Imagination and Harmony in Leibniz's Philosophy of Language

Total Page:16

File Type:pdf, Size:1020Kb

Imagination and Harmony in Leibniz's Philosophy of Language Philosophie Imagination and Harmony in Leibniz‘s Philosophy of Language Inaugural-Dissertation zur Erlangung des akademischen Grades „Dr. phil.― an der Westfälischen Wilhelms-Universität, Münster (Westf) Vorgelegt von: Lucia Oliveri aus Reggio Calabria 2016 Tag der mündlichen Prüfung: 20. Juli 2016 Dekan: Prof. Dr. Tobias Leuker Erstgutachter: Prof. Dr. Stephan Meier-Oeser Zweitgutachter: Prof. Dr. Thomas Leinkauf ACKNOWLEDGEMENT V INTRODUCTION VII THOUGHT AND JUDGMENT 1 1.1. Sketching the Problems of Nouveaux Essais: Some Preliminaries 3 1.1.1. About Ideas before Locke: Old Solutions to New Problems? 10 1.2. Leibniz‘s Arguments Against Locke 17 1.2.1. Leibniz as Interpreter of Locke 18 1.2.2. On the Distinction Between Ideas, Concepts, and Actual Thoughts 26 1.2.3. Actual Thoughts and the Distinction Between Perceptions and Concepts 29 1.2.4. The Process of Judging 34 1.2.5. Leibniz on Deceptive States and Error 41 1.2.6. Conclusion 45 1.3. Apperception, Reflection, and Consciousness 47 1.3.1. The Puzzle of Apperception 51 1.3.2. The Relation between Action and Perceptual activity: Putting it in Context 56 1.3.3. The Structure of Animal Action 61 1.3.4. Animal and Human Knowledge: Two Different Species of Knowledge 75 1.3.5. Instincts and Habits 80 1.3.6. Conclusion 83 1.4. The I-Perspective 85 1.4.1. Reflection 87 1.4.2. Descartes‘ Cogito as Truth of Fact and Consciousness 90 1.4.3. Leibniz‘s Criticism of Locke‘s Theory of Consciousness 95 1.4.4. Minute Perceptions and the Self 100 1.4.5. The I-Perspective: Conclusion 105 1.5. From the I- to the I-Thou Perspective 107 1.5.1. Aquinian Roots of Leibnitian conscientia 109 1.5.2. Conscientia as Social Knowledge 116 1.5.3. Ruling out Solipsism: Conscientia as Source of Social Knowledge 118 1.5.4. Commercium mentium 127 1.5.5. Conclusion 133 CONCEPTS AND IDEAS 135 2.1. Leibniz‘s Theory of Concepts 137 2.1.1. On the Cognitive Role of Signs and Imagination 137 2.1.2. The Priority of Thought over Language: Leibniz as Innatist 145 2.1.3. Leibniz as an Extreme Innatist? 148 2.1.4. Leibniz‘s Commitment to the Variety of the Stimulus Argument 158 2.2. Concepts as Possibilities 165 iii 2.2.1. The Chimerical Character of Locke‘s Ideas 165 2.2.2. Concepts as Possibilities and Finite Minds‘ Mathematization of the World 171 2.2.3. An Axiomatic Approach to Truths: Intensional Interpretation of Concepts 177 2.2.4. Typicality Effects: Between Psychological and Logical Use of Concepts 179 2.2.5. Essences and Beings 185 2.2.6. Leibniz‘s Conceptualism and the Necessity of the Ideas in God‘s Intellect 192 2.2.7. Necessary Truths and Truths of Facts 201 2.2.8. Conclusion 210 2.3. Ideas as Constraints on Thought 211 2.3.1. Concepts as abilities or dispositions 211 2.3.2. Dispositions and Leibniz‘s Theory of Substance 218 2.3.3. Dispositions to Truths and Ideas 221 2.3.4. Spontaneity and Self-Determination. 224 2.3.5. Innate Ideas as Constraints on Thought 231 2.3.6. Logical and Historical Order of Truths 234 2.3.7. Conclusion 238 THE MUTUAL DEVELOPMENT BETWEEN LANGUAGE AND THOUGHT 239 3.1. Constraints on Thought and Language: The Place of The Other 241 3.1.1. The Analogy between Mind and Body 241 3.1.2. Constraints on Thought and Language 244 3.1.3. Experiencing Other Minds and General Concepts 251 3.1.4. Innate Ideas and Generality 257 3.1.5. Innate Ideas and the Acquisition of Moral and Metaphysical Concepts 267 3.1.6. Conclusion: What is the Place of Harmony in All This? 271 3.2. The origins of languages 275 3.2.1. Blind Thoughts and Language Origins: Towards Articulated Sounds 276 3.2.2. Interjections 282 3.2.3. Etymology and Imagination 285 3.2.4. The Role of Blind Thoughts in Reasoning. A Case Study: Preposition 292 3.2.5. Constraints on Thought and Language Origins 298 3.2.6. Conclusion 308 CONCLUSION 309 BIBLIOGRAPHY 315 iv Acknowledgement Every achievement in life is like a journey. On your way to the end, there are people that accompany you through it. Some of them make it special. Others make you wish you‘d never met. Few of them make it possible, help you in finding orientation, support you with every aspect of your life and work. From each of these persons you will learn a lot and become stronger. I wish to thank few people and institutions that made this journey possible. My utmost gratitude goes to the Leibniz-Forschungsstelle of Münster, and especially to my supervisors Prof. Stephan Meier-Oeser and Prof. Thomas Leinkauf for their constant support. This work would have never found its way without the possibility of philosophical discussions on any topic concerning the philosophy of Leibniz and his historical background. I am grateful to Prof. Heinrich Shepers for his trust and support as well. I still remember when I was a master student and we met for the first time. To my question ―from which texts of Leibniz shall I begin?‖, he replied pointing at the critical edition. Thanks to the editors Stefan Jenschcke, Stefan Lorenz, Henrik Wels, but especially Herma Kliege-Biller and Gerhard Biller for introducing me to ―the art of the edition‖ and for their friendship. Thanks also to the rest of the team: Jörg Dieckhoff, Manon Dutz, Magdalene Grosse-Fattorini, Anne-Sophie Naujoks, Monja Reinheirt, Angelika Rüter. The Leibniz-Forschungsstelle became in these years like a second family to me, thank you. I would like to thank the Studienstiftung des Deutschen Volkes who funded my PhD research, as well as a short stay at Rutgers University, with a scholarship. I am deeply grateful to Martha B. Bolton, my sponsor at Rutgers, for intense discussions that made me gain more insight into both Leibniz‘s philosophy and my interpretation. Thanks also to my proof-reader, Josh Rosario, for his wonderful work on the text. Parts of this work have been presented at the Research Colloquium of Prof. Leinkauf. A special thanks to the participants: Christian Zeuch, Marc Heimann, Dorothee Zucker. Other parts were presented at the Research Colloquium in Philosophy of Paderbon University; at the Summer School epistemology and Cognition in Groningen; at the Dutch Seminar in Early Modern Philosophy in Nijmegen; at the Workshop Concepts and Categorization in Linguistics, Cognitive Science, and Philosophie at the University of Düsseldorf. The very first draft of the dissertation project was presented at the Scuola Normale Superiore in Pisa. I am thankful to people met during those events and especially to: Matteo Favaretti- Camposampiero, Stefano Di Bella, Elena Ficara, Stefano Gensini, David Hommen, Michael v Kempe, Martin Lenz, Wenchao Li, Cristina Marras, Massimo Mugnai, Antonio Maria Nunziante, Carla Rita Palmerino, Volker Peckhaus. Achievements are void if you cannot share them with family and friends. I am lucky to have a big family to thank. They know how much I love them. I would not have made it through the German winters without the following people: Nemanja, Iva, Armando, Felicitas, Jonas, Denitsa, Sebastian, Gianluca, Evelina, Iulia, Jonathan. A special thanks to Anna, Stefano, Luca, Francesco, Federico, Angelo Matteo, Giulia. Finally, I want to thank three persons who changed my life, supported me, and loved me all the way through this difficult path: my philosophy teacher in high school, Professoressa Maria Rita Abramo and her philosophy teacher in high-school, Professoressa Pina Spataro. My lovely husband, Matteo Bozzon. They believed me capable of things I would have never been able to achieve without their encouragement and love. This work is for you. vi Introduction The aim of the work is to inquire into Leibniz‘s conception of natural languages from a particular angle: his theory of the cognition of finite minds. Two basic theses structure his theory of human cognition. The first thesis can be labelled as cognitive necessity of signs and states that finite minds necessarily need signs or some other kind of characters to reason. The second thesis is what I call imagination thesis and claims that finite minds tend to represent through the imagination what is not subject to it. An analysis of Leibniz‘s theory of human cognition must answer the question of why finite minds‘ thinking activity needs languages or other kinds of characters. The result of my inquiry is the demonstration of a more substantial thesis directly derivable from cognitive necessity of signs and imagination thesis: a mutual development between language and thought. Finite minds cannot reason without a language intended as a syntactically and grammatically ruled system of signs. The developments of natural languages support a mind‘s cognitive stages of development of its reasoning capacity. A consequence of this view is that language and thought develop mutually. Languages are expedients of the human mind to overcome its cognitive and metaphysical limitations. Languages and in general any ruled system of signs enable a rational cognitive subject to evolve and develop its inborn cognitive skills. Given this function of language and assuming the imagination thesis, it follows that languages and thought evolve through cognitive stages: first minds acquire notions and express thoughts concerning sensible knowledge domain. Once they learn to manage this domain, minds reflect on sensible knowledge, develop more abstract notions, like knowledge about morality and metaphysics; motivated by cooperation with other peers, they learn to use their language figuratively, via tropes, to express knowledge of what is not subject to imagination.
Recommended publications
  • Philosophical Review
    Philosophical Review Main Trends in Recent Philosophy: Two Dogmas of Empiricism Author(s): W. V. Quine Source: The Philosophical Review, Vol. 60, No. 1 (Jan., 1951), pp. 20-43 Published by: Duke University Press on behalf of Philosophical Review Stable URL: http://www.jstor.org/stable/2181906 . Accessed: 19/01/2011 11:47 Your use of the JSTOR archive indicates your acceptance of JSTOR's Terms and Conditions of Use, available at . http://www.jstor.org/page/info/about/policies/terms.jsp. JSTOR's Terms and Conditions of Use provides, in part, that unless you have obtained prior permission, you may not download an entire issue of a journal or multiple copies of articles, and you may use content in the JSTOR archive only for your personal, non-commercial use. Please contact the publisher regarding any further use of this work. Publisher contact information may be obtained at . http://www.jstor.org/action/showPublisher?publisherCode=duke. Each copy of any part of a JSTOR transmission must contain the same copyright notice that appears on the screen or printed page of such transmission. JSTOR is a not-for-profit service that helps scholars, researchers, and students discover, use, and build upon a wide range of content in a trusted digital archive. We use information technology and tools to increase productivity and facilitate new forms of scholarship. For more information about JSTOR, please contact [email protected]. Duke University Press and Philosophical Review are collaborating with JSTOR to digitize, preserve and extend access to The Philosophical Review. http://www.jstor.org TWO DOGMAS OF EMPIRICISM' M ODERN empiricismhas been conditionedin large part by two dogmas.
    [Show full text]
  • Levels of Discourse in Leibniz's Metaphysics the Ontological Status of Bodies
    Levels of Discourse in Leibniz's Metaphysics The Ontological Status of Bodies: A Study of the Levels of Discourse in Leibniz's Metaphysics By SCOTT STAPLEFORD, B.A. A Thesis Submitted to the School of Graduate Studies in Partial Fulfilment of the Requirements for the Degree Master of Arts McMaster University C> Copyright by Scott Stapleford, August 1998 MASTER OF ARTS (1998) McMaster University (Philosophy) Hamilton, Ontario TITLE: The Ontological Status of Bodies: A Study of the Levels of Discourse in Leibniz's Metaphysics AUTHOR: Scott Stapleford, B.A. (Brock University) SUPERVISOR: Professor Wilfrid Waluchow NUMBER OF PAGES: iv, 169 ii Table of Contents Introduction 1 The Problem 2 Collateral Issues 3 Procedure Part I 4 Some Working Deftnitions 5 Phenomenalism 5.1 Linguistic Phenomenalism 5.2 Berkeleian Phenomenalism 6 Leibniz and Phenomenalism 6.1 Macintosh's Interpretation 6.2 Jolley's Interpretation 6.3 Wilson's Interpretation 111 Part II 7 Recapitulation and Procedure 8 Athenian and Darwinian Approaches 8.1 Woolhouse's Interpretation 8.2 Adams' Interpretation 8.3 Hartz's Interpretation 8.4 Loeb's Interpretation 8.5 Rutherford's Interpretation 9 Psychology and Ontology 9.1 Mind and Matter in Descartes and Locke 9.2 Leibniz's Analysis of Mind and Matter 9.2.1 The Primary-Secondary Quality Distinction 9.2.2 Physical Considerations 9.2.3 Metaphysical Considerations 9.2.3.1 Substance as Unity 9.2.3.2 Substance as Activity 9.2.3.3 Substance as Subject 9.2.4 Psychological Considerations 10 Levels of Discourse 11 Leibniz's Epistemological Realism 11.1 Requirements of the System 11.2 The Contrary Proposition 11.
    [Show full text]
  • Some Philowphical Prehistory of General Relativity
    - ----HOWARD STEI N ----- Some Philowphical Prehistory of General Relativity As history, my remarks will form rather a medley. If they can claim any sort of unity (apart from a general concern with space and time), it derives from two or three philosophi<lal motifs: the notion- metaphysical, if you will-of structure in the world, or vera causa; 1 the epistemological princi­ ple of the primacy ofexperience , as touchstone of both the content and the admissibility of knowledge claims; and a somewhat delicate issue of scien­ tific method that arises from the confrontation of that notion and that principle. The historical figures to be touched on are Leibniz, Huygens, Newton; glancingly, Kant; Mach , Helmholtz, and Riemann. The heroes of my story are Newton and Riemann, who seem to me to have expressed (although laconically) the clearest and the deepest views of the matters concerned. The story has no villains; but certain attributions often made to the credit of Leibniz and of Mach will come under criticism. It is well known that Leibniz denied, in some sense, to space the status of a vera ctwsa. Jn what precise sense he intended the denial is perhaps less well known; indeed, as I shall soon explain, I myself consider that sense in some respects difficult if not impossible to determine. The fact !hat Leibniz characterizes space as not "real" but "ideal," or as an "entity of reason" or abstraction, by itself decides nothing; for he also tells us that lhc structure thus abstracted is the structure--or, as he puts it, the "order"- of the situations of coexistent things; furthermore, of the situa­ liuns of all actual or 11ossible coexistent things; or, again (in the fourth lctlcr lo Clarke).
    [Show full text]
  • Leibniz on Logic, Language and Signs: a Bibliography (A- K)
    Leibniz on Logic, Language and Signs: a Bibliography (A- K) https://www.historyoflogic.com/biblio/leibniz-logic-biblio-one.htm History of Logic from Aristotle to Gödel by Raul Corazzon | e-mail: [email protected] Leibniz on Logic, Language and Semiotics. Annotated bibliography (First Part: A - K) BIBLIOGRAPHY 1. Aarsleff, Hans. 1964. "Leibniz on Locke on Language." American Philosophical Quarterly no. 1:165-188. Reprinted in: H. Aarsleff - From Locke to Saussure. Essays on the study of language and intellectual history - London, Athlone Press, 1982 pp. 42-83 and in: R. S. Woolhouse - Leibniz. Critical assessments - Vol. III - New York, Routledge, 1994, pp. 452-495 2. ———. 1975. "The Eighteenth Century Including Leibniz." In Current Trends in Linguistics, edited by Sebeok, Thomas A., 383-479. The Hague: Mouton. 3. Abraham, William E. 1969. "Complete Concepts and Leibniz's Distinction between Necessary and Contingent Propositions." Studia Leibnitiana no. 1:263-279. 4. Aguado, Javier. 1997. "Analisis De Las Relaciones En La Gramatica Logica De Leibniz. Historia De Un Conflicto Hermeneutico." Revista de Filosofia (Spain) no. 10:223-263. 5. Andrews, F.E. 1983. "Leibniz's Logic within His Philosophical System." Dionysius no. 7:73-128. "The work purports to provide a philosophical history of Leibniz's logical works. The principal conclusion is that Leibniz's work on logical calculi, the modifications in it coinciding with the three periods identified by Couturat, rest upon refinements in the expression of his philosophical system, and end when his philosophical thought reached that point at which it is manifest that a logical calculus such as he had envisaged is not competent to his philosophical standpoint." 6.
    [Show full text]
  • |||GET||| Metaepistemology and Skepticism 1St Edition
    METAEPISTEMOLOGY AND SKEPTICISM 1ST EDITION DOWNLOAD FREE Richard Fumerton | 9780847681075 | | | | | Skepticism and Disagreement He was quite familiar with the philosophy of Descartes and unprecedentedly extended the application of the Cartesian method to the religious context by analyzing religious texts with it. Elgin, Catherine. Be that as it may, in this section we set aside externalist misgivings about reasons and introduce basic issues surrounding reasons for belief and epistemic psychology. Rather, given the broad span of themes and problems that fall under the label of metaepistemology, the aim is to introduce some bibliography and some works that provide an overview of some of the cutting edge research that is currently undertaken in metaepistemology debates. Argues for meta-epistemological skepticism. An argument commonly made but limited to science is that the scientific method asserts only probable findings, because the number of cases tested is always limited and because the tests constitute perceptual observations. For instance, Allan Gibbard, one of the most prominent and influential expressivists and one of the first to extend expressivism from metaethics to metaepistemology, has held at least two expressivist theories, the early norm-expressivism and the later plan-expressivism Main article: Buddhist philosophy. Baehr, Jason. Philosophy Compass 7 2 That is, they respect the thesis that normative propositions express descriptive mental states like beliefs Metaepistemology and Skepticism 1st edition purport to pick out corresponding normative properties and facts. A Virtue Epistemology. Philosophical Issues 14, Epistemology, pp. Mind 93 : Williamson argues against the reductive conceptual analysis approach to knowledge and for the introduction of a nonreductive account of knowledge that reverses the traditional explanatory order in Metaepistemology and Skepticism 1st edition.
    [Show full text]
  • Metaphysical Rationalism
    4 Metaphysical Rationalism Martin Lin “To try and fnd out the reason for everything is very dangerous and leads to nothing but disappointment and dissatisfaction.” —Queen Victoria The world, according to Spinoza, is an intelligible place. This conviction is reflected in his philosophy in numerous ways. He believes that the order of being and the order of reason mirror each other, as is evident in the way he defines his basic ontological categories both in terms of what inheres in what and what is conceived through what. Moreover, for him, every event is causally determined in accordance with natural laws that are always and everywhere the same. These laws follow from the eternal and infinite essence of God in the same way that the geometrical properties of a triangle follow from its nature. Thus, laws of nature are intelligible in the same way as the objects of geometry are intelligible, and all events conform to this rational order. Spinoza’s confidence in the rationality of the world is also reflected in his Principle of Sufficient Reason, which says that if something exists, there is a cause or reason why it exists, and if it doesn’t exist, there is an explanation of its nonexistence. Not only does the world have an intelligible structure, but human reason is capable of discovering that structure. We have, in virtue of being modes of God, an adequate idea of the infinite and eternal divine essence that allows us to infer from it the laws of nature as well as the formal essences of singular things.
    [Show full text]
  • How to Hintikkize a Frege Fabien Schang
    How to Hintikkize a Frege Fabien Schang 1 Frege’s theory of meaning and its critics 1.1 A one-sorted semantics Frege’s rationale is to uphold his own theory of meaning by means of an argument by contraposition (α ⊃ ) ⊃ (: ⊃ :α). It runs as follows: If (α) every sign (Zeichen) of an arbitrary sentence includes both a sense (Sinn) and a reference (Bedeutung), then ( ) no substitution of equivalent components (with the same reference) alters the whole. Now if (: ) at least one counterexample of this substitution salva veritate can be found, then (:α) Frege’s theory of meaning collapses. The kinds of argument under review are the following: Frege asserts both α and ; Kripke denies α and asserts ; Hintikka asserts α and denies . The contrast between two modes of meaning (conveying information) through every linguistic item, that is the one between “sense” and “reference”, 162 Fabien Schang primarily cancels some naïve theory of meaning, according to which every sign would purport to tag or label one object (recall Quine’s museum myth of meanings [13], or Saint Augustine’s assimilation between meaning and pointing something out [14]). How to account for the information gain from “a = a” to “a = b”, if meaning is reduced to reference? For this purpose, Frege’s philosophy of language relies upon two main assumptions: compositionality, and extensionalism. According to the for- mer, the reference of a complex sentence is determined by the reference of its components and sense (reference) cannot contribute to determinate a reference (sense). A crucial point for the following: the references of sen- tences are truth-values, among the True and the False.
    [Show full text]
  • Leibniz on the Logic of Conceptual Containment and Coincidence
    LEIBNIZ ON THE LOGIC OF CONCEPTUAL CONTAINMENT AND COINCIDENCE Marko Malink Anubav Vasudevan New York University University of Chicago [email protected] [email protected] Contents 1. Conceptual Containment and Coincidence 1 2. The Rule of Substitution 6 3. Composition in the Containment Calculus 9 4. Privation in the Containment Calculus 13 5. Propositional Terms in the Containment Calculus 17 6. The Two Roots of Leibniz's Logic 24 Appendix: Algebraic Semantics for Leibniz's Containment Calculi 30 References 39 Abstract. In a series of early essays written around 1679, Leibniz sets out to explore the logic of conceptual containment. In his more mature logical writings from the mid-1680s, however, his focus shifts away from the logic of containment to that of coincidence, or mutual containment. This shift in em- phasis is indicative of the fact that Leibniz's logic has its roots in two distinct theoretical frameworks: (i) the traditional theory of the categorical syllogism based on rules of inference such as Barbara, and (ii) equational systems of arithmetic and geometry based on the rule of substitution of equals. While syllogistic reasoning is naturally modeled in a logic of containment, substi- tutional reasoning of the sort performed in arithmetic and geometry is more naturally modeled in a logic of coincidence. In this paper, we argue that Leib- niz's logic of conceptual containment and his logic of coincidence can in fact be viewed as two alternative axiomatizations, in different but equally expressive languages, of one and the same logical theory. Thus, far from being incoherent, the varying syllogistic and equational themes that run throughout Leibniz's logical writings complement one another and fit together harmoniously.
    [Show full text]
  • PHILOSOPHY of SCIENCE Some Philosophical Prehistury of General Relativity
    k'/1 I ,/ ~f I"';:, (" - '~~/!--- lMinnesota Studies in the ---.. PHILOSOPHY OF SCIENCE Some Philosophical Prehistury of General Relativity As history. my remarks will form rather a medley. If they can claim any sort of unity (apart from a general concern with space and time), it derives from two or three philosophical motifs: the notion-metaphysical, if you will-of structure in the world, or vera causa; 1 the epistemological princi- ple of the primacy of experience, as touchstone of hath the content and the admissibility of knowledge claims; and a somewhat delicate issue of scien- tific method that arises from the confrontation of that notion and that principle. The historical figures to be touched on are Leibniz. Huygens, Newton; glancingly, Kant; Mach, Helmholtz. and Riemann. The heroes of my story are Newton and Riemann, who seem to me to have expressed (although laconically) the clearest and the deepest views of the matters concerned. The story has no villains; but certain attributions often made to the credit of Leibniz and of Mach will come under criticism. It is well known that Leibniz denied, in some sense, to space the status of a vera causa. In what precise sense he intended the denial is perhaps less well known; indeed. as I shall soon explain. I myself consider that sense in some respects difficult if not impossible to determine. The fact that Leibniz characterizes space as not "real" but "ideaL" or as an "entity of reason" or abstraction. by itself decides nothing; for he also tells us that the structure thus abstracted is the structure--or, as he puts it.
    [Show full text]
  • Monadic Interaction∗
    Monadic Interaction∗ Stephen Puryear North Carolina State University Leibniz has almost universally been represented as denying that created mon- ads, including human minds and the souls of animals, can causally interact either with one another or with bodies.1 Yet his writings contain many state- ments which appear to contradict this reading. For example, he maintains in numerous passages that created monads can be said to interact or to cause changes in one another in the special sense of what he calls ‘ideal’ interaction. Thus he writes to Des Bosses that ‘The modifications of one monad are the ideal causes of the modifications of other monads’ (G 2:475/L 608).2 And in the Monadology he discusses a kind of action which ‘in simple substances is only an ideal influence of one monad on the other’ (M 51). Given that such claims appear in the same writings and in writings from the same period in which Leibniz supposedly denies that created monads interact, a puzzle arises concerning how to square these claims with the traditional reading. Proponents of the traditional reading rarely address this puzzle, but those who do have usually proposed to solve it by denying that what Leibniz calls ideal action is a genuine form of action or causation. As R. C. Sleigh (1990b, ∗Author Posting. (c) BSHP, 2010. This is the author’s version of the work. It is posted here by permission of BSHP for personal use, not for redistribution. The definitive version was published in British Journal for the History of Philosophy, Volume 18 Issue 5, December 2010.
    [Show full text]
  • The Concept of Similarity in “Der Ähnlichkeitsbegriff Bei Leibniz”, In: Mathesis Rationis
    1 Leibniz’s Science of Forms as a Structural Science and Similarity as its Central Concept1. Oscar M. Esquisabel UNQ-CONICET-UNLP Introduction This paper is concerned with an aspect of combinatory science or art2 that, in our opinion, has so far been relatively neglected in the attempts to clarify the nature and goals of this science. This aspect is the presentation of combinatory science as the science of the similar and dissimilar, which nevertheless plays a central role in the determination of its function and scope, particularly in its connection with the other sciences and with the leibnizian program of a new kind of ars inveniendi. Usually, combinatory science is associated with two main ideas: on the one hand, wiht the analysis and recombination of concepts, and, on the other, with the assignations of characters or signs to those concepts, in order to obtain their possible combinations through operations with signs. Moreover, combinatory mathematics helps us to carry out in a systematic way the calculation of combinations. Therefore, we have an orderly method of finding new truths and of judging or evaluating the truths that we possess beforehand. The fact that combinatory science operates by means of characters gives to it a “symbolic” dimension. In this way, it becomes for Leibniz not only a science that manipulates signs, but also a science that has complete symbolic systems as objects. Hence, combinatory science is promoted to the status of a characteristic combinatory science or characteristic combinatorics simpliciter. Its scope is so general that all the other sciences are subordinated to it.
    [Show full text]
  • Theory and History of Ontology by Raul Corazzon | E-Mail: [email protected]
    14/4/2021 Ontology: Theory and History Theory and History of Ontology by Raul Corazzon | e-mail: [email protected] Ontology: Its Role in Modern Philosophy What's New: Last Update: April 14th 2021. Introduction: A Working Definition Ontology is the theory of objects and their ties. It provides criteria for distinguishing different types of objects (concrete and abstract, existent and nonexistent, real and ideal, independent and dependent) and their ties (relations, dependencies and predication). We can distinguish: a) formal, b) descriptive and c) formalized ontologies. a) Formal ontology was introduced by Edmund Husserl in his Logical Investigations (1): according to Husserl, its object is the study of the genera of being, the leading regional concepts, i.e., the categories; its true method is the eidetic reduction coupled with the method of categorial intuition. The phenomenological ontology is divided into two: (I) Formal, and (II) Regional, or Material, Ontologies. The former investigates the problem of truth on three basic levels: (a) Formal Apophantics, or formal logic of judgments, where the a priori conditions for the possibility of the doxic certainty of reason are to be sought, along with (b) the synthetic forms for the possibility of the axiological, and (c) "practical" truths. In other words it is divided into formal logic, formal axiology, and formal praxis. In contemporary philosophy, formal ontology has been developed in two principal ways. The first approach has been to study formal ontology as a part of ontology, and to analyze it using the tools and approach of formal logic: from this point of view formal ontology examines the logical features of predication and of the various theories of universals.
    [Show full text]