A Philosophical Reading of Legal Positivism Juliele Maria Sievers

Total Page:16

File Type:pdf, Size:1020Kb

A Philosophical Reading of Legal Positivism Juliele Maria Sievers A philosophical reading of legal positivism Juliele Maria Sievers To cite this version: Juliele Maria Sievers. A philosophical reading of legal positivism. Philosophy. Université Charles de Gaulle - Lille III, 2015. English. NNT : 2015LIL30017. tel-01221770 HAL Id: tel-01221770 https://tel.archives-ouvertes.fr/tel-01221770 Submitted on 28 Oct 2015 HAL is a multi-disciplinary open access L’archive ouverte pluridisciplinaire HAL, est archive for the deposit and dissemination of sci- destinée au dépôt et à la diffusion de documents entific research documents, whether they are pub- scientifiques de niveau recherche, publiés ou non, lished or not. The documents may come from émanant des établissements d’enseignement et de teaching and research institutions in France or recherche français ou étrangers, des laboratoires abroad, or from public or private research centers. publics ou privés. Université de Lille 3 – Sciences Humaines et Sociales UMR 8163 – Savoirs, Textes, Langage THESIS Submitted for the Degree of PhD in Philosophy at the Université de Lille 3 Advisor: Pr. Dr. Shahid Rahman A Philosophical Reading of Legal Positivism Juliele Maria SIEVERS Université de Lille 3, July 16, 2015 Members of the Jury: Pr. Dr. Patrice CANIVEZ Université de Lille 3 Pr. Dr. Sandrine CHASSAGNARD-PINET Université de Lille 2 Pr. Dr. Jan-Reinard SIECKMANN Friedrich-Alexander Universität (Erlangen-Nürnberg) Pr. Dr. Matthias ARMGARDT Konstanz Universität Pr. Dr. Shahid RAHMAN Université de Lille 3 1 2 3 4 To my brother, Joel. (Para o mano.) 5 6 Table of Contents 1. Introduction……………………………………………………………………………………………………………………..1 2. The Author and his Theory……………………………………………………………………………………………….7 2.1 Three Schools of Thought, or: Why Legal Positivism? ………………………………………………….….8 2.1.1 Legal Realism……………………………………………………………………………………………………9 2.1.2 Natural Law Theory……………………………………………………………………………….……….10 2.1.3 Legal Positivism…………………………………………………………………………………………..…12 2.2 Why Kelsen? …………………………………………………………………………………………………….…….…….14 2.2.1 The Historical Context…………………………………………………………….……………………..14 2.2.2 The Pure Theory of Law (1960) ……………………………………………………………………..16 2.2.3 The General Theory of Norms (1979) …………………………………………….………………17 3. Preliminary Notions………………………………………………………………………………………………………..21 3.1 The Notion of Legal Validity………………………………………………………………………………..…………22 3.1.1 Defining “Legal Norm” …………………………………………………………………………………..22 3.1.2 Validity as Existence…………………………………………………………………………………….…24 3.2 Legal Science and its Object: Hume’s Naturalistic Fallacy………………………………………………27 3.2.1 Hume’s Naturalistic Fallacy…………………………………………………………………….……..28 3.2.2 The Relations between the Science and its Object…………………………………………30 3.3 Legal Conditions……………………………………………………………………………………………….…………..32 3.3.1 Imperatives and Norms………………………………………………………………….………………32 3.3.2 Causality and Imputation…………………………………………………………..…………………..34 3.4 Fictions………………………………………………………………………………………………………………………….35 3.4.1 The Hyerarchy of Norms…………………………………………………………………………….….36 3.4.2 The Basic Norm (Grundnorm) ………………………………………………………………………..38 7 3.5 Normative Conflicts and Logical Contradictions ……………………………………………………………41 3.5.1 The Problem of Applicability …………………………………………………………….…………..41 3.5.2 Conflicts between Norms ………………………………………………………………………………42 3.5.3 Derogation ……………………………………………………………………………………………….…..43 3.5.4 Temporality and Efficacy …………………………………………………………………………….…45 3.6 Practical Reasoning and the Rule of Inference ……………………………………………………….…….46 3.6.1 Dissipating the Confusion ……………………………………………………………………………..48 3.7 Final Remarks on this Topic ………………………………………………………………………………………….49 4. Legal Positivism: A Defense of the Scientific Method ……………………………………………………51 4.1 Positivism versus Natural Law Theories ………………………………………………………………………..52 4.1.1 Legal Validity and the Positive Law Perspective …………………………………….………56 4.1.2 Statics versus Dynamics ………………………………………………………………………..………57 4.1.3 Normative Content and the Natural Law Perspective …………………………….…….60 4.2 Understanding the Tension ……………………………………………………………………..……………………62 4.3 Overcoming the Tension ……………………………………………………………………………..……………….64 4.4 Final Remarks on this Topic ………………………………………………………………………………..………..65 5. Science and Method: The Naturalistic Fallacy ……………………………………………………………… 69 5.1 David Hume as a Model ………………………………………………………………………………………………..70 5.1.1 The “Ought” …………………………………………………………………………………….……………72 5.1.2 The “Is” …………………………………………………………………………………………………….…..74 5.2 One Example of the Fallacy: Jørgensen’s Dilemma ………………………………………….…………..75 5.3 Final Remarks on this Topic ……………………………………………………………………………..…………..79 6. The Non-Existence in Legal Science ………………………………………………………..……………………..82 6.1 Legal Science: Meaning and Particularities ………………………………………….…………….…………83 6.1.1 Some Examples …………………………………………………………………….……………………...84 6.1.2 Dichotomies in Kelsen’s Theory ……………………………………………………………………86 6.2 The Basic Norm as a Scientific Fiction …………………………………………….……….…………………..87 6.2.1 The Searching for Justification ……………………………………….……………………..……..88 6.2.2 Understanding the Fiction ……………………………………………………………..…………….89 6.2.3 A Little Help from Philosophy: Vaihinger’s “As-If” approach………………………….90 8 6.3 Where is the Basic Norm? ………………………………………………………………………………….…………91 6.4 Final Remarks on this Topic ………………………………………………………………………………..………..94 7. Normative Conflicts and Temporality in Law …………………………………………………………………96 7.1 Norms versus Sentences …..………………………………………………………………………………..………..97 7.2 Derogation ………………………………………………………………………………………………………………..….99 7.2.1 The Formulation of the Derogation Norm ……………………………………………………..99 7.3 The context of the Normative Conflict ………………………………………………………………………..101 7.3.1 Some Examples …………………………………………………………………………………………..101 7.4 Retroactivity ………………………………………………………………………………………………….……………103 7.5 The Basic Norm ……………………………………………………………………………………………………..……104 7.6 Final Remarks on this Topic ………………………………………………………………………………………..105 8. The Notion of Practical Reasoning (Part I) ……………………………………………………..……….…..107 8.1 Introduction …………………………………………………………………………………………….………….……..107 8.2 Understanding Jørgensen’s Dilemma ………………………………………………………..……………….109 8.3 First Attempts: Jørgensen and Ross ………………………………………………………….………………..109 8.3.1 Jørgensen’s Answer to the Dilemma ………………………………………….….……………110 8.3.2 Ross’ Answer to the Dilemma ……………………………………………….………….…………111 8.4 Kelsen’s Battle against the Dilemma …………………………………………………………………………..116 8.4.1 Correcting Jørgensen ……………………………………………………………………….…………117 8.4.2 Correcting Ross ………………………………………………………………………………..…………118 8.4.3 Kelsen’s Final Solution ……………………………………………………………..…………………119 8.5 Any Objections? Von Wright’s Deontic Logic ………………………………………………………………121 8.6 Final Remarks on this Topic ………………………………………………………………………………………..123 9. The Notion of Practical Reasoning (Part II) …………………………………………………..……………..125 9.1 Dialogs about Kelsen’s Solution ……………………………………………………………………….…………126 9.2 The Dialogical Approach to Logic ………………………………………………………………………………..127 9.2.1 Dialog, Validity, Truth and Justification ………………………………………………...…....128 9.3 The (Dia)logical Tools ………………………………………………………………………………………….………131 9.3.1 Preliminary Notions ……………………………………………………………………..……………..131 9.3.2 Set F Facts and the Problem of Justification …………………………….………………….134 9 9.3.3 The N Normative System ……………………………………………………….………………..….137 9.4 The Dialogical System DLLC2 …………………………………………………………………………………..…..141 9.5 Jérôme C.’s Guilt and Further Discussions ……………………………………..……………………..……142 9.5.1 Jérôme C.’s Example ………………………………………………….………………………………..142 9.5.2 Further Discussions …………………………………………………..……………………….….……145 9.6 Back to Jørgensen’s Dilemma and Final Remarks …………………….…………………….….……….147 10. Conclusion …………………………………………………………………………………….………………….……….149 Appendix ……………………………………………………………………………….………………………………….…….156 Bibliography ………………………………………………………………….…………………………………………….…..215 Abstract …………………………………………………………………………………………………………………………..220 Résumé ……………………………………………………………………………………………………………………………222 Acknowledgments …………………………………………………………………………………………………………..224 10 11 12 Chapter 1 Introduction The present study represents a true effort in bringing closer two disciplines which have a long history of mutual collaborations but also of remarkable tensions. By the way, the undeniable connections between law and philosophy have already generated a hybrid discipline called “philosophy of law”. This special branch aims to studying questions concerning the fundaments of law, the justification of legal norms, the sources of law and also its fundamental notions and concepts such as that of justice, for example, as well as the relations between the legal and the moral field. But the field of legal philosophy is a very vast one, since it tries to cover different issues conforming the different aspects of the legal domain, such as constitutional law, international law, contract law, and so on. Then, it seems reasonable that an interdisciplinary study must, to begin with, find its specific place and have a specific objective and justification within this legal context. Then, for the present study, we have chosen to place our inquiry in the field of legal theory and, more specifically, the field of analytical jurisprudence. Nowadays, the multidisciplinary feature seems to be a positive quality on the academic context. But the interests in interdisciplinarity are not recent: Logic and Law are a perfect example of two disciplines that were intimate related already when the period of Roman law prevailed. Nevertheless, the results of the possible associations
Recommended publications
  • Some Strands of Wittgenstein's Normative Pragmatism
    Some Strands of Wittgenstein’s Normative Pragmatism, and Some Strains of his Semantic Nihilism ROBERT B. BRANDOM ABSTRACT WORK TYPE In this reflection I address one of the critical questions this monograph is Article about: How to justify proposing yet another semantic theory in the light of Wittgenstein’s strong warnings against it. I see two clear motives for ARTICLE HISTORY Wittgenstein’s semantic nihilism. The first one is the view that philosophical Received: problems arise from postulating hypothetical entities such as ‘meanings’. To 27–January–2018 dissolve the philosophical problems rather than create new ones, Wittgenstein Accepted: suggests substituting ‘meaning’ with ‘use’ and avoiding scientism in philosophy 3–March–2018 together with the urge to penetrate in one's investigation to unobservable depths. I believe this first motive constitutes only a weak motive for ARTICLE LANGUAGE Wittgenstein’s quietism, because there are substantial differences between English empirical theories in natural sciences and semantic theories in philosophy that KEYWORDS leave Wittgenstein’s assimilation of both open to criticism. But Wittgenstein is Meaning and Use right, on the second motive, that given the dynamic character of linguistic Hypothetical Entities practice, the classical project of semantic theory is a disease that can be Antiscientism removed or ameliorated only by heeding the advice to replace concern with Semantic Nihilism meaning by concern with use. On my view, this does not preclude, however, a Linguistic Dynamism different kind of theoretical approach to meaning that avoids the pitfalls of the Procrustean enterprise Wittgenstein complained about. © Studia Humanitatis – Universidad de Salamanca 2019 R. Brandom (✉) Disputatio. Philosophical Research Bulletin University of Pittsburgh, USA Vol.
    [Show full text]
  • The Philosophical Underpinnings of Educational Research
    The Philosophical Underpinnings of Educational Research Lindsay Mack Abstract This article traces the underlying theoretical framework of educational research. It outlines the definitions of epistemology, ontology and paradigm and the origins, main tenets, and key thinkers of the 3 paradigms; positivist, interpetivist and critical. By closely analyzing each paradigm, the literature review focuses on the ontological and epistemological assumptions of each paradigm. Finally the author analyzes not only the paradigm’s weakness but also the author’s own construct of reality and knowledge which align with the critical paradigm. Key terms: Paradigm, Ontology, Epistemology, Positivism, Interpretivism The English Language Teaching (ELT) field has moved from an ad hoc field with amateurish research to a much more serious enterprise of professionalism. More teachers are conducting research to not only inform their teaching in the classroom but also to bridge the gap between the external researcher dictating policy and the teacher negotiating that policy with the practical demands of their classroom. I was a layperson, not an educational researcher. Determined to emancipate myself from my layperson identity, I began to analyze the different philosophical underpinnings of each paradigm, reading about the great thinkers’ theories and the evolution of social science research. Through this process I began to examine how I view the world, thus realizing my own construction of knowledge and social reality, which is actually quite loose and chaotic. Most importantly, I realized that I identify most with the critical paradigm assumptions and that my future desired role as an educational researcher is to affect change and challenge dominant social and political discourses in ELT.
    [Show full text]
  • Introduction to Philosophy. Social Studies--Language Arts: 6414.16. INSTITUTION Dade County Public Schools, Miami, Fla
    DOCUMENT RESUME ED 086 604 SO 006 822 AUTHOR Norris, Jack A., Jr. TITLE Introduction to Philosophy. Social Studies--Language Arts: 6414.16. INSTITUTION Dade County Public Schools, Miami, Fla. PUB DATE 72 NOTE 20p.; Authorized Course of Instruction for the Quinmester Program EDRS PRICE MF-$0.65 HC-$3.29 DESCRIPTORS Course Objectives; Curriculum Guides; Grade 10; Grade 11; Grade 12; *Language Arts; Learnin4 Activities; *Logic; Non Western Civilization; *Philosophy; Resource Guides; Secondary Grades; *Social Studies; *Social Studies Units; Western Civilization IDENTIFIERS *Quinmester Program ABSTRACT Western and non - western philosophers and their ideas are introduced to 10th through 12th grade students in this general social studies Quinmester course designed to be used as a preparation for in-depth study of the various schools of philosophical thought. By acquainting students with the questions and categories of philosophy, a point of departure for further study is developed. Through suggested learning activities the meaning of philosopky is defined. The Socratic, deductive, inductive, intuitive and eclectic approaches to philosophical thought are examined, as are three general areas of philosophy, metaphysics, epistemology,and axiology. Logical reasoning is applied to major philosophical questions. This course is arranged, as are other quinmester courses, with sections on broad goals, course content, activities, and materials. A related document is ED 071 937.(KSM) FILMED FROM BEST AVAILABLE COPY U S DEPARTMENT EDUCATION OF HEALTH. NAT10N41
    [Show full text]
  • Lexisnexis™ Academic
    LexisNexis™ Academic Copyright (c) 1996 The University of Notre Dame The American Journal of Jurisprudence 1996 41 Am. J. Juris. 133 LENGTH: 13043 words ARTICLE: KELSEN'S UNSTABLE ALTERNATIVE TO NATURAL LAW: RECENT CRITIQUES NAME: Jeffrey Brand-Ballard * BIO: * The author wishes to thank Wilfred E. Rumble and James Q. Whitman for valuable comments on earlier versions of this article. They retain responsibility for none of the remaining defeats. TEXT: [*133] I. INTRODUCTION Legal theorists in this century have often perceived a need for a theory capable of occupying a stable middle ground between natural law theory and nineteenth-century legal positivism. The prolific German-American legal philosopher, Hans Kelsen, was perhaps not the first to feel the need for such a theory, but he was certainly among the first to attempt to construct one. n1 Although Kelsen's own efforts failed, in many ways they defined the ambitions of twentieth-century legal theory and inspired others to take up the challenge. In order to understand the nature of the challenge, which confronts us still today, it is helpful to examine central difficulties with Kelsen's own Pure Theory of Law. Despite Kelsen's indubitable influence on legal theorists in the Anglo-American world and elsewhere, n2 the seminal nature of his work remains underappreciated in the United States. The international community, by contrast, has treated the Pure Theory to extensive criticism at every stage of its long development. Kelsen's earlier work, especially, has received some studious and illuminating criticism in recent years from critics on both sides of the Atlantic.
    [Show full text]
  • Legal Positivism: an Analysis of Austin and Bentham
    INTERNATIONAL JOURNAL OF LAW AND LEGAL JURISPRUDENCE STUDIES, VOLUME 1, ISSUE 6 LEGAL POSITIVISM: AN ANALYSIS OF AUSTIN AND BENTHAM Authors PRAGALBH BHARDWAJ National Law University, Odisha BH-1, National Law University, Odisha, Sector 13, CDA, Cuttack, Odisha. Country-India [email protected] RISHI RAJ National Law University, Odisha BH-1, National Law University, Odisha, Sector 13, CDA, Cuttack, Odisha. Country-India [email protected] 1 INTERNATIONAL JOURNAL OF LAW AND LEGAL JURISPRUDENCE STUDIES, VOLUME 1, ISSUE 6 Abstract Key words- Austin, Bentham, Criticism of Positivist School, Indian Perspective of Positivist School, Legal Positivist School. The school of Legal Positivism developed over the period of 18th and 19th century through the works of influential jurists such as John Austin and Jeremey Bentham. The works of these two great jurists was mainly responsible for the Legal Positivist School to acquire such importance in the field of legal jurisprudence. Their work was taken forward by jurists such as H.L.A.Hart. Although not free from shortcomings, the Legal Positivist School is regarded as the most influential school of thought in jurisprudence. Judges have based their decisions on this school of thought across various countries, including India. Indian Judges have been greatly influenced by the thinking of legal positivists and have applied their jurisprudence while giving landmark judgements such as A.K.Gopalan v. State of Madras to name one of them. The basic idea behind legal positivists was that they considered law as it is and not what it ought to be. They separated moral principles from legal principles.
    [Show full text]
  • David Hume on Norms and Institutions"
    Max Weber Programme Conference "David Hume on Norms and Institutions" San Domenico di Fiesole, Villa la Fonte, 17 April 2008 Justice as Unintended Consequence Please do not cite without prior permission Russel Hardin Department of Politics, New York University © 2006, Russell Hardin 2008.04.14 Justice As Unintended Consequence Russell Hardin* NYU - Politics One of the most neglected of all major legal philosophers is David Hume. His neglect as a specifically legal philosopher has followed from at least two unrelated causes. First, Hume’s work on ethics and on political philosophy was widely opposed and even dismissed in his own time. Second, a generation or so after his death, the positive law tradition of Jeremy Bentham and John Austin took center-stage in legal philosophy and dominated the Anglo-Saxon tradition for more than a century thereafter. This latter phenomenon might not have occluded attention to Hume except that Bentham ([1789] 1970) and Austin ([1832] 1954) took over a continental and quasi Hobbesian principle that was not necessary for their approach but which came to define it in the view of many. That principle is that there must be a primary law giver who is above the law. One could read this principle as analogous to the Aristotelian assumption that there must be a first mover, in this case, a first mover to get law started. Or one could read it as a Hobbesian assumption that we require an all powerful sovereign who is above the law but who gives and enforces the law for all other citizens. Hobbes sees his requirement as both logically and causally necessary.
    [Show full text]
  • A Priori Rules: Wittgenstein on the Normativity of Logic
    A Priori Rules: Wittgenstein on the Normativity of Logic Peter Railton The University of Michigan Introduction Like many, I have long been uneasy with the category of the a priori. Perhaps I have simply misunderstood it. It has seemed to me, at any rate, that asserting a claim or principle as a priori is tantamount to claiming that we would be justified in ruling out alternatives in advance, no matter what the future course of experience might hold. Yet in my own case, I have felt it would be mere bluffing were I to lodge such a claim. I certainly could not discover in myself any sense of the requisite authority, nor even any clear idea of where to look for guidance in forming it. Contemplating widely-used examples of "propositions true a priori" did not remove my worry. For a start, there was the shadow of history. A claim like "logical truth is a priori" or "the attribution of rationality is a priori in intentional explanation" kept sounding, to my ears, as if they echoed "the Euclidean geometry of space is a priori" or "the principle of sufficient reason is a priori in physical explanation". And these echoes awakened just sort of the worry that had initially unsettled me: I would pronouce myself satisfied that certain claims, at least, were safe from the threat of contrary experience, just on the eve of developments in our on-going view of the world that would lead a sensible person to want to reopen the question. So I would emerge looking like the (perhaps apocryphal) fellow who claimed, in the wake of the great inventions of the nineteenth century, that the US Patent Office could now be closed, since all the really new ideas had been used up.
    [Show full text]
  • Philosophy of Natural Law
    4YFPMWLIHMR-RWXMXYXI W.SYVREP7IT PHILOSOPHY OF NATURAL LAW Justice K. N. Saikia Former Judge Supreme Court of India. Director General National Judicial Academy By philosophy of law, for the purpose of this article, is meant the pursuit of wisdom, truth and knowledge of law by use of reason. In other words, philosophy of law means the ratlonal investigation and study of the basic ideal and principles of law. The philosophy of natural law is the subject of this article. Longing for a Higher Law - In the human bosom there has always been a longing for a higher law than those made by the community itself. The divine theory of law, the theory of natural law, and the principles of natural justice are some theories or notions found in fulfilment of this longing. Divine laws are those ascribed to God. Divine rights of kings were supposed to have been derived from God. Laws which are claimed to be God-made, may not be amendable by man; and their reasoning and provisions also not to be ques- tioned by man. Greek thinkers from Homer to the Stoics, and reflections of Plato and Aristotle mainly provide the beginning of systematic legal thinking. In Homer, law is embodied in the themistes which the kings receive from Zeus as the divine source of all earthly justice which is still identical with order and authority. Solon the great Athenian lawgiver appeals to Dike, the daughter of Zeus, as a guarantor of justice against earthly tyranny, violation of rights and social injustice. The Code of Hamurapi was handed over by the Sun god.
    [Show full text]
  • Kant on Obligation and Motivation in Law and Ethics
    University of Nebraska - Lincoln DigitalCommons@University of Nebraska - Lincoln Faculty Publications - Department of Philosophy Philosophy, Department of 1994 Kant on Obligation and Motivation in Law and Ethics Nelson T. Potter Jr. University of Nebraska - Lincoln, [email protected] Follow this and additional works at: https://digitalcommons.unl.edu/philosfacpub Part of the Continental Philosophy Commons, Ethics and Political Philosophy Commons, Legal Ethics and Professional Responsibility Commons, and the Legal History Commons Potter, Nelson T. Jr., "Kant on Obligation and Motivation in Law and Ethics" (1994). Faculty Publications - Department of Philosophy. 15. https://digitalcommons.unl.edu/philosfacpub/15 This Article is brought to you for free and open access by the Philosophy, Department of at DigitalCommons@University of Nebraska - Lincoln. It has been accepted for inclusion in Faculty Publications - Department of Philosophy by an authorized administrator of DigitalCommons@University of Nebraska - Lincoln. Potter in Jarbuch für Recht und Ethik (1994) 2. Copyright 1994, Friedrich-Alexander-Universität Erlangen-Nürnberg. Used by permission. Kant on Obligation and Motivation in Law and Ethics Nelson Potter I. There is a passage in Immanuel Kant's general introduction to both parts of Die Metaphysik der Sitten that deserves more attention than it has received. I plan to build the present paper around the implil:ations of this passage: In all lawgiving (Gesetzgebung) (whether it prescribes for internal or external actions, and whether it prescribes them a priori by reason alone or by the choice of another) there are two elements: first, a law, which represents an action that is to be done as objectively necessary, that is, which makes the action a duty; and second, an incentive, which connects a ground for determining choice to this action subjectively with the representation of the law.
    [Show full text]
  • Hans Kelsen's Contributions to the Changing Notion of International Criminal Responsibility
    City University of New York (CUNY) CUNY Academic Works All Dissertations, Theses, and Capstone Projects Dissertations, Theses, and Capstone Projects 5-2019 Between Politics and Morality: Hans Kelsen's Contributions to the Changing Notion of International Criminal Responsibility Jason Kropsky The Graduate Center, City University of New York How does access to this work benefit ou?y Let us know! More information about this work at: https://academicworks.cuny.edu/gc_etds/3249 Discover additional works at: https://academicworks.cuny.edu This work is made publicly available by the City University of New York (CUNY). Contact: [email protected] BETWEEN POLITICS AND MORALITY: HANS KELSEN’S CONTRIBUTIONS TO THE CHANGING NOTION OF INTERNATIONAL CRIMINAL RESPONSIBILITY by JASON REUVEN KROPSKY A dissertation submitted to the Graduate Faculty in Political Science in partial fulfillment of the requirements for the degree of Doctor of Philosophy, The City University of New York 2019 © 2019 JASON REUVEN KROPSKY All Rights Reserved ii Between Politics and Morality: Hans Kelsen’s Contributions to the Changing Notion of International Criminal Responsibility by Jason Reuven Kropsky This manuscript has been read and accepted for the Graduate Faculty in Political Science in satisfaction of the dissertation requirement for the degree of Doctor of Philosophy. Date John Wallach Chair of Examining Committee Date Alyson Cole Executive Officer Supervisory Committee: John Wallach Bruce Cronin Peter Romaniuk THE CITY UNIVERSITY OF NEW YORK iii ABSTRACT Between Politics and Morality: Hans Kelsen’s Contributions to the Changing Notion of International Criminal Responsibility by Jason Reuven Kropsky Advisor: John Wallach The pure theory of law analyzes the legal normative basis of jurisprudence.
    [Show full text]
  • A Brief Look at Mathematics and Theology Philip J
    Humanistic Mathematics Network Journal Issue 27 Article 14 Winter 1-1-2004 A Brief Look at Mathematics and Theology Philip J. Davis Brown University Follow this and additional works at: http://scholarship.claremont.edu/hmnj Part of the Logic and Foundations of Mathematics Commons, Mathematics Commons, and the Religious Thought, Theology and Philosophy of Religion Commons Recommended Citation Davis, Philip J. (2004) "A Brief Look at Mathematics and Theology," Humanistic Mathematics Network Journal: Iss. 27, Article 14. Available at: http://scholarship.claremont.edu/hmnj/vol1/iss27/14 This Article is brought to you for free and open access by the Journals at Claremont at Scholarship @ Claremont. It has been accepted for inclusion in Humanistic Mathematics Network Journal by an authorized administrator of Scholarship @ Claremont. For more information, please contact [email protected]. 1 A Brief Look at Mathematics and Theology Philip J. Davis "Such a really remarkable discovery. I wanted your opinion on it. You know the formula m over naught equals infinity, m being any positive number? [m/0 = ]. Well, why not reduce the equation to a simpler form by multiplying both sides by naught? In which case you have m equals infinity times naught [m = x 0]. That is to say, a positive number is the product of zero and infinity. Doesn't that demonstrate the creation of the Universe by an infinite power out of nothing? Doesn't it?" Aldous Huxley, Point Counter Point, (1928), Chapter XI. I Introduction We are living in a mathematical age. Our lives, from the personal to the communal, from the communal to the international, from the biological and physical to the economic and even to the ethical, are increasingly mathematicized.
    [Show full text]
  • Legal Theory Workshop UCLA School of Law Samuele Chilovi
    Legal Theory Workshop UCLA School of Law Samuele Chilovi Postdoctoral Fellow Pompeu Fabra University “GROUNDING, EXPLANATION, AND LEGAL POSITIVISM” Thursday, October 15, 2020, 12:15-1:15 pm Via Zoom Draft, October 6, 2020. For UCLA Workshop. Please Don’t Cite Or Quote Without Permission. Grounding, Explanation, and Legal Positivism Samuele Chilovi & George Pavlakos 1. Introduction On recent prominent accounts, legal positivism and physicalism about the mind are viewed as making parallel claims about the metaphysical determinants or grounds of legal and mental facts respectively.1 On a first approximation, while physicalists claim that facts about consciousness, and mental phenomena more generally, are fully grounded in physical facts, positivists similarly maintain that facts about the content of the law (in a legal system, at a time) are fully grounded in descriptive social facts.2 Explanatory gap arguments have long played a central role in evaluating physicalist theories in the philosophy of mind, and as such have been widely discussed in the literature.3 Arguments of this kind typically move from a claim that an epistemic gap between physical and phenomenal facts implies a corresponding metaphysical gap, together with the claim that there is an epistemic gap between facts of these kinds, to the negation of physicalism. Such is the structure of, for instance, Chalmers’ (1996) conceivability argument, Levine’s (1983) intelligibility argument, and Jackson’s (1986) knowledge argument. Though less prominently than in the philosophy of mind, explanatory gap arguments have also played some role in legal philosophy. In this area, the most incisive and compelling use of an argument of this kind is constituted by Greenberg’s (2004, 2006a, 2006b) powerful attack on positivism.
    [Show full text]