Kant, Immanuel, 9, 53-4, 140, 144, 164, 124-48 174 Peter, Saint, 178 Kashgar, 24-6 Phillips, D. Z., 9 Kastil, Alfred, 11 philosophy, 8, 12, 13, 118-21, 184 I<ierkegaard, Seren, 146, 182, 189 Pitcher, John, 12-14 Kripke, Saul, 14, 28-9 pity, 23, 88, 107-8, 173 Plato, 113-14, 137, 139, 140-4, 153 language, 14-34: language game, 6, 24, Platts, Mark, 134 35-44, 92-111; private language, Polus, 113-14, 141-3 20-2; see also grammar Popper, Sir Karl, 70-1 laughter, 158 possibility, 20 Lorenz, Konrad, 137 preaching, 195-6 love, 5-6, 74, 77-80, 82, 85, 86, 93-4, proof, 10 97-9, 1os-9, 118, 123, 198 psychological characteristics, 5, 75-89 luck, 9, 165-93 publicity, 22-6 Lucretius, 69 punishment, 8-9, 151-64 Luria, A. R., 24-6 Putnam, Hilary, 30 Luther, Martin, 133 Quinton (Lord), Anthony, 78-80, 82-3, Macintyre, Alasdair, 149, 155-6 88 Mackie, J. L., 149, 160-3 Malcolm, Norman, 2, 4 rationality, 140, 165, 166-8, 173-4, 178 Mann, Thomas, 185 reaction, 3, 8, 37-8, 41, 55-6, 86, 106, materialism, 6, 95-7 158-9, 161-3, 168 meaning, theories of, 1, 14, 30 Realism, 61-4, 67-8, 126, 139 measuring, 16-19 regularity, 17-18, 70-3 Melville, Herman, 131 religion, 10, 69-70, 194-200 Mendus, Susan, 90 resemblance, 4, 62-8 method, 13 retribution, 160 miracle, 46, 48 Rhees, Benjamin Rush, 10 Moore, G. E., 11 Rhees, Rush Or.), 2, 4, 10-11, 12-14, moralism, 190 16-17, 34, 35-44, 73, 109, 110, morality, 7, 101, 112-23, 124-48, 163, 112-23, 124-6, 130-1, 147, 151, 159, 165-90 181-6, 189, 191 Mounce, H. 0., 4-5 Rhees, Rush (Sr.), 10-11 Murdoch, his, 137, 156 Rhys, Morgan John, 10 Musil, Robert, 93, 98, 108 romanticism, see sentimentality Index 205 Rousseau, Jean-Jacques, 162 time, 31-3, 52-3, 75-7, 81, 84, 86-9, rule, 1, 12-34: moral rule, 180-1 153-6 Rush, Benjamin, 10 Tolstoy, Count Leo Nikolaevich, Russell (Earl), Bertrand, 158 117-18, 121 truth, 94, 96, 112-23, 139, 142 Saint-Hilaire, Etienne & Isidore truth-condition, 14 Geoffroy, 45 trying, 170-1 same, 14-16: see also identity turning into, 46-52 Santayana, George, 70 Sartre, Jean-Paul, 125 uncertainty, see certainty saying, 14-16, 37-44, 136, 139-44 understanding, 103, 197: common scepticism, 69-70 understanding, 49, 59; moral secondary sense, 48 understanding, 133-40, 146-8 Sellcirk, AJexander, 30-1 unity, 13 sense and nonsense, 37-44 universal, see generality sentiment, 161-2, 167-8 sentimentality, 78, 117-21, 134, 137-8, 147 vanishing, 3, 51-9 Sidgwick, Henry, 131 Singer, Isaac Bashevis, 52, 55 weighing, see measuring Slater, John Rothwell, 11 Weil, Simone, 130, 137, 164, 177, 178 Socrates, 8, 51, 140-4, 164 Wiggins, David, 125 Sophocles, 171, 178 will, 9, 167-73, 176-7: freedom of the speaking, see saying will, 179 sport of nature, 45-52 Williams, Bernard, 89, 165, 167-8, Strawson, P.
Recommended publications
  • Rethinking Fideism Through the Lens of Wittgenstein's Engineering Outlook
    University of Dayton eCommons Religious Studies Faculty Publications Department of Religious Studies 2012 Rethinking Fideism through the Lens of Wittgenstein’s Engineering Outlook Brad Kallenberg University of Dayton, [email protected] Follow this and additional works at: https://ecommons.udayton.edu/rel_fac_pub Part of the Catholic Studies Commons, Christianity Commons, Ethics and Political Philosophy Commons, Other Religion Commons, and the Religious Thought, Theology and Philosophy of Religion Commons eCommons Citation Kallenberg, Brad, "Rethinking Fideism through the Lens of Wittgenstein’s Engineering Outlook" (2012). Religious Studies Faculty Publications. 82. https://ecommons.udayton.edu/rel_fac_pub/82 This Article is brought to you for free and open access by the Department of Religious Studies at eCommons. It has been accepted for inclusion in Religious Studies Faculty Publications by an authorized administrator of eCommons. For more information, please contact [email protected], [email protected]. Note: This is the accepted manuscript for the following article: Kallenberg, Brad J. “Rethinking Fideism through the Lens of Wittgenstein’s Engineering Outlook.” International Journal for Philosophy of Religion 71, no. 1 (2012): 55-73. http://dx.doi.org/10.1007/s11153-011-9327-0 Rethinking Fideism through the Lens of Wittgenstein’s Engineering Outlook Brad J. Kallenberg University of Dayton, 2011 In an otherwise superbly edited compilation of student notes from Wittgenstein’s 1939 Lectures on the Foundations of Mathematics, Cora Diamond makes an false step that reveals to us our own tendencies to misread Wittgenstein. The student notes she collated attributed the following remark to a student named Watson: “The point is that these [data] tables do not by themselves determine that one builds the bridge in this way: only the tables together with certain scientific theory determine that.”1 But Diamond thinks this a mistake, presuming instead to change the manuscript and put these words into the mouth of Wittgenstein.
    [Show full text]
  • What Calvin and Wittgenstein Had Against Images
    Works Cited Green, Mitchell S., and John Williams, eds. Moore's Paradox: New Essays on Belief, Rationality, and the First Person. Oxford: Baker, Gordon P., and P. M. S. Hacker. An Analytical Commentary Clarendon Press, 2007. on the Philosophical Investigations. 4 vols. Chicago - Oxford: Jenkins, Keith, ed. The Postmodern History Reader. London - New University of Chicago Press - Blackwell Publishers, 1980- York: Routledge, 1997. 1996. Kerr, Fergus. Theology after Wittgenstein. Oxford: Blackwell, 1986. Bloor, David. Wittgenstein: A Social Theory of Knowledge. New York: Malcolm, Norman. Wittgenstein: A Religious Point of View? Ed. with Columbia University Press, 1983. a response by Peter Winch. London: Routledge, 1993. Bonnell, Victoria E., and Lynn Avery Hunt, eds. Beyond the McGinn, Marie. Routledge Philosophy Guidebook to Wittgenstein and the Cultural Turn: New Directions in the Study of Society and Culture. Philosophical Investigations. London - New York: Routledge, Berkeley: University of California Press, 1999. 1997. Bouwsma, O. K. Wittgenstein: Conversations, 1949-1951. Ed. J. L. McGrath, Alister. A Life of John Calvin: A Study in the Shaping of Craft and Ronald E. Hustwit. Indianapolis: Hackett, 1986. Western Culture. Oxford - Cambridge, Mass.: Basil Battles, Ford Lewis. Trans. Institutes of the Christian Religion, by Blackwell, 1990. John Calvin. Ed. John T. McNeill. 2 vols. Philadelphia: Monk, Ray. Ludwig Wittgenstein: The Duty of Genius. The Westminster Press, 1960. Harmondsworth: Penguin Books, 1991. Crary, Alice Marguerite, and Rupert J. Read, eds. The New Morse, Christopher. "Raising God's Eyebrows: Some Further Wittgenstein. London - New York: Routledge, 2000. Thoughts on the Concept of the analogia fidei." Union Crary, Alice Marguerite. "Wittgenstein's Philosophy in Relation to Seminary Quarterly Review, 37 (1981-1982): 39-49.
    [Show full text]
  • The Debate Over ›Wittgensteinian Fideism‹ and Phillips’ Contemplative Philosophy of Religion
    The Debate over ›Wittgensteinian Fideism‹ and Phillips’ Contemplative Philosophy of Religion Thomas D. Carroll Sometimes in a philosophical dispute, conflicting parties debate the truth or falsity of a given proposition. ›A fetus is a person‹, ›The meaning of the truth predicate is captured by the disquotational schema‹, and ›Con- sciousness is an emergent property of complex neural systems‹, are some examples of propositions whose truth and relative warrant are debated in recent philosophical literature. While many philosophical disputes follow this model, not all do. After all, in some philosophical disputes, no uncon- troversial framing of the terms of disagreement is available. Indeed, in some such disputes, it is not the truth of or warrant for a proposition that is be- ing debated, but instead the very words used to describe the disagreement itself. When surveying the scholarly literature over Wittgensteinian fideism, it is easy to get the sense that the principal interlocutors, Kai Nielsen and D.Z. Phillips, talk past one another, but finding the right words for apprais- ing the distance between the two voices is difficult. In this paper, I seek to appreciate this intellectual distance through an exploration of the varying philosophical aims of Nielsen and Phillips, of the different intellectual im- peratives that guide their respective conceptions of philosophical practice. In so doing, I seek to show how a contemplative mode in philosophy may be used to appraise a philosophical dispute and the terms of disagreement. In this case, a contemplative approach to understanding the dispute would frame Nielsen’s and Phillips’ contributions against the backdrop of the ends they conceive philosophy to have.
    [Show full text]
  • Rush Rhees on Philosophy and Religious Discourse
    View metadata, citation and similar papers at core.ac.uk brought to you by CORE provided by Asbury Theological Seminary Faith and Philosophy: Journal of the Society of Christian Philosophers Volume 18 Issue 4 Article 3 10-1-2001 Rush Rhees on Philosophy and Religious Discourse Lars Hertzberg Follow this and additional works at: https://place.asburyseminary.edu/faithandphilosophy Recommended Citation Hertzberg, Lars (2001) "Rush Rhees on Philosophy and Religious Discourse," Faith and Philosophy: Journal of the Society of Christian Philosophers: Vol. 18 : Iss. 4 , Article 3. Available at: https://place.asburyseminary.edu/faithandphilosophy/vol18/iss4/3 This Article is brought to you for free and open access by the Journals at ePLACE: preserving, learning, and creative exchange. It has been accepted for inclusion in Faith and Philosophy: Journal of the Society of Christian Philosophers by an authorized editor of ePLACE: preserving, learning, and creative exchange. RUSH RHEES ON PHILOSOPHY AND RELIGIOUS DISCOURSE Lars Hertzberg Rush Rhees is primarily known as an expOlmder ofWittgenstein's philosophy. However, his depth and originality as a thinker is increasingly recognized, largely due to the posthumous publication of his Nachlass. In this essay, char­ acteristic features of Rhees's philosophical style and method are conveyed through comparing and contrasting them with those of Wittgenstein. Rhees, it is found, is more of a dialogical thinker than Wittgenstein. His most distinctive contributions to philosophy were concerned with language and religion. Rhees's views on the unity of language are compared with those of Wittgenstein, and in conclusion Rhees's thinking about religion is presented through a close reading of one of his essays on that topic.
    [Show full text]
  • Religious Belief, Language Games and Postmodern Narratives
    37 Al-Hikmat Volume 27 (2007), pp. 37-58 RELIGIOUS BELIEF, LANGUAGE GAMES AND POSTMODERN NARRATIVES MUHAMMAD IQBĀL AFAQI* Abstract. This paper is centred on the question of objectivity of religious truth-claims in the Wittgensteinian perspective and explains how the evidentialist standard model of rationality leads us nowhere except putting us in a flyglass wherein like distraught flies we hopelessly flutter and flutter without finding the way out. This flyglass was manufactured by the Cartesian epistemology which demanded proofs in order to establish the cognitive validity of a truth-claim. Wittgenstein rejects this standpoint as wholly mistaken and misguided. There is no objectively neutral place from which the philosopher can have a critical look on a particular mode of discourse. The question of true/false depends on forms of life and language games. This line of argument has been followed by D. Z. Phillips, Peter Winch and Norman Malcolm. They also denounced the claim that there must be a common paradigm of rationality for all modes of discourse. Indeed, there are many difficulties in Wittgensteinian criteriology. But it is a fact that evidentialism fails to take account of diversity in modes of discourse. Likewise, the scientism suffers the fallacies of generalization and exclusivism. Rationalist ontology fallaciously promotes the idea of transcendental truth which Prof. Stuhar rejects as a system of delusion. Taking lead from Wittgensteinianism, postmodernism lays emphasis on equality of different cluster of meaning and affirms that there is no objective point of view that gives us access to a global truth. Hence, what is temporary, immanent and historically particular is accepted.
    [Show full text]
  • I Am in Training: Wittgenstein on Language Acquisition Megan J
    150 Wittgenstein on Language Acquisition I Am in Training: Wittgenstein on Language Acquisition Megan J. Laverty Teachers College, Columbia University Norm Friesen’s analysis of Wittgenstein as a tragic philosopher of education draws upon an understanding of Wittgenstein’s German influences: Arthur Schopenhauer, Friedrich Nietzsche, Sigmund Freud, Karl Kraus, Alfred Loos, Otto Wininger, and Oswald Spengler. According to Friesen, these influences share “a dark view of the world and our place within it,” which inspired Wittgenstein’s deeply pessimistic philosophy of education. Friesen argues that Wittgenstein deliberately brings the experience of learning a language into relation with the way “we talk of an animal being trained to do certain things” in order to highlight that the process of becom- ing a cultured or “conventionalized” being — otherwise known as humanization — necessarily entails “renunciation and brutality.” Friesen may be right that En- glish-speaking philosophers of education have failed to appreciate the full force of Wittgenstein on Abrichtung — the breaking in of an animal by means of obedience training or dressage — but he does not go all the way to establishing that Abrichtung is characteristically brutal and harsh. Wittgenstein uses the word Abrichtung to describe language learning and ed- ucation. As Wolfgang Huemer explains, in German the term is “exclusively used for animals, for training dogs to sit down on the command ‘sit,’ or horses to gallop when the rider performs a certain bodily movement.”1 Thus, to German speakers, Wittgenstein’s suggestion that “we have to abrichten our children” seems quite drastic; it implies that children are animals. According to Friesen, English-speaking philos- ophers of education are inclined to explain away Wittgenstein’s reliance upon the term, and so make his philosophy of education appear far more progressive than it is.
    [Show full text]
  • Rush Rhees on Religious Belief Language
    ©til Philosophical Writings, No. 12, Autumn 1999 BELIEF OR 'BELIEF': RUSH RHEES ON RELIGIOUS BELIEF LANGUAGE Todd R. Long-University ofRochester he recent book Rush Rhees on Religion and Philosophy contains a Tstimulating collection of writin~s by Rush Rhees on a variety of topics in the philosophy of religion. Comprising accounts of personal, religious and moral struggles, these essays provide a refreshing change from the often dry, overly technical approach to philosophy writing. Despite spanning more than thirty years, Rhees' s essays disclose a fairly consistent philosophy .of religion with a clear emphasis. Since he was Wittgenstein's student and long-time friend as well as a literary executor ofWittgenstein's writings, it is not surprising that Rhees's comments on the philosophy of religion reveal a distinctly Wittgensteinian approach, both in content and style. Moreover, Rhees's particular way of doing philosophy of religion seems, in retrospect, to have set the course that subsequent philosophy of religion of the Wittgensteinian type would take. Two themes, or methods, inform nearly the whole book: a concentrated focus on the "grammar" of religious statements and a selective reliance on verificationism. Although the latter may sound provocative since Wittgensteinian philosophy of religion can rightly be seen as a polemic against logical positivism, I will argue that Rhees's reliance on verificationism is important for his project. In this essay, I want to consider Rhees' s treatment of the sense of religious language, for it both exemplifies his approach to nearly all aspects of his philosophy of religion, and it discloses what I will argue is his chief failing: the distortion of Christian concepts on the basis of what he thinks ought to be deep about religion.
    [Show full text]
  • The Wittgensteinian Philosophy of Religion Is Misunderstood
    CHAPTER EIGHT THE WITTGENSTEINIAN PHILOSOPHY OF RELIGION IS MISUNDERSTOOD Ludwig Wittgenstein’s contribution to philosophy of religion is not very widely appreciated.1 From among those who bother themselves with such contribution critics are so easy to come by. Though it is D. Z. Phillips, rather than Wittgenstein, who bears the brunt of the criticisms.2 This is so probably because he is the most prolific of all those who dealt with religious matters in a Wittgensteinian manner— which makes it probably right to designate him the doyen of the so-called neo-Wittgensteinians, the propagators of the Wittgenstein- ian philosophy of religion—or because his interest in philosophy of religion and theology is a lot more focused than that of Wittgenstein whose concern is less on matters within religion or theology proper than on how religious matters are spoken of, and whose most signifi- cant contribution is providing philosophical materials to those who would care to specialize in philosophizing about religion (cf. Bar- rett 1991, 258). However the criticisms against the Wittgensteinian 1 One commentator points out that “the impact of Wittgenstein in [analytic philos- ophy of religion] has been minimal is self-evident. philosophy of religion goes on as if [he] never existed, or as if he had never written anything on the philosophy of reli- gion. [He] and his followers have certainly not succeeded in changing the agenda in philosophy of religion” (Moore 2005, 210). But, to put this claim in perspective, this case in the philosophy of religion is probably representative of the case in philosophy as a whole: as suggested by one other commentator, mainstream Anglophone philoso- phy has become practically anti-Wittgensteinian (Hacker 1996, 272).
    [Show full text]
  • Wittgenstein and Mid-20Th Century Political Philosophy: Naturalist Paths from Facts to Values
    chapter 7 Wittgenstein and Mid-20th Century Political Philosophy: Naturalist Paths from Facts to Values Andrius Gališanka The mid-20th century witnessed a transformation of analytic political philoso- phy. By the 1960s, meta-ethical discussions about the nature of the good and the meaning of ethical utterances were replaced by discussions about the na- ture of justice, liberty, and other substantive political values. This change drew on a variety of intellectual sources and was inspired by a variety of events.1 In this paper, I explore Ludwig Wittgenstein’s role in this intellectual transforma- tion, focusing on his influence on political philosophy in the 1950s and 1960s. While Wittgenstein wrote little directly on political philosophy or ethics, his philosophical approach inspired, among others, Elizabeth Anscombe, Philip- pa Foot, Stephen Toulmin, and John Rawls.2 The nature of this influence is still largely unexplored. Analyzing it will help us to better understand the patterns of political thinking that emerged in mid-century. I argue that Wittgenstein’s influence in the 1950s and 1960s was twofold. Primarily, his thought helped to argue that there is such a thing as normative reasoning, or reasoning about values and ways of life in which values are em- bedded. Wittgensteinians argued that the rules of this reasoning, including in- ferences from facts to values, were embedded in the conventions of normative practices or “language games.” Assuming that these rules have fixed meanings, they concluded that the fact-value gap did not
    [Show full text]
  • Wittgenstein on Rules and Private Language
    SAUL A. KRIPKE Wittgenstein on Rules and Private Language An Elementary Exposition Harvard University Press Cambridge, Massachusetts Contents Copyright © 1982 by Saul A. Kripke All rights reserved Preface Vll EIGHTH PRINTING, 1995 1 Introductory 1 Printed in the United States of America 2 The Wittgensteinian Paradox 7 3 The Solution and the 'Private Language' Argument 55 Postscript Wittgenstein and Other Minds Library ofCongress Cataloging in Publication Data 114 Index Kripke, Saul A., 1940- 147 Wittgenstein on rules and private language. Includes bibliographical references and index. Wittgenstein, Ludwig, 1889-1951. I. Title B3376.W564K74 192 81-20070 AACR2 ISBN 0-674-95401-7 (paper) - To my parents Preface The main part ofthis work has been delivered at various places as lectures, series oflectures, or seminars. It constitutes, as I say, 'an elementary exposition' ofwhat I take to be the central thread of Wittgenstein's later work on the philosophy of language and the philosophy of mathematics, including my interpretation of the 'private language argument', which on my view is principally to be explicated in terms ofthe problem of 'following a rule'. A postscript presents another problem Wittgenstein saw in the conception ofprivate language, which leads to a discussion of some aspects of his views on the problem ofother minds. Since I stress the strong connection in Wittgenstein's later philosophy between the philosophy of psychology and the philosophy of mathematics, I had hoped to add a second postscript on the philosophy ofmathematics. Time has not permitted this, so for the moment the basic remarks on philosophy ofmathematics in the main text must suffice.
    [Show full text]
  • Wittgenstein and Religion
    Georgia State University ScholarWorks @ Georgia State University Philosophy Theses Department of Philosophy 8-3-2006 Wittgenstein and Religion Daniel Patrick Corrigan Follow this and additional works at: https://scholarworks.gsu.edu/philosophy_theses Part of the Philosophy Commons Recommended Citation Corrigan, Daniel Patrick, "Wittgenstein and Religion." Thesis, Georgia State University, 2006. https://scholarworks.gsu.edu/philosophy_theses/13 This Thesis is brought to you for free and open access by the Department of Philosophy at ScholarWorks @ Georgia State University. It has been accepted for inclusion in Philosophy Theses by an authorized administrator of ScholarWorks @ Georgia State University. For more information, please contact [email protected]. WITTGENSTEIN AND RELIGION by DANIEL CORRIGAN Under the Direction of Robert L. Arrington ABSTRACT This thesis considers the implications of Wittgenstein’s early and later philosophy for the issue of religious belief, as well as the relation of religion to Wittgenstein’s thought. In the first chapter I provide an overview of the Tractatus and discuss the place of religion within the Tractarian framework. I then provide an overview of Philosophical Investigations . In the second chapter I consider interpretations by Norman Malcolm and Peter Winch of Wittgenstein’s comment that he could not help seeing every problem from a religious point of view, as well as Kai Nielsen’s famous critique of ‘Wittgensteinian Fideism.’ The third and final chapter takes up the issue of construing religious belief as a distinctive language-game. I consider arguments from D. Z. Phillips and criticisms of Phillips from Mark Addis and Gareth Moore. INDEX WORDS: Wittgenstein, Religion, Language-games WITTGENSTEIN AND RELIGION by DANIEL CORRIGAN A Thesis Submitted in Partial Fulfillment of the Requirements for the Degree of Master of Arts in the College of Arts and Sciences Georgia State University 2006 Copyright by Daniel Patrick Corrigan 2006 WITTGENSTEIN AND RELIGION by DANIEL CORRIGAN Major Professor: Robert L.
    [Show full text]
  • Approaches to Philosophy of Religion: Contemplating the World Or Trying to Find Our Way Home?
    This is a repository copy of Approaches to philosophy of religion: Contemplating the world or trying to find our way home?. White Rose Research Online URL for this paper: http://eprints.whiterose.ac.uk/85283/ Version: Accepted Version Article: Burley, M (2015) Approaches to philosophy of religion: Contemplating the world or trying to find our way home? Religious Studies, 51 (2). 221 - 239. ISSN 0034-4125 https://doi.org/10.1017/S0034412514000377 Reuse Unless indicated otherwise, fulltext items are protected by copyright with all rights reserved. The copyright exception in section 29 of the Copyright, Designs and Patents Act 1988 allows the making of a single copy solely for the purpose of non-commercial research or private study within the limits of fair dealing. The publisher or other rights-holder may allow further reproduction and re-use of this version - refer to the White Rose Research Online record for this item. Where records identify the publisher as the copyright holder, users can verify any specific terms of use on the publisher’s website. Takedown If you consider content in White Rose Research Online to be in breach of UK law, please notify us by emailing [email protected] including the URL of the record and the reason for the withdrawal request. [email protected] https://eprints.whiterose.ac.uk/ Approaches to philosophy of religion: contemplating the world or trying to find our way home? MIKEL BURLEY School of Philosophy, Religion and the History of Science, University of Leeds, Leeds LS2 9JT, UK e-mail: [email protected] Abstract: What is the point of philosophy of religion? Is it to help us find the right path in life, with the philosopher as guide and mentor? Or is it, as D.
    [Show full text]