The Wittgensteinian Philosophy of Religion Is Misunderstood

Total Page:16

File Type:pdf, Size:1020Kb

The Wittgensteinian Philosophy of Religion Is Misunderstood CHAPTER EIGHT THE WITTGENSTEINIAN PHILOSOPHY OF RELIGION IS MISUNDERSTOOD Ludwig Wittgenstein’s contribution to philosophy of religion is not very widely appreciated.1 From among those who bother themselves with such contribution critics are so easy to come by. Though it is D. Z. Phillips, rather than Wittgenstein, who bears the brunt of the criticisms.2 This is so probably because he is the most prolific of all those who dealt with religious matters in a Wittgensteinian manner— which makes it probably right to designate him the doyen of the so-called neo-Wittgensteinians, the propagators of the Wittgenstein- ian philosophy of religion—or because his interest in philosophy of religion and theology is a lot more focused than that of Wittgenstein whose concern is less on matters within religion or theology proper than on how religious matters are spoken of, and whose most signifi- cant contribution is providing philosophical materials to those who would care to specialize in philosophizing about religion (cf. Bar- rett 1991, 258). However the criticisms against the Wittgensteinian 1 One commentator points out that “the impact of Wittgenstein in [analytic philos- ophy of religion] has been minimal is self-evident. philosophy of religion goes on as if [he] never existed, or as if he had never written anything on the philosophy of reli- gion. [He] and his followers have certainly not succeeded in changing the agenda in philosophy of religion” (Moore 2005, 210). But, to put this claim in perspective, this case in the philosophy of religion is probably representative of the case in philosophy as a whole: as suggested by one other commentator, mainstream Anglophone philoso- phy has become practically anti-Wittgensteinian (Hacker 1996, 272). 2 Perhaps one of the most galling of these criticisms is the accusation that Phil- lips, Peter Winch, Normal Malcolm are “being most un-Wittgensteinian” as they are “clinging too closely to some assumption that Wittgenstein was rightly opposed to;” and to top it all is the hope expressed following the accusation that they “could cor- rect an important error in their positive characterization of religion if they were more loyal to the insights of Wittgenstein” (Brambough 1977, 16 and 19). It is as if the critic understands and respects Wittgenstein more than the Wittgensteinians like—of all people—Malcolm. The critic’s absolution of Wittgenstein from blame sounds patron- izing to a Wittgensteinian philosopher of religion. And there are others, too, who are almost as patronizing, like Kai Nielsen (1967, 193–4) who makes explicit his unwill- ingness to lay his criticisms on what he calls “Wittgensteinian fideism” at Wittgen- stein’s door, Patrick Sherry (1977, 28ff), and John Hick (1984, 46). 190 chapter eight philosophy of religion have a dubious provenance—this is what this chapter argues. Section I presents a selection of these criticisms. Section II shows two distinct traditions where one speaks of God as a being and the other does not. Section II argues that Wittgenstein belongs to the tradition where God is not spoken of as a being. Section IV sug- gests that criticisms against the Wittgensteinian philosophy of religion are borne of a misunderstanding owing to the lack of cognizance on the part of the critics of the tradition in which it belongs. I. The criticisms against Wittgensteinian philosophy of religion The general issue against the Wittgensteinian philosophy of religion— with Phillips at the focal point—is that it propagates theological posi- tions that are so unorthodox as to be bizarre even. One such charge of unorthodoxy—or more bluntly, heresy—is expressed by Renford Brambough thus: It is true that some who have called themselves Christians, and not only in recent times, have repudiated such beliefs [in the substantive exis- tence of God, the historical roots of the Christian religion, the incarna- tion of God in Jesus Christ at a particular time and place], even when they have continued to use for other purposes the language that was designed to express them: but at least until recently they were set down as heretics. Are the modern reinterpreters, including [Phillips, Winch and Malcolm], willing to face . the recognition that their understanding of the Christian religion is profoundly unorthodox? Do they cheerfully accept the consequences that all or nearly all Popes and Cardinals, and Luther and Milton and Donne and Saint Thomas Aquinas profoundly misunderstood their faith or faiths? (Brambough 1977, 16–17) Two of those theological positions of the neo-Wittgensteinians are here identified.3 One position—if proof-texting is to be called for—is suggested supposedly in, for instance, declarations such as this: 3 Albeit D. Z. Phillips (1986a, Ch. 1) identifies five positions attributed by critics to the Wittgensteinans, and most of all to him: (a) Religious beliefs are logically cut off from all other aspects of human life, (b) Religious beliefs can only be understood by religious believers, (c) Whatever is called religious language determines what is and what is not meaningful in religion, and (d) Religious beliefs cannot be criticized. However, these five positions seem to share a single theme such that they can be subsumed under ‘fideism’. .
Recommended publications
  • Rethinking Fideism Through the Lens of Wittgenstein's Engineering Outlook
    University of Dayton eCommons Religious Studies Faculty Publications Department of Religious Studies 2012 Rethinking Fideism through the Lens of Wittgenstein’s Engineering Outlook Brad Kallenberg University of Dayton, [email protected] Follow this and additional works at: https://ecommons.udayton.edu/rel_fac_pub Part of the Catholic Studies Commons, Christianity Commons, Ethics and Political Philosophy Commons, Other Religion Commons, and the Religious Thought, Theology and Philosophy of Religion Commons eCommons Citation Kallenberg, Brad, "Rethinking Fideism through the Lens of Wittgenstein’s Engineering Outlook" (2012). Religious Studies Faculty Publications. 82. https://ecommons.udayton.edu/rel_fac_pub/82 This Article is brought to you for free and open access by the Department of Religious Studies at eCommons. It has been accepted for inclusion in Religious Studies Faculty Publications by an authorized administrator of eCommons. For more information, please contact [email protected], [email protected]. Note: This is the accepted manuscript for the following article: Kallenberg, Brad J. “Rethinking Fideism through the Lens of Wittgenstein’s Engineering Outlook.” International Journal for Philosophy of Religion 71, no. 1 (2012): 55-73. http://dx.doi.org/10.1007/s11153-011-9327-0 Rethinking Fideism through the Lens of Wittgenstein’s Engineering Outlook Brad J. Kallenberg University of Dayton, 2011 In an otherwise superbly edited compilation of student notes from Wittgenstein’s 1939 Lectures on the Foundations of Mathematics, Cora Diamond makes an false step that reveals to us our own tendencies to misread Wittgenstein. The student notes she collated attributed the following remark to a student named Watson: “The point is that these [data] tables do not by themselves determine that one builds the bridge in this way: only the tables together with certain scientific theory determine that.”1 But Diamond thinks this a mistake, presuming instead to change the manuscript and put these words into the mouth of Wittgenstein.
    [Show full text]
  • What Calvin and Wittgenstein Had Against Images
    Works Cited Green, Mitchell S., and John Williams, eds. Moore's Paradox: New Essays on Belief, Rationality, and the First Person. Oxford: Baker, Gordon P., and P. M. S. Hacker. An Analytical Commentary Clarendon Press, 2007. on the Philosophical Investigations. 4 vols. Chicago - Oxford: Jenkins, Keith, ed. The Postmodern History Reader. London - New University of Chicago Press - Blackwell Publishers, 1980- York: Routledge, 1997. 1996. Kerr, Fergus. Theology after Wittgenstein. Oxford: Blackwell, 1986. Bloor, David. Wittgenstein: A Social Theory of Knowledge. New York: Malcolm, Norman. Wittgenstein: A Religious Point of View? Ed. with Columbia University Press, 1983. a response by Peter Winch. London: Routledge, 1993. Bonnell, Victoria E., and Lynn Avery Hunt, eds. Beyond the McGinn, Marie. Routledge Philosophy Guidebook to Wittgenstein and the Cultural Turn: New Directions in the Study of Society and Culture. Philosophical Investigations. London - New York: Routledge, Berkeley: University of California Press, 1999. 1997. Bouwsma, O. K. Wittgenstein: Conversations, 1949-1951. Ed. J. L. McGrath, Alister. A Life of John Calvin: A Study in the Shaping of Craft and Ronald E. Hustwit. Indianapolis: Hackett, 1986. Western Culture. Oxford - Cambridge, Mass.: Basil Battles, Ford Lewis. Trans. Institutes of the Christian Religion, by Blackwell, 1990. John Calvin. Ed. John T. McNeill. 2 vols. Philadelphia: Monk, Ray. Ludwig Wittgenstein: The Duty of Genius. The Westminster Press, 1960. Harmondsworth: Penguin Books, 1991. Crary, Alice Marguerite, and Rupert J. Read, eds. The New Morse, Christopher. "Raising God's Eyebrows: Some Further Wittgenstein. London - New York: Routledge, 2000. Thoughts on the Concept of the analogia fidei." Union Crary, Alice Marguerite. "Wittgenstein's Philosophy in Relation to Seminary Quarterly Review, 37 (1981-1982): 39-49.
    [Show full text]
  • The Debate Over ›Wittgensteinian Fideism‹ and Phillips’ Contemplative Philosophy of Religion
    The Debate over ›Wittgensteinian Fideism‹ and Phillips’ Contemplative Philosophy of Religion Thomas D. Carroll Sometimes in a philosophical dispute, conflicting parties debate the truth or falsity of a given proposition. ›A fetus is a person‹, ›The meaning of the truth predicate is captured by the disquotational schema‹, and ›Con- sciousness is an emergent property of complex neural systems‹, are some examples of propositions whose truth and relative warrant are debated in recent philosophical literature. While many philosophical disputes follow this model, not all do. After all, in some philosophical disputes, no uncon- troversial framing of the terms of disagreement is available. Indeed, in some such disputes, it is not the truth of or warrant for a proposition that is be- ing debated, but instead the very words used to describe the disagreement itself. When surveying the scholarly literature over Wittgensteinian fideism, it is easy to get the sense that the principal interlocutors, Kai Nielsen and D.Z. Phillips, talk past one another, but finding the right words for apprais- ing the distance between the two voices is difficult. In this paper, I seek to appreciate this intellectual distance through an exploration of the varying philosophical aims of Nielsen and Phillips, of the different intellectual im- peratives that guide their respective conceptions of philosophical practice. In so doing, I seek to show how a contemplative mode in philosophy may be used to appraise a philosophical dispute and the terms of disagreement. In this case, a contemplative approach to understanding the dispute would frame Nielsen’s and Phillips’ contributions against the backdrop of the ends they conceive philosophy to have.
    [Show full text]
  • Religious Belief, Language Games and Postmodern Narratives
    37 Al-Hikmat Volume 27 (2007), pp. 37-58 RELIGIOUS BELIEF, LANGUAGE GAMES AND POSTMODERN NARRATIVES MUHAMMAD IQBĀL AFAQI* Abstract. This paper is centred on the question of objectivity of religious truth-claims in the Wittgensteinian perspective and explains how the evidentialist standard model of rationality leads us nowhere except putting us in a flyglass wherein like distraught flies we hopelessly flutter and flutter without finding the way out. This flyglass was manufactured by the Cartesian epistemology which demanded proofs in order to establish the cognitive validity of a truth-claim. Wittgenstein rejects this standpoint as wholly mistaken and misguided. There is no objectively neutral place from which the philosopher can have a critical look on a particular mode of discourse. The question of true/false depends on forms of life and language games. This line of argument has been followed by D. Z. Phillips, Peter Winch and Norman Malcolm. They also denounced the claim that there must be a common paradigm of rationality for all modes of discourse. Indeed, there are many difficulties in Wittgensteinian criteriology. But it is a fact that evidentialism fails to take account of diversity in modes of discourse. Likewise, the scientism suffers the fallacies of generalization and exclusivism. Rationalist ontology fallaciously promotes the idea of transcendental truth which Prof. Stuhar rejects as a system of delusion. Taking lead from Wittgensteinianism, postmodernism lays emphasis on equality of different cluster of meaning and affirms that there is no objective point of view that gives us access to a global truth. Hence, what is temporary, immanent and historically particular is accepted.
    [Show full text]
  • Rush Rhees: Main Publications
    Rush Rhees: Main Publications Books Without Answers, London: Routledge & Kegan Paul, 1%9. Discussions of Wittgenstein, London: Routledge & Kegan Paul, 1970. Contributions to Books Introduction to George Boole, Studies in Logic and Probability, London, 1952. ' "Ontology" and Identity in the Tractatus', in Studies in the Philosophy of Wittgenstein, ed. Peter Winch, London: Routledge & Kegan Paul, 1969. 'Postscript', in Ludwig Wittgenstein: Personal Recollections, Oxford: Basil Blackwell, 1981. 'Wittgenstein on Language and Ritual', in Wittgenstein and His Times, ed. Brian McGuiness, Oxford: Basil Blackwell, 1982. Introduction to Jakob Friedrich Fries, Dialogues on Morality and Religion, trans. David Walford, ed. D. Z. Phillips, Oxford: Basil Blackwell, 1982. Editorial work etc. Ludwig Wittgenstein, Philosophical Investigations, ed. G. E. M. Anscombe and R. Rhees, trans. G. E. M. Anscombe, Oxford: Basil Blackwell, 1953. Ludwig Wittgenstein, The Blue and Brown Books, ed. with an Introduction by R. Rhees, Oxford: Basil Blackwell, 1958. Ludwig Wittgenstein, 'A Lecture on Ethics', ed. R. Rhees, Philosophical Review, Vol. 74, 1965. Ludwig Wittgenstein, Lectures and Conversations on Aesthetics, Psychology and Religious Belief, ed. C. Barrett, from notes taken by Yorick Smythies, Rush Rhees and James Taylor, Oxford: Basil Blackwell, 1966. 'Wittgenstein's Notes for Lectures on "Private Experience" and "Sense Data"', ed. R. Rhees, Philosophical Review, Vol. 77, 1968. Ludwig Wittgenstein, Eine Philosophische Betrachtung, ed. R. Rhees, in Ludwig Wittgenstein: Schriften 5, Frankfurt: Suhrkamp, 1970. Ludwig Wittgenstein, 'Remarks on Frazer's "Golden Bough"', trans. A. C. Miles and R. Rhees, ed. R. Rhees, The Human World, No. 3, May 1971. Ludwig Wittgenstein, Philosophical Grammar, ed. R. Rhees, trans. A. J.P.
    [Show full text]
  • Wittgenstein and Mid-20Th Century Political Philosophy: Naturalist Paths from Facts to Values
    chapter 7 Wittgenstein and Mid-20th Century Political Philosophy: Naturalist Paths from Facts to Values Andrius Gališanka The mid-20th century witnessed a transformation of analytic political philoso- phy. By the 1960s, meta-ethical discussions about the nature of the good and the meaning of ethical utterances were replaced by discussions about the na- ture of justice, liberty, and other substantive political values. This change drew on a variety of intellectual sources and was inspired by a variety of events.1 In this paper, I explore Ludwig Wittgenstein’s role in this intellectual transforma- tion, focusing on his influence on political philosophy in the 1950s and 1960s. While Wittgenstein wrote little directly on political philosophy or ethics, his philosophical approach inspired, among others, Elizabeth Anscombe, Philip- pa Foot, Stephen Toulmin, and John Rawls.2 The nature of this influence is still largely unexplored. Analyzing it will help us to better understand the patterns of political thinking that emerged in mid-century. I argue that Wittgenstein’s influence in the 1950s and 1960s was twofold. Primarily, his thought helped to argue that there is such a thing as normative reasoning, or reasoning about values and ways of life in which values are em- bedded. Wittgensteinians argued that the rules of this reasoning, including in- ferences from facts to values, were embedded in the conventions of normative practices or “language games.” Assuming that these rules have fixed meanings, they concluded that the fact-value gap did not
    [Show full text]
  • Wittgenstein and Religion
    Georgia State University ScholarWorks @ Georgia State University Philosophy Theses Department of Philosophy 8-3-2006 Wittgenstein and Religion Daniel Patrick Corrigan Follow this and additional works at: https://scholarworks.gsu.edu/philosophy_theses Part of the Philosophy Commons Recommended Citation Corrigan, Daniel Patrick, "Wittgenstein and Religion." Thesis, Georgia State University, 2006. https://scholarworks.gsu.edu/philosophy_theses/13 This Thesis is brought to you for free and open access by the Department of Philosophy at ScholarWorks @ Georgia State University. It has been accepted for inclusion in Philosophy Theses by an authorized administrator of ScholarWorks @ Georgia State University. For more information, please contact [email protected]. WITTGENSTEIN AND RELIGION by DANIEL CORRIGAN Under the Direction of Robert L. Arrington ABSTRACT This thesis considers the implications of Wittgenstein’s early and later philosophy for the issue of religious belief, as well as the relation of religion to Wittgenstein’s thought. In the first chapter I provide an overview of the Tractatus and discuss the place of religion within the Tractarian framework. I then provide an overview of Philosophical Investigations . In the second chapter I consider interpretations by Norman Malcolm and Peter Winch of Wittgenstein’s comment that he could not help seeing every problem from a religious point of view, as well as Kai Nielsen’s famous critique of ‘Wittgensteinian Fideism.’ The third and final chapter takes up the issue of construing religious belief as a distinctive language-game. I consider arguments from D. Z. Phillips and criticisms of Phillips from Mark Addis and Gareth Moore. INDEX WORDS: Wittgenstein, Religion, Language-games WITTGENSTEIN AND RELIGION by DANIEL CORRIGAN A Thesis Submitted in Partial Fulfillment of the Requirements for the Degree of Master of Arts in the College of Arts and Sciences Georgia State University 2006 Copyright by Daniel Patrick Corrigan 2006 WITTGENSTEIN AND RELIGION by DANIEL CORRIGAN Major Professor: Robert L.
    [Show full text]
  • Norman Malcolm, Edited with a Response by Peter Winch, WITTGENSTEIN: a RELIGIOUS POINT of VIEW?
    Faith and Philosophy: Journal of the Society of Christian Philosophers Volume 13 Issue 1 Article 12 1-1-1996 Norman Malcolm, edited with a response by Peter Winch, WITTGENSTEIN: A RELIGIOUS POINT OF VIEW? Ronald E. Hustwit Follow this and additional works at: https://place.asburyseminary.edu/faithandphilosophy Recommended Citation Hustwit, Ronald E. (1996) "Norman Malcolm, edited with a response by Peter Winch, WITTGENSTEIN: A RELIGIOUS POINT OF VIEW?," Faith and Philosophy: Journal of the Society of Christian Philosophers: Vol. 13 : Iss. 1 , Article 12. DOI: 10.5840/faithphil199613123 Available at: https://place.asburyseminary.edu/faithandphilosophy/vol13/iss1/12 This Book Review is brought to you for free and open access by the Journals at ePLACE: preserving, learning, and creative exchange. It has been accepted for inclusion in Faith and Philosophy: Journal of the Society of Christian Philosophers by an authorized editor of ePLACE: preserving, learning, and creative exchange. 146 Faith and Philosophy University Press, 1963); for criticisms of Almond and Verba, see Alasdair MacIntyre "The Essential Contestability of Some Social Concepts" Ethics 84 (1973) 1-9; Edward N. Muller and Mitchell A. Seligson, "Civic Culture and Democracy: The Question of Causal Relationships" American Political Science Review 88 (1994): 635-52. 8. Murray, op. cit., p. 103. 9. George Will "Conservatism and Character" in his The Morning After (New York: The Free Press, 1986), pp. 365-68, p. 365. 10. See Murray, op. cit., pp. 103ff. In these passages, Murray relies upon Adolph A. Berle, Jr. Power Without Property (New York: Harcourt, Brace and World, 1959), pp. 98-116, where the issue of legitimacy is more explicitly addressed than in his own discussion.
    [Show full text]
  • “Rules of the Game”: Max Weber and Peter Winch on Rule-Following Akos Sivado
    Reassessing the “Rules of the Game”: Max Weber and Peter Winch on Rule-Following Akos Sivado Introduction Many accounts of social scientific understanding (Verstehen) had been written in the past couple of decades that aim to reconstruct the differences in the approach social theorists suggest regarding the understanding and interpretation of social phenomena.1 One of the most striking shifts in what exactly social scientists are supposed to understand has been the exchanging of an individually oriented methodological approach (understood to be championed by Max Weber) for one that is centered on some shared, collective features of social phenomena – the most important example being Peter Winch’s focus on the necessarily social process of rule-following that underpins all actions we can rightfully deem meaningful. Winch’s critique of the Weberian framework for Verstehen is well-known and well- researched:2 while he gave credit to Weber for placing the emphasis on interpretation in social science (as opposed to searching for all-governing social laws) and anticipating much of his own contributions, Winch remarkedly disagreed with Weber about the categorization of types of actions to be understood. For Weber, the categories of action and social action are distinct in that while both contain the element of meaning-attribution by the actors, only the latter compose the proper subject matter of the social sciences, since the former lack the specific social orientation of the action that takes into account the existence and potential responses of other people. Such a distinction, from a Winchian perspective, seems unnecessary (and detrimental, even): in order for something to qualify as a legitimate action, it has to be amenable to be understood as an instance of rule-following.
    [Show full text]
  • On Peter Winch and Qualitative Social Research
    Wilfrid Laurier University Scholars Commons @ Laurier Sociology Major Research Papers Sociology 2015 On Peter Winch and Qualitative Social Research Miad Ranjbar Follow this and additional works at: https://scholars.wlu.ca/soci_mrp Part of the Theory, Knowledge and Science Commons Recommended Citation Ranjbar, Miad, "On Peter Winch and Qualitative Social Research" (2015). Sociology Major Research Papers. 1. https://scholars.wlu.ca/soci_mrp/1 This Article is brought to you for free and open access by the Sociology at Scholars Commons @ Laurier. It has been accepted for inclusion in Sociology Major Research Papers by an authorized administrator of Scholars Commons @ Laurier. For more information, please contact [email protected]. ON PETER WINCH AND QUALITATIVE SOCIAL RESEARCH by Miad Ranjbar B.Sc., York University, 2011 M.A., Ryerson University, 2013 Major Research Paper Submitted to the Department of Sociology in partial fulfillment of the requirements for Master of Arts in Sociology Wilfrid Laurier University © Miad Ranjbar, 2014 Abstract The aim of this paper is to discuss the tenets of the philosophy of Peter Winch, a Wittgensteinian philosopher, and the relevance of his work to conducting qualitative social research. In this paper, Peter Winch’s philosophy which is elaborately presented in his book The Idea of Social Science and its Relation to Philosophy is first extrapolated and examined. I then discuss how his philosophical reasoning can substitute for the philosophical underpinnings of constructivism, critical realism, and pragmatism as qualitative social research paradigms. In this paper, it is argued that the history of empirical social studies has been prone to important conceptual confusions both when researchers dwelled on the principles of positivistic and post-positivistic structure of the social scientific methodology, but more importantly, upon and after the emergence of qualitative sociology.
    [Show full text]
  • Final Version
    Making Sense of Winch Jan Overwijk 3400247 22 August 2012 Supervisors: Bert van den Brink Joel Anderson Making Sense of Winch In this thesis, I will examine Peter Winch’s contribution to the debate about how to depict human action in social theory. This debate is about how and in what terms may we best describe or interpret the activities of human beings. For example, is man a helpless character in the grand scheme of structures and institutions, his actions an effect of a series of external, causal factors? Or ought we to portray him as an agent, who, rather, is the author of these structures, whose actions we should interpret in terms of motives, purposes and intentions? These are two options that have been put forward in philosophical debate, and, here, I wish not to defend any particular position, but, rather, I would like to inquire into the presuppositions that underlie different strands in social theory. In particular, I want to examine how these presuppositions are present in Winch’s contribution on this matter. As a frame of reference, then, there seem to be two general options with regard to the presuppositions that inform separate currents of social theory. Firstly, we let human action dictate our methods by way of how it really is. It is then the social theorists job to represent it as accurately as possible on his ontological views. Representation here constitutes the link between the subject and the object of social theorising, and it is the object that is continually the criterion of correctness for a truthful representation.
    [Show full text]
  • PHILOSOPHY AS the ART of DISAGREEMENT on the Social and Moral Philosophy of Peter Winch Lars Hertzberg
    PHILOSOPHY AS THE ART OF DISAGREEMENT On the Social and Moral Philosophy of Peter Winch Lars Hertzberg If I light an electric torch at night out of doors I don’t judge its power by looking at the bulb, but by seeing how many objects it lights up. The brightness of a source of light is appreciated by the illumination it projects upon non- luminous objects. Simone Weil1 Make visible that which, but for you, might not have been seen. Robert Bresson Peter Winch’s2 work spans most of the main areas of philosophy. His early work dealt with the philosophy of the social sciences and with the problem of understanding alien cultures. Later on he returned to these issues on only a handful of occasions. Winch’s later work concerned itself, most prominently, with moral and political philosophy, but also with the philosophy of mind and language, epistemology, and the philosophy of religion. One of his most widely noted essays of later years is one in which he discusses the intelligibility of the suggestion that an object might 1 First and Last Notebooks (Oxford University Press, 1970), pp. 115-6. Quoted in Peter Winch, Ethics and Action (London: Routledge and Kegan Paul, 1971), p. 222. 2 Peter Winch was born in London on 14 January, 1926, and died in Champaign, Illinois, on 29 April, 1997. He was a student at Oxford in the late 1940’s. His most important influence during that time was Gilbert Ryle. Wittgenstein was then still living in Cambridge, but Winch never met him. From 1951 to 1964 Winch taught at Swansea.
    [Show full text]