Optimal Partitions in Additively Separable Hedonic Games∗

Total Page:16

File Type:pdf, Size:1020Kb

Optimal Partitions in Additively Separable Hedonic Games∗ Proceedings of the Twenty-Second International Joint Conference on Artificial Intelligence Optimal Partitions in Additively Separable Hedonic Games∗ Haris Aziz Felix Brandt Hans Georg Seedig Department of Informatics Technische Universitat¨ Munchen¨ 85748 Garching bei Munchen,¨ Germany {aziz,brandtf,seedigh}@in.tum.de Abstract form just as much as the formation of coalitions depends on how the payoffs are distributed. We conduct a computational analysis of fair and Coalition formation games, as introduced by Dreze` and optimal partitions in additively separable hedonic Greenberg [1980], provide a simple but versatile formal games. We show that, for strict preferences, a model that allows one to focus on coalition formation as such. Pareto optimal partition can be found in polynomial In many situations it is natural to assume that a player’s appre- time while verifying whether a given partition is ciation of a coalition structure only depends on the coalition Pareto optimal is coNP-complete, even when pref- he is a member of and not on how the remaining players are erences are symmetric and strict. Moreover, com- grouped. Initiated by Banerjee et al. [2001] and Bogomolnaia puting a partition with maximum egalitarian or util- and Jackson [2002], much of the work on coalition formation itarian social welfare or one which is both Pareto now concentrates on these so-called hedonic games. optimal and individually rational is NP-hard. We The main focus in hedonic games has been on notions of also prove that checking whether there exists a par- stability for coalition structures such as Nash stability, indi- tition which is both Pareto optimal and envy-free vidual stability, contractual individual stability, or core stabil- is Σp-complete. Even though an envy-free partition 2 ity and characterizing conditions under which they are guar- and a Nash stable partition are both guaranteed to anteed to be non-empty [see, e.g., Bogomolnaia and Jackson, exist for symmetric preferences, checking whether 2002]. The most prominent examples of hedonic games are there exists a partition which is both envy-free and two-sided matching games in which only coalitions of size Nash stable is NP-complete. two are admissible [Roth and Sotomayor, 1990]. General coalition formation games have also received at- 1 Introduction tention from the artificial intelligence community, where the focus has generally been on computing partitions that give Ever since the publication of von Neumann and Morgen- rise to the greatest social welfare [see, e.g., Sandholm et stern’s Theory of Games and Economic Behavior in 1944, al., 1999]. The computational complexity of hedonic games coalitions have played a central role within game theory. The has been investigated with a focus on the complexity of crucial questions in coalitional game theory are which coali- computing stable partitions for different models of hedonic tions can be expected to form and how the members of coali- games [Ballester, 2004; Dimitrov et al., 2006; Cechlarov´ a,´ tions should divide the proceeds of their cooperation. Tra- 2008]. We refer to Hajdukova´ [2006] for a critical overview. ditionally the focus has been on the latter issue, which led to Among hedonic games, additively separable hedonic the formulation and analysis of concepts such as Gillie’s core, games (ASHGs) are a particularly natural and succinct rep- the Shapley value, or the bargaining set. Which coalitions resentation in which each player has a value for every other are likely to form is commonly assumed to be settled exoge- player and the value of a coalition to a particular player is nously, either by explicitly specifying the coalition structure, computed by simply adding his values of the players in his a partition of the players in disjoint coalitions, or, implicitly, coalition. by assuming that larger coalitions can invariably guarantee Additive separability satisfies a number of desirable ax- better outcomes to its members than smaller ones and that, as iomatic properties [Barbera` et al., 2004]. ASHGs are the a consequence, the grand coalition of all players will eventu- non-transferable utility generalization of graph games stud- ally form. ied by Deng and Papadimitriou [1994]. Sung and Dimitrov The two questions, however, are clearly interdependent: ff [2010] showed that for ASHGs, checking whether a core sta- the individual players’ payo s depend on the coalitions that ble, strict-core stable, Nash stable, or individually stable par- ∗This material is based on work supported by the Deutsche tition exists is NP-hard. Dimitrov et al. [2006] obtained posi- Forschungsgemeinschaft under grants BR-2312/6-1 (within the Eu- tive algorithmic results for subclasses of additively separable ropean Science Foundation’s EUROCORES program LogICCC) hedonic games in which each player divides other players into and BR 2312/7-1. friends and enemies. Branzei and Larson [2009] examined 43 ff ∈N the tradeo between stability and social welfare in ASHGs. coalition as i and if i is in coalition S i, then i gets utility , ∈N j∈S \{i} vi( j). For coalitions S T i, S i T if and only if ≥ j∈S \{i} vi( j) j∈T\{i} vi( j). Contribution In this paper, we analyze concepts from fair = division in the context of coalition formation games. We A preference profile is symmetric if vi( j) v j(i) for any two players i, j ∈ N and is strict if vi( j) 0 for all i, j ∈ N present the first systematic examination of the complexity of computing and verifying optimal partitions of hedonic games, such that i j. We consider ASHGs (additively separable specifically ASHGs. We examine various standard criteria hedonic games) in this paper. Unless mentioned otherwise, from the social sciences: Pareto optimality, utilitarian social all our results are for ASHGs. welfare, egalitarian social welfare, and envy-freeness [see, e.g., Moulin, 1988]. 2.2 Fair and optimal partitions In Section 3, we show that computing a partition with max- In this section, we formulate concepts from the social sci- imum egalitarian social welfare is NP-hard. Similarly, com- ences, especially the literature on fair division, for the context puting a partition with maximum utilitarian social welfare is of hedonic games. A partition π satisfies individual rational- NP-hard in the strong sense even when preferences are sym- ity if each player does as well as by being alone, i.e., for all metric and strict. i ∈ N, π(i) i {i}. For a utility-based hedonic game (N, P) and In Section 4, the complexity of Pareto optimality is studied. partition π, we will denote the utility of player i ∈ N by uπ(i). We prove that checking whether a given partition is Pareto op- The different notions of fair or optimal partitions are defined timal is coNP-complete in the strong sense, even when pref- as follows.2 erences are strict and symmetric. By contrast, we present a 1. The utilitarian social welfare of a partition is defined as polynomial-time algorithm for computing a Pareto optimal the sum of individual utilities of the players: u (π) = partition when preferences are strict.1 Interestingly, comput- ut uπ(i). A maximum utilitarian partition maximizes ing an individually rational and Pareto optimal partition is i∈N the utilitarian social welfare. NP-hard in general. In Section 5, we consider complexity questions regarding 2. The elitist social welfare is given by the utility of the envy-free partitions. Checking whether there exists a parti- player that is best off: uel(π) = max{uπ(i) | i ∈ N}.A tion which is both Pareto optimal and envy-free is shown to maximum elitist partition maximizes the utilitarian so- be Σp-complete. We present an example which exemplifies cial welfare. 2 ff the tradeo between satisfying stability (such as Nash sta- 3. The egalitarian social welfare is given by the utility of bility) and envy-freeness and use the example to prove that the agent that is worst off: ueg(π) = min{uπ(i) | i ∈ N}. checking whether there exists a partition which is both envy- A maximum egalitarian partition maximizes the egali- free and Nash stable is NP-complete even when preferences tarian social welfare. are symmetric. 4. A partition π of N is Pareto optimal if there exists no partition π of N which Pareto dominates π, that is for 2 Preliminaries all i ∈ N, π (i) i π(i) and there exists at least one player In this section, we provide the terminology and notation re- j ∈ N such that j ∈ N, π ( j) j π( j). quired for our results. 5. Envy-freeness is a notion of fairness. In an envy-free 2.1 Hedonic games partition, no player has an incentive to replace another player. A hedonic coalition formation game is a pair (N, P) where N is a set of players and P is a preference profile which specifies For the sake of brevity, we will call all the notions de- for each player i ∈ N the preference relation i, a reflexive, scribed above “optimality criteria” although envy-freeness is complete and transitive binary relation on set Ni = {S ⊆ N | rather concerned with fairness than optimality. We consider i ∈ S }. the following computational problems with respect to the S i T denotes that i strictly prefers S over T and S ∼i T optimality criteria defined above. that i is indifferent between coalitions S and T.Apartition π is a partition of players N into disjoint coalitions. By π(i), we Optimality: Given (N, P) and a partition π of N,isπ optimal? denote the coalition in π which includes player i. Existence: Does an optimal partition for a given (N, P) exist? A game (N, P)isseparable if for any player i ∈ N and any Search: If an optimal partition for a given (N, P) exists, find coalition S ∈Ni and for any player j not in S we have the one.
Recommended publications
  • Pareto Optimality in Coalition Formation
    Pareto Optimality in Coalition Formation Haris Aziz NICTA and University of New South Wales, 2033 Sydney, Australia Felix Brandt∗ Technische Universit¨atM¨unchen,80538 M¨unchen,Germany Paul Harrenstein University of Oxford, Oxford OX1 3QD, United Kingdom Abstract A minimal requirement on allocative efficiency in the social sciences is Pareto op- timality. In this paper, we identify a close structural connection between Pareto optimality and perfection that has various algorithmic consequences for coali- tion formation. Based on this insight, we formulate the Preference Refinement Algorithm (PRA) which computes an individually rational and Pareto optimal outcome in hedonic coalition formation games. Our approach also leads to var- ious results for specific classes of hedonic games. In particular, we show that computing and verifying Pareto optimal partitions in general hedonic games, anonymous games, three-cyclic games, room-roommate games and B-hedonic games is intractable while both problems are tractable for roommate games, W-hedonic games, and house allocation with existing tenants. Keywords: Coalition Formation, Hedonic Games, Pareto Optimality, Computational Complexity JEL: C63, C70, C71, and C78 1. Introduction Ever since the publication of von Neumann and Morgenstern's Theory of Games and Economic Behavior in 1944, coalitions have played a central role within game theory. The crucial questions in coalitional game theory are which coalitions can be expected to form and how the members of coalitions should divide the proceeds of their cooperation. Traditionally the focus has been on the latter issue, which led to the formulation and analysis of concepts such as ∗Corresponding author Email addresses: [email protected] (Haris Aziz), [email protected] (Felix Brandt), [email protected] (Paul Harrenstein) Preprint submitted to Elsevier August 27, 2013 the core, the Shapley value, or the bargaining set.
    [Show full text]
  • Pareto-Optimality in Cardinal Hedonic Games
    Research Paper AAMAS 2020, May 9–13, Auckland, New Zealand Pareto-Optimality in Cardinal Hedonic Games Martin Bullinger Technische Universität München München, Germany [email protected] ABSTRACT number of agents, and therefore it is desirable to consider expres- Pareto-optimality and individual rationality are among the most nat- sive, but succinctly representable classes of hedonic games. This ural requirements in coalition formation. We study classes of hedo- can be established by encoding preferences by means of a complete nic games with cardinal utilities that can be succinctly represented directed weighted graph where an edge weight EG ¹~º is a cardinal by means of complete weighted graphs, namely additively separable value or utility that agent G assigns to agent ~. Still, this underlying (ASHG), fractional (FHG), and modified fractional (MFHG) hedo- structure leaves significant freedom, how to obtain (cardinal) pref- nic games. Each of these can model different aspects of dividing a erences over coalitions. An especially appealing type of preferences society into groups. For all classes of games, we give algorithms is to have the sum of values of the other individuals as the value that find Pareto-optimal partitions under some natural restrictions. of a coalition. This constitutes the important class of additively While the output is also individually rational for modified fractional separable hedonic games (ASHGs) [6]. hedonic games, combining both notions is NP-hard for symmetric In ASHGs, an agent is willing to accept an additional agent into ASHGs and FHGs. In addition, we prove that welfare-optimal and her coalition as long as her valuation of this agent is non-negative Pareto-optimal partitions coincide for simple, symmetric MFHGs, and in this sense, ASHGs are not sensitive to the intensities of single- solving an open problem from Elkind et al.
    [Show full text]
  • Optimizing Expected Utility and Stability in Role Based Hedonic Games
    Proceedings of the Thirtieth International Florida Artificial Intelligence Research Society Conference Optimizing Expected Utility and Stability in Role Based Hedonic Games Matthew Spradling University of Michigan - Flint mjspra@umflint.edu Abstract Table 1: Ex. RBHG instance with |P | =4,R= {A, B} In the hedonic coalition formation game model Roles Based r, c u (r, c) u (r, c) u (r, c) u (r, c) Hedonic Games (RBHG), agents view teams as compositions p0 p1 p2 p3 of available roles. An agent’s utility for a partition is based A, AA 2200 upon which roles she and her teammates fulfill within the A, AB 0322 coalition. I show positive results for finding optimal or sta- B,AB 3033 ble role matchings given a partitioning into teams. In set- B,BB 1111 tings such as massively multiplayer online games, a central authority assigns agents to teams but not necessarily to roles within them. For such settings, I consider the problems of op- timizing expected utility and expected stability in RBHG. I As per (Spradling and Goldsmith 2015), a Role Based He- show that the related optimization problems for partitioning donic Game (RBHG) instance consists of: are NP-hard. I introduce a local search heuristic method for • P approximating such solutions. I validate the heuristic by com- : A population of players parison to existing partitioning approaches using real-world • R: A set of roles data scraped from League of Legends games. • C: A set of compositions, where a composition c ∈ C is a multiset (bag) of roles from R. Introduction • U : P × R × C → Z defines the utility function ui(r, c) In coalition formation games, agents from a population have for each player pi.
    [Show full text]
  • The Dynamics of Europe's Political Economy
    Die approbierte Originalversion dieser Dissertation ist in der Hauptbibliothek der Technischen Universität Wien aufgestellt und zugänglich. http://www.ub.tuwien.ac.at The approved original version of this thesis is available at the main library of the Vienna University of Technology. http://www.ub.tuwien.ac.at/eng DISSERTATION The Dynamics of Europe’s Political Economy: a game theoretical analysis Ausgeführt zum Zwecke der Erlangung des akademischen Grades einer Doktorin der Sozial- und Wirtschaftswissenschaften unter der Leitung von Univ.-Prof. Dr. Hardy Hanappi Institut für Stochastik und Wirtschaftsmathematik (E105) Forschunggruppe Ökonomie Univ.-Prof. Dr. Pasquale Tridico Institut für Volkswirtschaftslehre, Universität Roma Tre eingereicht an der Technischen Universität Wien Fakultät für Mathematik und Geoinformation von Mag. Gizem Yildirim Matrikelnummer: 0527237 Hohlweggasse 10/10, 1030 Wien Wien am Mai 2017 Acknowledgements I would like to thank Professor Hardy Hanappi for his guidance, motivation and patience. I am grateful for inspirations from many conversations we had. He was always very generous with his time and I had a great freedom in my research. I also would like to thank Professor Pasquale Tridico for his interest in my work and valuable feedbacks. The support from my family and friends are immeasurable. I thank my parents and my brother for their unconditional and unending love and support. I am incredibly lucky to have great friends. I owe a tremendous debt of gratitude to Sarah Dippenaar, Katharina Schigutt and Markus Wallerberger for their support during my thesis but more importantly for sharing good and bad times. I also would like to thank Gregor Kasieczka for introducing me to jet clustering algorithms and his valuable suggestions.
    [Show full text]
  • Fractional Hedonic Games
    Fractional Hedonic Games HARIS AZIZ, Data61, CSIRO and UNSW Australia FLORIAN BRANDL, Technical University of Munich FELIX BRANDT, Technical University of Munich PAUL HARRENSTEIN, University of Oxford MARTIN OLSEN, Aarhus University DOMINIK PETERS, University of Oxford The work we present in this paper initiated the formal study of fractional hedonic games, coalition formation games in which the utility of a player is the average value he ascribes to the members of his coalition. Among other settings, this covers situations in which players only distinguish between friends and non-friends and desire to be in a coalition in which the fraction of friends is maximal. Fractional hedonic games thus not only constitute a natural class of succinctly representable coalition formation games, but also provide an interesting framework for network clustering. We propose a number of conditions under which the core of fractional hedonic games is non-empty and provide algorithms for computing a core stable outcome. By contrast, we show that the core may be empty in other cases, and that it is computationally hard in general to decide non-emptiness of the core. 1 INTRODUCTION Hedonic games present a natural and versatile framework to study the formal aspects of coalition formation which has received much attention from both an economic and an algorithmic perspective. This work was initiated by Drèze and Greenberg[1980], Banerjee et al . [2001], Cechlárová and Romero-Medina[2001], and Bogomolnaia and Jackson[2002] and has sparked a lot of follow- up work. A recent survey was provided by Aziz and Savani[2016]. In hedonic games, coalition formation is approached from a game-theoretic angle.
    [Show full text]
  • Pareto Optimality in Coalition Formation
    Pareto Optimality in Coalition Formation Haris Aziz Felix Brandt Paul Harrenstein Technische Universität München IJCAI Workshop on Social Choice and Artificial Intelligence, July 16, 2011 1 / 21 Coalition formation “Coalition formation is of fundamental importance in a wide variety of social, economic, and political problems, ranging from communication and trade to legislative voting. As such, there is much about the formation of coalitions that deserves study.” A. Bogomolnaia and M. O. Jackson. The stability of hedonic coalition structures. Games and Economic Behavior. 2002. 2 / 21 Coalition formation 3 / 21 Hedonic Games A hedonic game is a pair (N; ) where N is a set of players and = (1;:::; jNj) is a preference profile which specifies for each player i 2 N his preference over coalitions he is a member of. For each player i 2 N, i is reflexive, complete and transitive. A partition π is a partition of players N into disjoint coalitions. A player’s appreciation of a coalition structure (partition) only depends on the coalition he is a member of and not on how the remaining players are grouped. 4 / 21 Classes of Hedonic Games Unacceptable coalition: player would rather be alone. General hedonic games: preference of each player over acceptable coalitions 1: f1; 2; 3g ; f1; 2g ; f1; 3gjf 1gk 2: f1; 2gjf 1; 2; 3g ; f1; 3g ; f2gk 3: f2; 3gjf 3gkf 1; 2; 3g ; f1; 3g Partition ff1g; f2; 3gg 5 / 21 Classes of Hedonic Games General hedonic games: preference of each player over acceptable coalitions Preferences over players extend to preferences over coalitions Roommate games: only coalitions of size 1 and 2 are acceptable.
    [Show full text]
  • 15 Hedonic Games Haris Azizaand Rahul Savanib
    Draft { December 5, 2014 15 Hedonic Games Haris Azizaand Rahul Savanib 15.1 Introduction Coalitions are a central part of economic, political, and social life, and coalition formation has been studied extensively within the mathematical social sciences. Agents (be they humans, robots, or software agents) have preferences over coalitions and, based on these preferences, it is natural to ask which coalitions are expected to form, and which coalition structures are better social outcomes. In this chapter, we consider coalition formation games with hedonic preferences, or simply hedonic games. The outcome of a coalition formation game is a partitioning of the agents into disjoint coalitions, which we will refer to synonymously as a partition or coalition structure. The defining feature of hedonic preferences is that every agent only cares about which agents are in its coalition, but does not care how agents in other coali- tions are grouped together (Dr`ezeand Greenberg, 1980). Thus, hedonic preferences completely ignore inter-coalitional dependencies. Despite their relative simplicity, hedonic games have been used to model many interesting settings, such as research team formation (Alcalde and Revilla, 2004), scheduling group activities (Darmann et al., 2012), formation of coalition governments (Le Breton et al., 2008), cluster- ings in social networks (see e.g., Aziz et al., 2014b; McSweeney et al., 2014; Olsen, 2009), and distributed task allocation for wireless agents (Saad et al., 2011). Before we give a formal definition of a hedonic game, we give a standard hedonic game from the literature that we will use as a running example (see e.g., Banerjee et al.
    [Show full text]
  • Issues of Fairness and Computation in Partition Problems
    Fair and Square: Issues of Fairness and Computation in Partition Problems Inaugural-Dissertation zur Erlangung des Doktorgrades der Mathematisch-Naturwissenschaftlichen Fakultät der Heinrich-Heine-Universität Düsseldorf vorgelegt von Nhan-Tam Nguyen aus Hilden Düsseldorf, Juli 2017 aus dem Institut für Informatik der Heinrich-Heine-Universität Düsseldorf Gedruckt mit der Genehmigung der Mathematisch-Naturwissenschaftlichen Fakultät der Heinrich-Heine-Universität Düsseldorf Referent: Prof. Dr. Jörg Rothe Koreferent: Prof. Dr. Edith Elkind Tag der mündlichen Prüfung: 20.12.2017 Selbstständigkeitserklärung Ich versichere an Eides Statt, dass die Dissertation von mir selbstständig und ohne unzulässige fremde Hilfe unter Beachtung der „Grundsätze zur Sicherung guter wissenschaftlicher Praxis an der Heinrich-Heine-Universität Düsseldorf“ erstellt worden ist. Desweiteren erkläre ich, dass ich eine Dissertation in der vorliegenden oder in ähnlicher Form noch bei keiner anderen Institution eingereicht habe. Teile dieser Arbeit wurden bereits in den folgenden Schriften veröffentlicht oder zur Begutach- tung eingereicht: Baumeister et al. [2014], Baumeister et al. [2017], Nguyen et al. [2015], Nguyen et al. [2018], Heinen et al. [2015], Nguyen and Rothe [2016], Nguyen et al. [2016]. Düsseldorf, 7. Juli 2017 Nhan-Tam Nguyen Acknowledgments First and foremost, I owe a debt of gratitude to Jörg Rothe, my advisor, for his positive en- couragement, understanding, patience, and for asking the right questions. I’m grateful for his guidance through the academic world. Dorothea Baumeister deserves much thanks for being my mentor and her thorough feedback. I’d like to thank Edith Elkind for agreeing to review my thesis and be part of my defense and examination, as well as for sharing the durian at AAMAS 2016 in Singapore.
    [Show full text]
  • Pareto-Optimality in Cardinal Hedonic Games
    Pareto-Optimality in Cardinal Hedonic Games Martin Bullinger Technische Universität München München, Germany [email protected] ABSTRACT number of agents, and therefore it is desirable to consider expres- Pareto-optimality and individual rationality are among the most nat- sive, but succinctly representable classes of hedonic games. This ural requirements in coalition formation. We study classes of hedo- can be established by encoding preferences by means of a complete nic games with cardinal utilities that can be succinctly represented directed weighted graph where an edge weight EG ¹~º is a cardinal by means of complete weighted graphs, namely additively separable value or utility that agent G assigns to agent ~. Still, this underlying (ASHG), fractional (FHG), and modified fractional (MFHG) hedo- structure leaves significant freedom, how to obtain (cardinal) pref- nic games. Each of these can model different aspects of dividing a erences over coalitions. An especially appealing type of preferences society into groups. For all classes of games, we give algorithms is to have the sum of values of the other individuals as the value that find Pareto-optimal partitions under some natural restrictions. of a coalition. This constitutes the important class of additively While the output is also individually rational for modified fractional separable hedonic games (ASHGs) [6]. hedonic games, combining both notions is NP-hard for symmetric In ASHGs, an agent is willing to accept an additional agent into ASHGs and FHGs. In addition, we prove that welfare-optimal and her coalition as long as her valuation of this agent is non-negative Pareto-optimal partitions coincide for simple, symmetric MFHGs, and in this sense, ASHGs are not sensitive to the intensities of single- solving an open problem from Elkind et al.
    [Show full text]
  • Graphical Hedonic Games of Bounded Treewidth
    Proceedings of the Thirtieth AAAI Conference on Artificial Intelligence (AAAI-16) Graphical Hedonic Games of Bounded Treewidth Dominik Peters Department of Computer Science University of Oxford, UK [email protected] p Abstract NP-hard to maximise social welfare; and it is often even Σ2- complete to identify hedonic games with non-empty core. Hedonic games are a well-studied model of coalition See Ballester (2004), Sung and Dimitrov (2010), Woeginger formation, in which selfish agents are partitioned into (2013), and Peters and Elkind (2015) for a selection of such disjoint sets and agents care about the make-up of the coalition they end up in. The computational problems results. of finding stable, optimal, or fair outcomes tend to be A standard criticism of hardness results such as these is that computationally intractable in even severely restricted they apply only in the worst case. Instances arising in practice instances of hedonic games. We introduce the notion of can be expected to show much more structure than the highly a graphical hedonic game and show that, in contrast, on contrived instances produced in 3SAT-reductions. In non- classes of graphical hedonic games whose underlying cooperative game theory, graphical games (Kearns, Littman, graphs are of bounded treewidth and degree, such prob- and Singh 2001) are an influential way to allow formalisation lems become easy. In particular, problems that can be of the notion of a ‘structured’ game. In a graphical game, specified through quantification over agents, coalitions, and (connected) partitions can be decided in linear time. agents form the vertices of an undirected graph, and each The proof is by reduction to monadic second order logic.
    [Show full text]
  • Hedonic Diversity Games
    Session 2E: Game Theory 1 AAMAS 2019, May 13-17, 2019, Montréal, Canada Hedonic Diversity Games Robert Bredereck Edith Elkind Ayumi Igarashi TU Berlin University of Oxford Kyushu University Berlin, Germany Oxford, U.K. Fukuoka, Japan [email protected] [email protected] [email protected] ABSTRACT homophilic preferences, while others have heterophilic preferences, We consider a coalition formation setting where each agent belongs i.e., they seek out coalitions with agents who are not like them. to one of the two types, and agents’ preferences over coalitions There is a very substantial body of research on homophily and are determined by the fraction of the agents of their own type in heterophily in group formation. It is well-known that in a variety of each coalition. This setting differs from the well-studied Schelling’s contexts, ranging from residential location [25, 28, 29] to classroom model in that some agents may prefer homogeneous coalitions, activities and friendship relations [22, 23], individuals prefer to while others may prefer to be members of a diverse group, or a be together with those who are similar to them. There are also group that mostly consists of agents of the other type. We model settings where agents prefer to be in a group with agents of the this setting as a hedonic game and investigate the existence of stable other type(s): for instance, in a coalition of buyers and sellers, a outcomes using hedonic games solution concepts. We show that a buyer prefers to be in a group with many other sellers and no core stable outcome may fail to exist and checking the existence of other buyers, so as to maximize their negotiating power.
    [Show full text]
  • Facultad De Economía Y Empresa Dpto. Análisis Económico Three
    Facultad de Economía y Empresa Dpto. Análisis Económico Three Essays on Game Theory and Social Choice Oihane Gallo1 2 Ph.D Thesis Advisors: Elena Inarra and Jorge Alcalde-Unzu Bilbao, 2020 1Dpto. Análisis Económico, Facultad de Economía y Empresa, Universidad del País Vasco (UPV/EHU), Av. Lehendakari Aguirre 83, 48015 Bilbao (SPAIN), , email: oi- [email protected], personal page: https://sites.google.com/site/oihanegallofernandez/. 2This research was supported by the Basque Government through scholarship PRE_2019_2_0116. (c)2020 OIHANE GALLO FERNANDEZ Acknowledgements After five years of hard work it is time to look back and realize how many people have supported me, not only when there were successes, but also when forces fal- tered. This adventure was not in my plans when I started my Master’s degree and if it had not been for one of my advisors, Elena Iñarra of the University of the Basque Country, I would never have embarked on it. I would like to thank Elena for choos- ing me, guiding me, and supporting me through this long process. The development of this dissertation would not have been possible without her patience and the time she has devoted to me. It was in my first workshop, in Vigo, where I met a person who would play a rele- vant role in my thesis. He is my advisor Jorge Alcalde-Unzu of the Public University of Navarre. He introduced me to a new field and even though the process has not been easy, he has always encouraged me to improve my reasoning and resolution skills.
    [Show full text]