Redalyc.Some Arguments That the Mental Logic Theory Needs to Clarify

Total Page:16

File Type:pdf, Size:1020Kb

Redalyc.Some Arguments That the Mental Logic Theory Needs to Clarify Civilizar. Ciencias Sociales y Humanas ISSN: 1657-8953 [email protected] Universidad Sergio Arboleda Colombia López-Astorga, Miguel Some arguments that the mental logic theory needs to clarify to continue being an alternative to the mental models theory Civilizar. Ciencias Sociales y Humanas, vol. 16, núm. 31, julio-diciembre, 2016, pp. 235- 247 Universidad Sergio Arboleda Bogotá, Colombia Available in: http://www.redalyc.org/articulo.oa?id=100250983013 How to cite Complete issue Scientific Information System More information about this article Network of Scientific Journals from Latin America, the Caribbean, Spain and Portugal Journal's homepage in redalyc.org Non-profit academic project, developed under the open access initiative Civilizar Ciencias Sociales y Humanas 16 (31): 235-248, Julio-Diciembre de 2016 Some arguments that the mental logic theory needs to clarify to continue being an alternative to the mental models theory 1 Algunos argumentos que la teoría de la lógica mental necesita aclarar para continuar siendo una alternativa a la teoría de los modelos mentales Recibido: 04 de agosto de 2015 – Revisado: 31 de marzo de 2016 - Aprobado: 11 de mayo de 2016. Miguel López-Astorga 2 Abstract Undoubtedly, the mental models theory has become an important theory in cognitive science. This theory can predict and explain most of the experimental results that the literature of that eld shows. This fact can lead one to think that human mental processes are essentially semantic and that the syntactic approaches can no longer be held. In this way, in this paper, I try to analyze a framework based on formal rules, the mental logic theory, which also seems consistent with the experimental results, and review some of the reasons that its proponents often give in order to prove that it is worth continuing to consider it as an explicative alternative to the mental models theory. However, I show that such reasons can be questioned from the mental models theory and that, therefore, they need to be explained in a clearer way. Keywords Semantics, syntax, formal rules, mental logic, mental models. 1 Este artículo es resultado del Proyecto N. I003011, "Algoritmos adaptativos e inferencias lógicas con Resumen enunciados condicionales", apoyado Indudablemente, la teoría de los modelos mentales se ha convertido en una teoría por la Dirección de Investigación de importante en el ámbito de la ciencia cognitiva. Esta teoría puede predecir y explicar la la Universidad de Talca, Chile) El mayoría de los resultados experimentales que se hallan en la literatura. Tal hecho puede autor, que es el investigador principal del pr oyecto, agradece a las insti- llevar a pensar que los procesos mentales humanos son esencialmente semánticos y que tuciones mencionadas por su ayuda en el presente ya no es posible defender enfoques sintácticos. En este sentido, en este en la nanciación de este documen - trabajo, trato de analizar un marco basado en reglas formales, la teoría de la lógica mental, to y a los expertos anónimos que lo que también parece consistente con los resultados experimentales, y de revisar algunas de revisaron por sus comentarios, lo que sin duda mejoró la versión nal. las razones que sus defensores ofrecen a menudo para probar que puede ser productivo 2 Doctor en Lógica y Filosofía de la continuar considerándolo como una alternativa explicativa a la teoría de los modelos Ciencia por la Universidad de Cádiz, mentales. No obstante, muestro que esas razones pueden ser cuestionadas desde la teoría España. Licenciado en Filosofía de los modelos mentales y que, por tanto, necesitan ser explicadas de un modo más claro. y Ciencias de la Educación por la Universidad de Sevilla, España. Docente del Instituto de Estudios Palabras clave Humanísticos “Juan Ignacio Molina”, Semántica, sintaxis, reglas formales, lógica mental, modelos mentales. Universidad de Talca, Chile. Correo electrónico: [email protected] Para citar este artículo use: López- Astorga, M. (2016). Some arguments that t he mental logic theory needs to clarify to continue being an alter- native to the mental models theory. Civilizar Ciencias Sociales y Humanas, 16 (31), 235-248. 236 Miguel lópez -A storg A Introduction the discussion between the two approaches is more explicit (e.g., López-Astorga, 2014a, It is obvious that the mental models 2014b, 2015a, 2015b, 2015c, 2016a; O’Brien, theory (from now on, MM), which is explained, Braine, & Yang, 1994; Schroyens, Schaeken, & described, and commented on in papers such D’Ydewalle, 2001). In this way, I think that what as, for example, Byrne and Johnson-Laird is appropriate is to start by describing the general (2009), Johnson-Laird (1983, 2001, 2006, theses both of MM and ML. 2010, 2012, 2015), Johnson-Laird, Byrne, and Girotto (2009), Khemlani and Johnson-Laird The semantic approach of MM (2009), Oakhill and Garnham (1996), or Orenes and Johnson-Laird (2012), is a very relevant As said, MM is fundamentally a semantic theory at present. In addition to the fact that it theory. It states that syntax is not important in has wide acceptance in the eld of psychology human reasoning and that individuals, when they of reasoning and cognitive science, MM has reason, pay attention to the semantic possibilities proved to be consistent with almost all the or models of propositions. In this way, what experimental results that can be found in the people do is to look for the models in which, if literature on cognition. For these reasons, it the premises are true, the conclusion is true too. can be thought that this theory is the theory that best accounts for human inferential activity, One interesting point of MM is that that it is right to claim that mental processes are individuals do not always identify all the basically semantic, and that neither syntax nor models to which the propositions refer. Thus, logical forms play any role in such processes. it distinguishes between ‘mental models’ and ‘fully explicit models’. People immediately Thus, it seems that MM is revealing that and easily detect the mental models. However, formal approaches such as that of Rips (1994) the fully explicit models can only be noted if a or that of the mental logic theory (e.g., Braine & greater effort is made. Each logical connective, O’Brien, 1998a; O’Brien, 2009, 2014; O’Brien conjunction, disjunction, conditional, and & Li, 2013) must be overcome. However, this biconditional, has its models, but I will only last theory, the mental logic theory (from now consider here, as an example, the conditional. on, ML), is also coherent with many of the According to MM, a proposition such as ‘if A experimental ndings reported by the literature then B’ has a mental model: on cognitive science, and, for this reason, its proponents state that there is no conclusive A and B evidence that leads to its absolute rejection, and that the literature fails to demonstrate that it is a Nonetheless, its fully explicit models are mistaken or incorrect theory. the following: My aim in this paper is to show that, while A and B it is true that ML can offer arguments in its favor, ¬A and B it is also true that MM can easily respond to those arguments and that, if the proponents of ML ¬A and ¬B want their theory to continue to be an alternative Where ‘¬’ denotes negation. to be considered, they must necessarily clarify certain aspects of it. I will expose and explain In this way, it is not hard for MM to explain in details all of this in the next pages. To do phenomena such as the fact that the modus ponens that, I will base on not only works such as those rule is often less difcult than the modus tollens cited above, but also other papers in which rule for individuals (see, for example, Byrne & Civilizar Ciencias Sociales y Humanas 16 (31): 235-248, Julio-Diciembre de 2016 Some argument S that the mental logic theory need S to clarify to continue being 237 an alternative to the mental model S theory Johnson-Laird, 2009). As it is well known, the that human reasoning works following formal modus ponens schema is this one: rules and its adherents have proposed a number of such rules, which have not been selected ran - If A then B domly, but in accordance with empirical results. In other words, ML only accepts the formal rules A that, according to experiments reported in the li- ------------- terature on reasoning, people really use. Ergo B In this way, ML distinguishes different types of rules (see, e.g., Braine & O’Brien, Given that, as mentioned, the mental 1998b): ‘Core Schemas’, which are used as model of the conditional is ‘A and B’, it is often as possible, ‘Feeder Schemas’, which are evident, following MM, that, in a scenario in used as often as necessary, ‘Incompatibility which it is known that ‘if A then B’ and ‘A’ are Schemas’, which refer to contradictions, and true, most people will tend to draw that ‘B’ is ‘Other Schemas’, which play a limited role in true too. Nevertheless, the case of the modus the ‘Direct Reasoning Routine’ and are more tollens rule is different. As is also well known, linked to learned abilities. its schema is as follows: Core Schemas are a set of basic and If A then B simple rules. Some of them are, for example, a ¬B version of the modus tollendo ponens rule: ------------- A1 or… or An, ¬Ai; ergo A1 or… or Ai- Ergo ¬A 1or Ai+1 or… or An (schema 3 in Braine & O’Brien, 1998b, p. 80. ‘A1 or… or An’ and As can be noted, ‘¬A’ can only be derived ‘¬Ai’ are premises; on the other hand, what is from ‘if A then B’ and ‘¬B’ if the fully explicit after the word ‘ergo’, i.e., ‘A1 or… or Ai-1or Ai+1 or… or An’ is the conclusion).
Recommended publications
  • Principles of Logic Roehampton : Printed by John Griffin ^Principles of Logic
    PRINCIPLES OF LOGIC ROEHAMPTON : PRINTED BY JOHN GRIFFIN ^PRINCIPLES OF LOGIC By GEORGE HAYWARD JOYCE, S.J. M.A., ORIEL COLLEGE, OXFORD PROFESSOR OF LOGIC, ST. MARY S HALL, STONYHURST *.r LONGMANS, GREEN & CO 39, PATERNOSTER ROW, LONDON NEW YORK. BOMBAY, AND CALCUTTA 1908 INTRODUCTION THIS work is an attempt at a presentment of what is fre quently termed the Traditional Logic, and is intended for those who are making acquaintance with philosophical questions for the first time. Yet it is impossible, even in a text-book such as this, to deal with logical questions save in connexion with definite metaphysical and epistemolo- gical principles. Logic, as the theory of the mind s rational processes in regard of their validity, must neces sarily be part of a larger philosophical system. Indeed when this is not the case, it becomes a mere collection of technical rules, possessed of little importance and of less interest. The point of view adopted in this book is that of the Scholastic as far as is philosophy ; and compatible with the size and purpose of the work, some attempt has been made to vindicate the fundamental principles on which that philosophy is based. From one point of view, this position should prove a source of strength. The thinkers who elaborated our sys tem of Logic, were Scholastics. With the principles of that philosophy, its doctrines and its rules are in full accord. In the light of Scholasticism, the system is a connected whole ; and the subjects, traditionally treated in it, have each of them its legitimate place.
    [Show full text]
  • Truth Determinants. Another Theory of Meaning for the Propositional Connectives
    Philosophica 19, 1977 (1), pp. 11-32 11 TRUTH DETERMINANTS. ANOTHER THEORY OF MEANING FOR THE PROPOSITIONAL CONNECTIVES Niels Egmont Christensen --- The aim of this paper is to show that the truth-functional theory of meaning of the propositional connectives could be contrasted with another related, so-called truth-determinantal theory. With both theories and their ensuing different logics at hand we understand better the inadequacy of truth-functional logic and the difficulties in trying to make up for its shortcomings. 1. Introduction When raising the question about the philosophical relevance of the concept of meaning, the answer is in a sense both immediate and 1 impressive. For as Michael Dummett, in particular, has pointed out , there is, according to Frege, one part of philosophy that is the basis on which all other disciplines rest, viz. the theory of meaning. This has not always been the view of philosophers; Descartes, for instance, and many of his followers saw epistemology as the fundamental theory on which all other forms of philosophy should be based. But if we are prepared to take the Fregean approach and to admit instead theory of meaning as the starting point of philosophy there are two things to note. First, this order of approach will never prevent us from moving on from theory of meaning to questions about what we know and how to justify it. Merely we should be clear about the meaning of epistemological words before entering into a territory that difficult. Second, being clear about the meaning of a philosophical interesting word is very seldom, if ever, the same as to be able in language, ones own or in another language, to state the meaning of the wo rd in question.
    [Show full text]
  • CHAPTER 3 Methods of Inference
    04-108 C03 p115-188 pp3 8/30/04 2:48 PM Page 115 CHAPTER 3 Methods of Inference 3.1 INTRODUCTION This chapter is an introduction to reasoning about knowledge. It is important to separate the meaning of the words used in reasoning from the reasoning itself so we will cover it in a formal way by discussing various methods of inference (Russell 03). In particular we will look at an important type of reasoning in ex- pert systems in which conclusions follow from facts by using rules. It is particu- larly important in expert systems because making inferences is the fundamental method by which expert systems solve problems (Klir 98). As mentioned in Chapter 1, expert systems are commonly used when an in- adequate algorithm or no algorithmic solution exists. The expert system should make a chain of inferences to come up with a solution just as a person would, especially when faced with incomplete or missing information. A simple com- puter program that uses an algorithm to solve a problem cannot supply an answer if all the parameters needed are not given. However an expert system makes a best guess just like a human would when a problem needs to be solved and the optimum solution cannot be determined. The idea is to come up with a solution just as people come up with a (hopefully) good solution rather than none at all. While the solution may only be 95% as ef- ficient as the optimum solution, that’s still better than no solution. This type of approach is really nothing new.
    [Show full text]
  • A Dictionary of PHILOSOPHICAL LOGIC
    a dictionary of a dictionary of PHILOSOPHICAL LOGIC This dictionary introduces undergraduate and graduate students PHILOSOPHICAL LOGIC in philosophy, mathematics, and computer science to the main problems and positions in philosophical logic. Coverage includes not only key figures, positions, terminology, and debates within philosophical logic itself, but issues in related, overlapping disciplines such as set theory and the philosophy of mathematics as well. Entries are extensively cross-referenced, so that each entry can be easily located within the context of wider debates, thereby providing a dictionary of a valuable reference both for tracking the connections between concepts within logic and for examining the manner in which these PHILOSOPHICAL LOGIC concepts are applied in other philosophical disciplines. Roy T. Cook is Assistant Professor in the Department of Philosophy at Roy T. Cook the University of Minnesota and an Associate Fellow at Arché, the Philosophical Research Centre for Logic, Language, Metaphysics and Epistemology at the University of St Andrews. He works primarily in the philosophy of logic, language, and mathematics, and has also Cook Roy T. published papers on seventeenth-century philosophy. ISBN 978 0 7486 2559 8 Edinburgh University Press E 22 George Square dinburgh Edinburgh EH8 9LF www.euppublishing.com Cover image: www.istockphoto.com Cover design: www.paulsmithdesign.com 1004 01 pages i-vi:Layout 1 16/2/09 15:18 Page i A DICTIONARY OF PHILOSOPHICAL LOGIC 1004 01 pages i-vi:Layout 1 16/2/09 15:18 Page ii Dedicated to my mother, Carol C. Cook, who made sure that I got to learn all this stuff, and to George Schumm, Stewart Shapiro, and Neil Tennant, who taught me much of it.
    [Show full text]
  • Chrysippus' Indemonstrables and Mental Logic
    Croatian Journal of Philosophy Vol. XV, No. 43, 2015 Chrysippus’ Indemonstrables and Mental Logic MIGUEL LÓPEZ-ASTORGA Institute of Humanistic Studies “Juan Ignacio Molina” Talca University, Chile Stoic logic assumes fi ve inference schemata attributed to Chrysippus of Soli. Those schemata are the well-known indemonstrables. A problem related to them can be that, according to standard propositional calcu- lus, only one of them, modus ponens, is clearly indemonstrable. Never- theless, I try to show in this paper that the mental logic theory enables to understand why the Stoics considered such schemata to be basic kinds of arguments. Following that theory, four of them can be linked to ‘Core Schemata’ of mental logic and the only one that is more controversial is modus tollens. However, as I also comment, some assumptions of Stoic philosophy, which can be interpreted from the mental logic theory, can explain why this last argument was included into the set of the indemon- strables as well. Keywords: Classical logic, indemonstrable, mental logic, reasoning schemata, Stoic. Introduction The basic arguments that, according to Stoic logic lead inferences are the fi ve indemonstrables: modus ponens, modus tollendo ponens, mo- dus ponendo tollens (1), modus ponendo tollens (2), and modus tollens. Chrysippus of Soli is said to be the philosopher that identifi ed them. For example, Sextus Empiricus, in Adversus Mathematicos 8.223, states this fact. It is true that, as indicated by O’Toole and Jennings (2004), there is a certain discussion regarding this point. Nonetheless, what is important for this paper is that the Stoic idea seems to be that those fi ve schemata are rules that cannot be proved and that, however, serve to demonstrate all the other inferences.
    [Show full text]
  • Gödel's Basic Logic Course at Notre Dame
    Logic Lectures G¨odel’s Basic Logic Course at Notre Dame Edited by Miloˇs Adˇzic´ and Kosta Doˇsen Faculty of Philosophy, University of Belgrade Cikaˇ Ljubina 18-20, 11000 Belgrade, Serbia, and Mathematical Institute, Serbian Academy of Sciences and Arts Knez Mihailova 36, p.f. 367, 11001 Belgrade, Serbia email: [email protected], [email protected] April 2017 arXiv:1705.02601v3 [math.HO] 16 Jun 2017 LOGIC LECTURES iii Abstract. An edited version is given of the text of G¨odel’s unpublished manuscript of the notes for a course in basic logic he delivered at the University of Notre Dame in 1939. G¨odel’s notes deal with what is today considered as important logical problems par excellence, completeness, decidability, independence of axioms, and with natural deduction too, which was all still a novelty at the time the course was delivered. Full of regards towards beginners, the notes are not excessively formalistic. G¨odel presumably intended them just for himself, and they are full of abbreviations. This together with some other matters (like two versions of the same topic, and guessing the right order of the pages) required additional effort to obtain a readable edited version. Because of the quality of the material provided by G¨odel, including also important philosophical points, this effort should however be worthwhile. The edited version of the text is accompanied by another version, called the source version, which is quite close to G¨odel’s manuscript. It is meant to be a record of the editorial interventions involved in producing the edited version (in particular, how the abbreviations were disabridged), and a justification of that later version.
    [Show full text]
  • Hegel's Modal Ontological Argument
    THE CATHOLIC UNIVERSITY OF AMERICA Hegel’s Modal Ontological Argument A DISSERTATION Submitted to the Faculty of the School of Philosophy Of The Catholic University of America In Partial Fulfillment of the Requirements For the Degree Doctor of Philosophy © Copyright All Rights Reserved By David Pensgard Washington, D.C. 2019 Hegel’s Modal Ontological Argument David Pensgard, PhD Director: Antón Barba-Kay, PhD A recent trend in Hegel scholarship has recognized an irreducibly metaphysical component. Unlike traditional metaphysical views, this trend, sometimes referred to as the revised metaphysical view, accepts significant Kantian influence on Hegel, but also sees a rebuttal and counter-critique. Such a Hegel avoids the excesses of traditional metaphysics, including ontotheological speculation, but does not avoid metaphysics altogether. To extend this effort to understand Hegel’s metaphysics, without suggesting an argument for the existence of God, I here point to Hegel’s ontological argument as the one, indispensable interpretational key that he himself has provided for this purpose. Unfortunately, this argument is not only hard to detect because of the way Hegel presents it, but it is also difficult to accept because it takes a very unexpected form; it is a deduction in the ordinary sense. Perhaps without exception, scholars today think that Hegel could not possibly be using a deduction because deductive logic is considered to be antithetical to his project. It is true that Hegel criticized logic’s traditional practice for being dogmatic, and he did detect oppositional themes within the method of deduction itself, but Hegel neither condemned nor abandoned deduction. Instead, he worked to redeem it by purging its practice of two errors: presupposition and finitude.
    [Show full text]
  • Logic) 1 1.1 Formal Notation
    Universal generalization From Wikipedia, the free encyclopedia Contents 1 Absorption (logic) 1 1.1 Formal notation ............................................ 1 1.2 Examples ............................................... 1 1.3 Proof by truth table .......................................... 2 1.4 Formal proof ............................................. 2 1.5 References ............................................... 2 2 Associative property 3 2.1 Definition ............................................... 3 2.2 Generalized associative law ...................................... 4 2.3 Examples ............................................... 4 2.4 Propositional logic .......................................... 7 2.4.1 Rule of replacement ..................................... 7 2.4.2 Truth functional connectives ................................. 7 2.5 Non-associativity ........................................... 7 2.5.1 Nonassociativity of floating point calculation ......................... 8 2.5.2 Notation for non-associative operations ........................... 8 2.6 See also ................................................ 10 2.7 References ............................................... 10 3 Axiom 11 3.1 Etymology ............................................... 11 3.2 Historical development ........................................ 12 3.2.1 Early Greeks ......................................... 12 3.2.2 Modern development ..................................... 12 3.2.3 Other sciences ......................................... 13 3.3 Mathematical
    [Show full text]
  • A 4-Valued Logic of Strong Conditional Introduction
    South American Journal of Logic Vol. 3, n. 1, pp. 59{86, 2017 ISSN: 2446-6719 A 4-valued Logic of Strong Conditional Fabien Schang Abstract How to say no less, no more about conditional than what is needed? From a logical analysis of necessary and sufficient conditions (Section 1), we ar- gue that a stronger account of conditional can be obtained in two steps: firstly, by reminding its historical roots inside modal logic and set-theory (Section 2); secondly, by revising the meaning of logical values, thereby getting rid of the paradoxes of material implication whilst showing the bivalent roots of conditional as a speech-act based on affirmations and re- jections (Section 3). Finally, the two main inference rules for conditional, viz. Modus Ponens and Modus Tollens, are reassessed through a broader definition of logical consequence that encompasses both a normal relation of truth propagation and a weaker relation of falsity non-propagation from premises to conclusion (Section 3). Keywords: Bilateralism, Conditional, Connection, Modi, Relevance. Introduction: Elementary, my dear Wason? Undergraduate students are currently introduced to logical conditional {or im- plication1, through an explanation in terms of truth-tables. Hence their sur- prised faces, when confronted to the truth of a conditional sentence whenever its antecedent is false. But this logical method is neither the only one nor the best one. The literature on logical conditional is tremendous and some of its most famous developments intended to achieve the same purpose as ours, namely: to give a better definition of logical conditional, by getting rid of its undesired properties in classical logic.
    [Show full text]
  • A RESPONSE to LIU and CHOU (2012) and to LÓPEZ ASTORGA (2013) Universum
    Universum. Revista de Humanidades y Ciencias Sociales ISSN: 0716-498X [email protected] Universidad de Talca Chile O’Brien, David P. CONDITIONALS AND DISJUNCTIONS IN MENTAL-LOGIC THEORY: A RESPONSE TO LIU AND CHOU (2012) AND TO LÓPEZ ASTORGA (2013) Universum. Revista de Humanidades y Ciencias Sociales, vol. 29, núm. 2, 2014, pp. 221-235 Universidad de Talca Talca, Chile Available in: http://www.redalyc.org/articulo.oa?id=65032873015 How to cite Complete issue Scientific Information System More information about this article Network of Scientific Journals from Latin America, the Caribbean, Spain and Portugal Journal's homepage in redalyc.org Non-profit academic project, developed under the open access initiative UNIVERSUM • Vol. 2 • Nº 29 • 2014 • Universidad de Talca Conditionals and disjunctions in mental-logic theory: A response to Liu and Chou (2012) and to López Astorga (2013) David P. O’Brien Pp. 221 a 235 CONDITIONALS AND DISJUNCTIONS IN MENTAL-LOGIC THEORY: A RESPONSE TO LIU AND CHOU (2012) AND TO LÓPEZ ASTORGA (2013) Condicionales y disyunciones en la teoría de la lógica mental: Una respuesta a Liu y Chou (2012) y a López Astorga (2013) David P. O’Brien* ABSTRACT Liu and Chou (2012) presented a two-step theory to describe reasoning both on the four traditional conditional syllogisms and on four parallel syllogisms that replace the conditional with a disjunction. Tis article proposes that although Liu and Chou show that the words if and or play an important role in generating the data they report, their theory provides no explanation of how these words play any role.
    [Show full text]
  • The Basics of Formal Logic
    MGIMO University School of Government and International Affairs Syllabus approved Dean, The MGIMO School of Government and International Affairs Mikhail Troitskiy « » 2021 The Basics of Formal Logic Undergraduate Course Syllabus Instructor Prof. Nikolai Biryukov © Nikolai Biryukov, 2021 © MGIMO University, 2021 This syllabus is designed in accordance with the MGIMO Educational Standard for the Bachelor Program in Economics. Author ________________Prof. Nikolai Biryukov Director MGIMO Library__________Marina Reshetnikova Logic has been traditionally defined as the study of principles (laws), forms, methods and rules of thought, primarily reasoning. It should, however, be understood that even though principles (laws), forms, methods and rules of thought studied by logic can be traced to earlier practices of human thinking, their expounded versions have, in fact, been invented by logicians themselves in an attempt to develop and perfect a universal tool of theoretical thought. Logic is, therefore, better described and understood as an artificial language specially devised for and adapted to needs of theoretical discourse, including that of science. Scientific disciplines that lay at the core of university-level education can hardly be adequately comprehended without mastering this language. However, by the 19th century the language of traditional logic created and conceptualised by Aristotle more than two millennia earlier and sophisticated by generations of scholars throughout Antiquity, Middle Ages and Modern Times exhausted its potential and seized to fully meet the needs of sciences. A new language was required, more complex and more powerful, and that requirement has been met by mathematical (symbolic) logic. Nevertheless, since most classical scientific writings read at higher schools and universities date from the times that preceded symbolic logic, traditional formal logic suffices for their understanding as well as the understanding of their contemporary expositions.
    [Show full text]
  • A Response to Liu and Chou (2012) and to López Astorga (2013) David P
    6/*7&346.t7PMt/tt6OJWFSTJEBEEF5BMDB Conditionals and disjunctions in mental-logic theory: A response to Liu and Chou (2012) and to López Astorga (2013) David P. O’Brien Pp. 221 a 235 CONDITIONALS AND DISJUNCTIONS IN MENTAL-LOGIC THEORY: A RESPONSE TO LIU AND CHOU (2012) AND TO LÓPEZ ASTORGA (2013) Condicionales y disyunciones en la teoría de la lógica mental: Una respuesta a Liu y Chou (2012) y a López Astorga (2013) David P. O’Brien* ABSTRACT Liu and Chou (2012) presented a two-step theory to describe reasoning both on the four traditional conditional syllogisms and on four parallel syllogisms that replace the conditional with a disjunction. This article proposes that although Liu and Chou show that the words if and or play an important role in generating the data they report, their theory provides no explanation of how these words play any role. The article also corrects an assertion by López Astorga (2013) that mental-logic theory accounts for the findings of Liu and Chou by interpreting if as the material conditional. Instead I show why mental-logic theory rejects the material conditional and accounts for the data using a procedural- semantics approach to the meaning of logic particles. The article concludes that a theory like that of Liu and Chou requires something like mental-logic theory to account for their data. Keywords: Mental logic, reasoning, modus ponens, modus tollens, conditional reasoning, deductive reasoning, disjunctions, probabilistic reasoning. RESUMEN Liu y Chou (2012) plantearon una teoría de dos pasos para describir el razonamiento tanto con respecto a los silogismos condicionales tradicionales como en lo relativo a cuatro silogismos paralelos que reemplazan el condicional por una disyunción.
    [Show full text]