Substitutivity

Total Page:16

File Type:pdf, Size:1020Kb

Substitutivity SUBSTITUTIVITY CARLOS EMILIO GARCÍA DUQUE pUNIVERSI hDAD DE CALDAS RESUMEN ABSTRACT En este artículo, procuro hacer un examen In this paper, I attempt a careful examination cuidadoso del principio de sustitutividad, of the principle of substitutivity, sometimes algunas veces llamado ‘la ley de Leibniz’, referred to as ‘Leibniz’ Law’, or ‘Leibniz’ o ‘el principio leibniciano de identidad Principle of Identity of the Indiscernibles’. de los indiscernibles’. Tras ofrecer una After giving a precise and independent formulación precisa e independiente de formulation of these three principles, I take estos tres principios, me ocupo de ciertos issue with several alleged counterexamples supuestos contraejemplos al principio de to the principle of substitutivity and sustitutividad y discuto, por separado, las discuss, separately, the supposed failures of supuestas fallas que se pueden atribuir substitutivity attributable to the paradoxes a las paradojas de la intensionalidad, las of intensionality; difficulties involving the dificultades implícitas en las condiciones truth conditions of modal expressions and de verdad de expresiones modales y los belief contexts. I contend that the alleged contextos epistémicos. Sostengo que los counterexamples hardly account for the supuestos contraejemplos a duras penas meaning Leibniz himself originally ascribed se ajustan al sentido original que el mismo to the principle. Furthermore, I shall argue Leibniz le quiso dar al principio. Además, that a restricted version of Substitutivity argumentaré que una versión restringida may be true, and urge additional attempts de la sustitutividad puede ser verdadera to rescue this principle, under the conviction y recomiendo que se hagan esfuerzos that an appropriate dismissal of the attacks adicionales para salvar el principio, bajo on it, would give us better grounds to la convicción de que el rechazo adecuado understand Leibniz’ claims on identity de los ataques en su contra nos permitiría comprender mejor los planteamientos de Leibniz sobre la identidad. PALABRAS CLAVE KEY WORDS Principio de sustitutividad, ley de Leibniz, The principle of substitutivity, Leibniz, principio leibniciano de identidad de los ‘Law Leibniz’, Principle of Identity of the indiscernibles, salva veritate, intensionalidad, Indiscernibles, salva veritate, intensionality, contextos epistémicos, identidad, identidad belief context, identity, concept-identity. de conceptos. p hRecibido el 12 de Diciembre de 2006 y aprobado el 11 de Abril de 2007. Carlos Emilio García Duque THE PRINCIPLE OF SUBSTITUTIVITY In literature on identity, there is a frequent discussion of a principle sometimes referred to as 'Leibniz' Law', 'Leibniz' Principle of Identity of the Indiscernibles' or 'the Principle of Substitutivity'. Such variety of labels suggests that there must be a close relationship among the purported principles so designated. Letting issues of ambiguity aside, it transpires that the three labels just mentioned do not refer to the same concept. Scholars like Ishiguro, for example, have pointed out that the general understanding of 'Leibniz' law' aims to the Principle of Indiscernibility of Identicals, while the Principle of Substitutivity is a principle which defines identity of concepts. The disagreements about what could be the correct way to understand each of the three principles contrast with the almost universal agreement about the falsity of the Principle of Substitutivity. It is my interest in this paper to determine whether the standard arguments against the Principle of Substitutivity do justice to the meaning Leibniz himself originally ascribed to it. To accomplish this task, I shall examine a formulation of the Principle of Substitutivity and I shall try to spell out the arguments that show its falsity. Then I will argue that a restricted version of this Principle is true, and urge additional attempts to salvage it, under the conviction that, if such a project becomes successful, then one would be in a better position to interpret Leibniz' claims on identity. I To begin with, it will be useful to see what the three principles alluded to are exactly. Unfortunately, Leibniz did not arrive at a singular and definitive formulation of any of the principles (it is even dubious that he regarded them as strictly different principles), since he discussed the matter in several places. However, there are key features in each of them, which enable us to distinguish a formulation from another. In Leibniz’ own words the principles can be stated as follow: (A) “Those are the same of which one can be substituted for the other without loss of truth, such as triangle and trilateral, quadrangle and quadrilateral.” This is what has been called ‘Leibniz’ law’, or the principle of Indiscernibility of Identicals. It says that If A and B are identical then everything that is true of A is true of B, or in a more formal way that: (A = B) → (φ) (φA ≡ φB). 96 Discusiones Filosóficas. Año 8 pNº 11,Enero–Diciembre, 2007. pp. 95 - 108 h SUBSTITUTIVITY (B) “Those terms of which one can be substituted for the other without affecting truth are identical.” This corresponds to the Principle of Identity of Indiscernibles. It can be stated by saying that: If everything that is true of A is true of B, and vice versa, and hence if there is no discernible difference between A and B, then A is identical with B: (φ)(φA ≡ φB) → (A = B). (C) “Two terms are the same if one can be substituted for the other without altering the truth of any statement. If we have A and B and A enters into some true proposition, and the substitutions of B for A wherever it appears, results in a new proposition which is likewise true, and if this can be done for every such proposition, then A and B are said to be the same; and conversely, if A and B are the same, they can be substituted for one another as I have said.”1 This is what is properly called ‘the Principle of Substitutivity’ or ‘the Salva Veritate Principle’. Notice that (B) is the converse of (A), and that slightly different formulations of both (A) and (B) can be found in or derived from (C). On the other hand, many have contended that the three formulations are infected by a confusion of use/mention. What can be substituted for one another are words, not things as Leibniz seems to suggest, and what can be true or false are the propositions expressed by the sentences in which those words figure. A more precise formulation of the notions conveyed by (A) through (C) is offered by Richard Cartwright in his essay “Identity and Substitutivity”.2 I will use his formulation for the remaining of the paper: (D) for all expressions α and β, α = β expresses a true proposition if and only if, for all sentences S and S’, if S’ is like S save for containing and occurrence of β where S contains an occurrence of α, then S expresses a true proposition only if S’ does also. but this is just the conjunction of: 1 The first two formulations come from Leibniz’ Logical Papers (pages, 84 and 52), as quoted by Hide Ishiguro in her book: Leibniz’s Philosophy of Logic and Language. New York, Cornell University Press, 1990. p. 19. The third formulation comes from Richard Cartwright’s paper: “Identity and Substitutivity.” In: Identity and Individuation. Ed., by Milton K. Munitz, NYU Press, 1971. 2 I agree with Cartwright’s main conclusions and my own views are strongly influenced by his arguments. I do not, however, share his evaluation about the success of the counterexamples to the Principle of Substitutivity. p h 97 Carlos Emilio García Duque (E) for all expressions α and β, α = β expresses a true proposition if substitution of β for α is truth preserving with (F) for all expressions α and β, α = β expresses a true proposition only if substitution of β for α is truth preserving. In recent literature, mostly references to (F) are considered as references to “the Principle of Substitutivity”. On the other hand, there appears to be widespread agreement on the charge that (F) is simply false; and the reason to justify such charge is that there are counterexamples to it. The main arguments to this effect come from the paradoxes of intensionality, difficulties involving the truth conditions of modal expressions and failures in belief contexts. In my discussion, I will stick to the standard examples which are already familiar to the reader. Let us tackle one at a time. It has been argued that while the sentence ‘Giorgione was so-called because of his size’ (S1) is true, the sentence ‘Barbarelli was so-called because of his size’ (S2) is false, and yet Giorgione = Barbarelli. Therefore, S1 and S2 appear to be a pair of sentences that falsify (F). For (F) says that if the proposition ‘α = β’ is true, then substitution of β for α should be truth preserving. Under the supposition that there is no discussion regarding the truth of ‘α = β’, and according to (F), we should expect that if S1 and S2 only differ in that S2 contains an occurrence of β, where S1 contains an occurrence of α, then if S1 is true, S2 would be true also, but S2 seems to be false. Let me spell out the core of this argument. Since the Principle of Substitutivity, as expressed in (F), contains no restrictions whatsoever it is supposed to cover all occurrences of all expressions. The name ‘Giorgione’ was attributed to someone because of his size, but the same person was also called ‘Barbarelli’, so while the proposition ‘Barbarelli was called ‘Giorgione’ because of his size’ seems perfectly appropriate, the proposition ‘Barbarelli was called ‘Barbarelli’ because of his size’ seems not. It looks like we have a legitimate counterexample to (F). However, as it has been established by Cartwright, the contention that S2 is false (on the grounds that there is a property that Giorgione has but Barbarelli lacks) seems to be incoherent.
Recommended publications
  • Relative Interpretations and Substitutional Definitions of Logical
    Relative Interpretations and Substitutional Definitions of Logical Truth and Consequence MIRKO ENGLER Abstract: This paper proposes substitutional definitions of logical truth and consequence in terms of relative interpretations that are extensionally equivalent to the model-theoretic definitions for any relational first-order language. Our philosophical motivation to consider substitutional definitions is based on the hope to simplify the meta-theory of logical consequence. We discuss to what extent our definitions can contribute to that. Keywords: substitutional definitions of logical consequence, Quine, meta- theory of logical consequence 1 Introduction This paper investigates the applicability of relative interpretations in a substi- tutional account of logical truth and consequence. We introduce definitions of logical truth and consequence in terms of relative interpretations and demonstrate that they are extensionally equivalent to the model-theoretic definitions as developed in (Tarski & Vaught, 1956) for any first-order lan- guage (including equality). The benefit of such a definition is that it could be given in a meta-theoretic framework that only requires arithmetic as ax- iomatized by PA. Furthermore, we investigate how intensional constraints on logical truth and consequence force us to extend our framework to an arithmetical meta-theory that itself interprets set-theory. We will argue that such an arithmetical framework still might be in favor over a set-theoretical one. The basic idea behind our definition is both to generate and evaluate substitution instances of a sentence ' by relative interpretations. A relative interpretation rests on a function f that translates all formulae ' of a language L into formulae f(') of a language L0 by mapping the primitive predicates 0 P of ' to formulae P of L while preserving the logical structure of ' 1 Mirko Engler and relativizing its quantifiers by an L0-definable formula.
    [Show full text]
  • The Substitutional Analysis of Logical Consequence
    THE SUBSTITUTIONAL ANALYSIS OF LOGICAL CONSEQUENCE Volker Halbach∗ dra version ⋅ please don’t quote ónd June óþÕä Consequentia ‘formalis’ vocatur quae in omnibus terminis valet retenta forma consimili. Vel si vis expresse loqui de vi sermonis, consequentia formalis est cui omnis propositio similis in forma quae formaretur esset bona consequentia [...] Iohannes Buridanus, Tractatus de Consequentiis (Hubien ÕÉßä, .ì, p.óóf) Zf«±§Zh± A substitutional account of logical truth and consequence is developed and defended. Roughly, a substitution instance of a sentence is dened to be the result of uniformly substituting nonlogical expressions in the sentence with expressions of the same grammatical category. In particular atomic formulae can be replaced with any formulae containing. e denition of logical truth is then as follows: A sentence is logically true i all its substitution instances are always satised. Logical consequence is dened analogously. e substitutional denition of validity is put forward as a conceptual analysis of logical validity at least for suciently rich rst-order settings. In Kreisel’s squeezing argument the formal notion of substitutional validity naturally slots in to the place of informal intuitive validity. ∗I am grateful to Beau Mount, Albert Visser, and Timothy Williamson for discussions about the themes of this paper. Õ §Z êZo±í At the origin of logic is the observation that arguments sharing certain forms never have true premisses and a false conclusion. Similarly, all sentences of certain forms are always true. Arguments and sentences of this kind are for- mally valid. From the outset logicians have been concerned with the study and systematization of these arguments, sentences and their forms.
    [Show full text]
  • Philosophical Review
    Philosophical Review Main Trends in Recent Philosophy: Two Dogmas of Empiricism Author(s): W. V. Quine Source: The Philosophical Review, Vol. 60, No. 1 (Jan., 1951), pp. 20-43 Published by: Duke University Press on behalf of Philosophical Review Stable URL: http://www.jstor.org/stable/2181906 . Accessed: 19/01/2011 11:47 Your use of the JSTOR archive indicates your acceptance of JSTOR's Terms and Conditions of Use, available at . http://www.jstor.org/page/info/about/policies/terms.jsp. JSTOR's Terms and Conditions of Use provides, in part, that unless you have obtained prior permission, you may not download an entire issue of a journal or multiple copies of articles, and you may use content in the JSTOR archive only for your personal, non-commercial use. Please contact the publisher regarding any further use of this work. Publisher contact information may be obtained at . http://www.jstor.org/action/showPublisher?publisherCode=duke. Each copy of any part of a JSTOR transmission must contain the same copyright notice that appears on the screen or printed page of such transmission. JSTOR is a not-for-profit service that helps scholars, researchers, and students discover, use, and build upon a wide range of content in a trusted digital archive. We use information technology and tools to increase productivity and facilitate new forms of scholarship. For more information about JSTOR, please contact [email protected]. Duke University Press and Philosophical Review are collaborating with JSTOR to digitize, preserve and extend access to The Philosophical Review. http://www.jstor.org TWO DOGMAS OF EMPIRICISM' M ODERN empiricismhas been conditionedin large part by two dogmas.
    [Show full text]
  • The Development of Mathematical Logic from Russell to Tarski: 1900–1935
    The Development of Mathematical Logic from Russell to Tarski: 1900–1935 Paolo Mancosu Richard Zach Calixto Badesa The Development of Mathematical Logic from Russell to Tarski: 1900–1935 Paolo Mancosu (University of California, Berkeley) Richard Zach (University of Calgary) Calixto Badesa (Universitat de Barcelona) Final Draft—May 2004 To appear in: Leila Haaparanta, ed., The Development of Modern Logic. New York and Oxford: Oxford University Press, 2004 Contents Contents i Introduction 1 1 Itinerary I: Metatheoretical Properties of Axiomatic Systems 3 1.1 Introduction . 3 1.2 Peano’s school on the logical structure of theories . 4 1.3 Hilbert on axiomatization . 8 1.4 Completeness and categoricity in the work of Veblen and Huntington . 10 1.5 Truth in a structure . 12 2 Itinerary II: Bertrand Russell’s Mathematical Logic 15 2.1 From the Paris congress to the Principles of Mathematics 1900–1903 . 15 2.2 Russell and Poincar´e on predicativity . 19 2.3 On Denoting . 21 2.4 Russell’s ramified type theory . 22 2.5 The logic of Principia ......................... 25 2.6 Further developments . 26 3 Itinerary III: Zermelo’s Axiomatization of Set Theory and Re- lated Foundational Issues 29 3.1 The debate on the axiom of choice . 29 3.2 Zermelo’s axiomatization of set theory . 32 3.3 The discussion on the notion of “definit” . 35 3.4 Metatheoretical studies of Zermelo’s axiomatization . 38 4 Itinerary IV: The Theory of Relatives and Lowenheim’s¨ Theorem 41 4.1 Theory of relatives and model theory . 41 4.2 The logic of relatives .
    [Show full text]
  • 12 Propositional Logic
    CHAPTER 12 ✦ ✦ ✦ ✦ Propositional Logic In this chapter, we introduce propositional logic, an algebra whose original purpose, dating back to Aristotle, was to model reasoning. In more recent times, this algebra, like many algebras, has proved useful as a design tool. For example, Chapter 13 shows how propositional logic can be used in computer circuit design. A third use of logic is as a data model for programming languages and systems, such as the language Prolog. Many systems for reasoning by computer, including theorem provers, program verifiers, and applications in the field of artificial intelligence, have been implemented in logic-based programming languages. These languages generally use “predicate logic,” a more powerful form of logic that extends the capabilities of propositional logic. We shall meet predicate logic in Chapter 14. ✦ ✦ ✦ ✦ 12.1 What This Chapter Is About Section 12.2 gives an intuitive explanation of what propositional logic is, and why it is useful. The next section, 12,3, introduces an algebra for logical expressions with Boolean-valued operands and with logical operators such as AND, OR, and NOT that Boolean algebra operate on Boolean (true/false) values. This algebra is often called Boolean algebra after George Boole, the logician who first framed logic as an algebra. We then learn the following ideas. ✦ Truth tables are a useful way to represent the meaning of an expression in logic (Section 12.4). ✦ We can convert a truth table to a logical expression for the same logical function (Section 12.5). ✦ The Karnaugh map is a useful tabular technique for simplifying logical expres- sions (Section 12.6).
    [Show full text]
  • Logical Consequence: a Defense of Tarski*
    GREG RAY LOGICAL CONSEQUENCE: A DEFENSE OF TARSKI* ABSTRACT. In his classic 1936 essay “On the Concept of Logical Consequence”, Alfred Tarski used the notion of XU~@~ZC~~NIto give a semantic characterization of the logical properties. Tarski is generally credited with introducing the model-theoretic chamcteriza- tion of the logical properties familiar to us today. However, in his hook, The &ncel>f of Lugid Consequence, Etchemendy argues that Tarski’s account is inadequate for quite a number of reasons, and is actually incompatible with the standard mod&theoretic account. Many of his criticisms are meant to apply to the model-theoretic account as well. In this paper, I discuss the following four critical charges that Etchemendy makes against Tarski and his account of the logical properties: (1) (a) Tarski’s account of logical consequence diverges from the standard model-theoretic account at points where the latter account gets it right. (b) Tarski’s account cannot be brought into line with the model-thcorctic account, because the two are fundamentally incompatible. (2) There are simple countcrcxamples (enumerated by Etchemcndy) which show that Tarski’s account is wrong. (3) Tarski committed a modal faIlacy when arguing that his account captures our pre-theoretical concept of logical consequence, and so obscured an essential weakness of the account. (4) Tarski’s account depends on there being a distinction between the “log- ical terms” and the “non-logical terms” of a language, but (according to Etchemendy) there are very simple (even first-order) languages for which no such distinction can be made. Etchemcndy’s critique raises historica and philosophical questions about important foun- dational work.
    [Show full text]
  • Presupposition: a Semantic Or Pragmatic Phenomenon?
    Arab World English Journal (AWEJ) Volume. 8 Number. 3 September, 2017 Pp. 46 -59 DOI: https://dx.doi.org/10.24093/awej/vol8no3.4 Presupposition: A Semantic or Pragmatic Phenomenon? Mostafa OUALIF Department of English Studies Faculty of Letters and Humanities Ben M’sik, Casablanca Hassan II University, Casablanca, Morocco Abstract There has been debate among linguists with regards to the semantic view and the pragmatic view of presupposition. Some scholars believe that presupposition is purely semantic and others believe that it is purely pragmatic. The present paper contributes to the ongoing debate and exposes the different ways presupposition was approached by linguists. The paper also tries to attend to (i) what semantics is and what pragmatics is in a unified theory of meaning and (ii) the possibility to outline a semantic account of presupposition without having recourse to pragmatics and vice versa. The paper advocates Gazdar’s analysis, a pragmatic analysis, as the safest grounds on which a working grammar of presupposition could be outlined. It shows how semantic accounts are inadequate to deal with the projection problem. Finally, the paper states explicitly that the increasingly puzzling theoretical status of presupposition seems to confirm the philosophical contention that not any fact can be translated into words. Key words: entailment, pragmatics, presupposition, projection problem, semantic theory Cite as: OUALIF, M. (2017). Presupposition: A Semantic or Pragmatic Phenomenon? Arab World English Journal, 8 (3). DOI: https://dx.doi.org/10.24093/awej/vol8no3.4 46 Arab World English Journal (AWEJ) Volume 8. Number. 3 September 2017 Presupposition: A Semantic or Pragmatic Phenomenon? OUALIF I.
    [Show full text]
  • • Speech Errors (Review) • Issues in Lexicalization • LRP in Language Production (Review) • N200 (N2b) • N200 in Language Production • Semantic Vs
    Plan • Speech Errors (Review) • Issues in Lexicalization • LRP in Language Production (Review) • N200 (N2b) • N200 in Language Production • Semantic vs. Phonological Information • Semantic vs. Syntactic Information • Syntactic vs. Phonological Information • Time Course of Word Production in Picture Naming Eech Sperrors • What can we learn from these things? • Anticipation Errors – a reading list Æ a leading list • Exchange Errors – fill the pool Æ fool the pill • Phonological, lexical, syntactic • Speech is planned in advance – Distance of exchange, anticipation errors suggestive of how far in advance we “plan” Word Substitutions & Word Blends • Semantic Substitutions • Lexicon is organized – That’s a horse of another color semantically AND Æ …a horse of another race phonologically • Phonological Substitutions • Word selection must happen – White Anglo-Saxon Protestant after the grammatical class of Æ …prostitute the target has been • Semantic Blends determined – Edited/annotated Æ editated – Nouns substitute for nouns; verbs for verbs • Phonological Blends – Substitutions don’t result in – Gin and tonic Æ gin and topic ungrammatical sentences • Double Blends – Arrested and prosecuted Æ arrested and persecuted Word Stem & Affix Morphemes •A New Yorker Æ A New Yorkan (American) • Seem to occur prior to lexical insertion • Morphological rules of word formation engaged during speech production Stranding Errors • Nouns & Verbs exchange, but inflectional and derivational morphemes rarely do – Rather, they are stranded • I don’t know that I’d
    [Show full text]
  • Substitution and Propositional Proof Complexity
    Substitution and Propositional Proof Complexity Sam Buss Abstract We discuss substitution rules that allow the substitution of formulas for formula variables. A substitution rule was first introduced by Frege. More recently, substitution is studied in the setting of propositional logic. We state theorems of Urquhart’s giving lower bounds on the number of steps in the substitution Frege system for propositional logic. We give the first superlinear lower bounds on the number of symbols in substitution Frege and multi-substitution Frege proofs. “The length of a proof ought not to be measured by the yard. It is easy to make a proof look short on paper by skipping over many links in the chain of inference and merely indicating large parts of it. Generally people are satisfied if every step in the proof is evidently correct, and this is permissable if one merely wishes to be persuaded that the proposition to be proved is true. But if it is a matter of gaining an insight into the nature of this ‘being evident’, this procedure does not suffice; we must put down all the intermediate steps, that the full light of consciousness may fall upon them.” [G. Frege, Grundgesetze, 1893; translation by M. Furth] 1 Introduction The present article concentrates on the substitution rule allowing the substitution of formulas for formula variables.1 The substitution rule has long pedigree as it was a rule of inference in Frege’s Begriffsschrift [9] and Grundgesetze [10], which contained the first in-depth formalization of logical foundations for mathematics. Since then, substitution has become much less important for the foundations of Sam Buss Department of Mathematics, University of California, San Diego, e-mail: [email protected], Supported in part by Simons Foundation grant 578919.
    [Show full text]
  • The History of Logic
    c Peter King & Stewart Shapiro, The Oxford Companion to Philosophy (OUP 1995), 496–500. THE HISTORY OF LOGIC Aristotle was the first thinker to devise a logical system. He drew upon the emphasis on universal definition found in Socrates, the use of reductio ad absurdum in Zeno of Elea, claims about propositional structure and nega- tion in Parmenides and Plato, and the body of argumentative techniques found in legal reasoning and geometrical proof. Yet the theory presented in Aristotle’s five treatises known as the Organon—the Categories, the De interpretatione, the Prior Analytics, the Posterior Analytics, and the Sophistical Refutations—goes far beyond any of these. Aristotle holds that a proposition is a complex involving two terms, a subject and a predicate, each of which is represented grammatically with a noun. The logical form of a proposition is determined by its quantity (uni- versal or particular) and by its quality (affirmative or negative). Aristotle investigates the relation between two propositions containing the same terms in his theories of opposition and conversion. The former describes relations of contradictoriness and contrariety, the latter equipollences and entailments. The analysis of logical form, opposition, and conversion are combined in syllogistic, Aristotle’s greatest invention in logic. A syllogism consists of three propositions. The first two, the premisses, share exactly one term, and they logically entail the third proposition, the conclusion, which contains the two non-shared terms of the premisses. The term common to the two premisses may occur as subject in one and predicate in the other (called the ‘first figure’), predicate in both (‘second figure’), or subject in both (‘third figure’).
    [Show full text]
  • Review of Gregory Landini, Russell's Hidden Substitutional Theory
    eiews SUBSTITUTION AND THE THEORY OF TYPES G S Philosophy / U. of Manchester Oxford Road, Manchester, .., ..@.. Gregory Landini. Russell’s Hidden Substitutional Theory. Oxford and New York: Oxford U.P., . Pp. xi, .£.; .. hen, in , Russell communicated to Frege the famous paradox of the Wclass of all classes which are not members of themselves, Frege im- mediately located the source of the contradiction in his generous attitude towards the existence of classes. The discovery of Russell’s paradox exposed the error in Frege’s reasoning, but it was left to Whitehead and Russell to reformu- late the logicist programme without the assumption of classes. Yet the “no- classes” theory that eventually emerged in Principia Mathematica, though admired by many, has rarely been accepted without significant alterations. Almost without exception, these calls for alteration of the system have been induced by distaste for the theory of types in Principia. Much of the dissatisfaction that philosophers and logicians have felt about type-theory hinged on Whitehead and Russell’s decision to supplement the hierarchy of types (as applied to propositional functions) with a hierarchy of orders restricting the range of quantifiers so as to obtain the ramified theory of types. This ramified system was roundly criticized, predominantly because it necessitated the axiom of reducibility—famously denounced as having “no place in mathematics” by Frank Ramsey, who maintained that “anything which cannot be proved without it cannot be regarded as proved at all”. Russell himself, who had admitted that the axiom was not “self-evident” in the first edition of Principia (PM, : ), explored the possibility of removing the axiom in the second edition.
    [Show full text]
  • Levels of Discourse in Leibniz's Metaphysics the Ontological Status of Bodies
    Levels of Discourse in Leibniz's Metaphysics The Ontological Status of Bodies: A Study of the Levels of Discourse in Leibniz's Metaphysics By SCOTT STAPLEFORD, B.A. A Thesis Submitted to the School of Graduate Studies in Partial Fulfilment of the Requirements for the Degree Master of Arts McMaster University C> Copyright by Scott Stapleford, August 1998 MASTER OF ARTS (1998) McMaster University (Philosophy) Hamilton, Ontario TITLE: The Ontological Status of Bodies: A Study of the Levels of Discourse in Leibniz's Metaphysics AUTHOR: Scott Stapleford, B.A. (Brock University) SUPERVISOR: Professor Wilfrid Waluchow NUMBER OF PAGES: iv, 169 ii Table of Contents Introduction 1 The Problem 2 Collateral Issues 3 Procedure Part I 4 Some Working Deftnitions 5 Phenomenalism 5.1 Linguistic Phenomenalism 5.2 Berkeleian Phenomenalism 6 Leibniz and Phenomenalism 6.1 Macintosh's Interpretation 6.2 Jolley's Interpretation 6.3 Wilson's Interpretation 111 Part II 7 Recapitulation and Procedure 8 Athenian and Darwinian Approaches 8.1 Woolhouse's Interpretation 8.2 Adams' Interpretation 8.3 Hartz's Interpretation 8.4 Loeb's Interpretation 8.5 Rutherford's Interpretation 9 Psychology and Ontology 9.1 Mind and Matter in Descartes and Locke 9.2 Leibniz's Analysis of Mind and Matter 9.2.1 The Primary-Secondary Quality Distinction 9.2.2 Physical Considerations 9.2.3 Metaphysical Considerations 9.2.3.1 Substance as Unity 9.2.3.2 Substance as Activity 9.2.3.3 Substance as Subject 9.2.4 Psychological Considerations 10 Levels of Discourse 11 Leibniz's Epistemological Realism 11.1 Requirements of the System 11.2 The Contrary Proposition 11.
    [Show full text]