On the Methodology of Informal Rigour: Set Theory, Semantics

Total Page:16

File Type:pdf, Size:1020Kb

On the Methodology of Informal Rigour: Set Theory, Semantics On the methodology of informal rigour: set theory, semantics, and intuitionism∗ Walter Dean† & Hidenori Kurokawa‡ In his paper Kreisel adumbrates a crucial insight into the nature of mathematics and foundations of mathematics by focusing on the notion of “informal rigor.” It seems to me that philosophy of mathematics should pay much more attention to this notion than has been the case. (Isaacson, 2011, p. 13) 1 Introduction Georg Kreisel is best known amongst philosophers for his defense of the model theoretic analysis of first-order logical validity and his argument that the Continuum Hypothesis (CH) possesses a definite truth value. The former – which is often referred to as Kreisel’s squeezing argument – continues to play a role in debates about logical consequence and validity after its popularization by authors such as Field (1989, 2008), Boolos (1985), and Etchemendy (1990). The latter has been influential in subsequent debates in philosophy of mathematics regarding the role of second-order logic in securing the determinacy of set theoretic truth – e.g. Weston (1976), Shapiro (1985, 1991), Potter (2004), Isaacson (2011). The locus classicus for both of Kreisel’s arguments is his paper ‘Informal rigour and complete- ness proofs’ (1967b). It is fair to say that this paper is well-known. But it is also not a substantial exaggeration to say that the sections of (1967b) which contain Kreisel’s validity and CH arguments are the only part of his otherwise substantial output which has been widely read or appreciated by philosophers. This is to some extent understandable. For not only is Kreisel’s style sometimes obscure, even the papers which he directed at philosophical audiences are typically informed by mathematical and historical considerations which are not readily appreciated without an under- standing of the milieu in which they were composed. This is particularly true of (1967b). For although this paper is one of several places in which Kreisel juxtaposed his validity and CH arguments, it also provides the most complete exposition of a technique which he referred to as informal rigour. Kreisel presented these arguments as examples arXiv:2104.14887v1 [math.LO] 30 Apr 2021 of the technique. But it is not entirely straightforward to discern what they have in common as applications of a more general method. Thus although ‘informal rigour’ is often taken to be a hallmark of Kreisel’s work, there is little consensus on how this method should be characterized or the sorts of questions it is intended to address. The primary goals of this paper will thus be to distill from Kreisel’s various expositions a general schema for what we will refer to as an informally rigorous argument and to illustrate in detail how ∗Forthcoming in Intuitionism, Computation, and Proof: Selected themes from the research of G. Kreisel, M. Antonutti Marfori and M. Petrolo (editors), Springer. Please do not cite without permission. †University of Warwick, [email protected]. ‡Kanazawa University, [email protected]. 1 Kreisel’s examples conform to it. In this context we will additionally demarcate what has come to be called a squeezing argument – as paradigmatically illustrated by Kreisel’s validity argument – and illustrate how such arguments can be understood as a subspecies of Kreisel’s more general method. We will present our proposed schematization of informal rigour in §3. In§4 we will then present detailed reconstructions of the three primary examples which Kreisel considered in (1967b). In addition to his validity and CH arguments, this includes his analysis of the notion of a creating subject which figures in Brouwer’s development of intuitionistic analysis. Little subsequent attention has been paid to this case as an example of informal rigour. But it is of particular interest not only because Kreisel’s exposition contains a novel mathematical result (whose proof we will reconstruct in §4.2.3) but also because it illustrates the central role which Kreisel assigned to reflection on what he refers to as ‘new primitive notions’ in the operation of informal rigour. In Appendix A we will summarize more briefly Kreisel’s proposals about the applicability of informal rigour to the following additional concepts: set, nonstandard model, finitist proof, predicative definability, and intuitionistic validity. These examples are illustrative of the many trees in the forest we are about to enter. But before considering them individually, it will be useful to consider in §2 the context in which Kreisel introduced informal rigour, inclusive of his motives for promoting this methodology and his strategy for presenting it to his intended audiences. In addition to the complexity of Kreisel’s relationships with his interlocutors, many aspects of his exposition were also informed by specific mathematical developments to which he either directly contributed or was otherwise an interested party. Several of these relate to the other titular concern of (1967b) – i.e. the significance of complete- ness proofs in mathematical logic. About such proofs Kreisel begins by remarking [Q]uite generally, problems of completeness (of rules) involve informal rigour, at least when one is trying to decide completeness with respect to an intuitive notion of consequence. (1967b, p. 139) By the time he composed (1967b) Kreisel indeed had extensive experience not only with the tech- nical details of completeness proofs for a variety of logical systems but also with the prior task of distilling notions of consequence and validity from the foundational work of theorists such as Zermelo, Poincaré, Hilbert, Brouwer, Heyting, and Gödel. It is thus useful to flag the following por- tions of Kreisel’s mathematical work as antecedents to his introduction of the expression ‘informal rigour’: i) his refinement of Hilbert and Bernays’s (1939) arithmetization of Gödel’s (1929) original completeness proof for classical first order logic (1950; 1953); ii) his metamathematical analysis of the completeness of intuitionistic first-order logic (1961; 1958a; 1958f; 1970a); iii) his investigation on the role of reflection principles in the characterization of finitary mathematics (1958a; 1970b; 1968); iv) his analysis of predicativity in terms of the hyperarithmetical sets (1959a; 1960a; 1960b; 1962a); and v) his anticipation of the method of forcing in set theory (1958g; 1961).1 Such developments may seem far afield to contemporary readers of ‘Informal rigour and com- pleteness proofs’. But perhaps the most interesting aspect of this paper is how Kreisel understood results in mathematical logic to be related to debates in mid-20th century analytic philosophy – e.g. the possibility of conceptual analysis, the viability of logical positivism, and the tenability of realism, idealism, and formalism in the foundations of mathematics. But although in some instances Kreisel’s proposals have gone on to have significant downstream effects, it is still difficult to concisely 1The following sources contain discussion of these developments: i) (Smorynski, 1984), (Dean, 2020); ii) (Sundholm, 1983), (McCarty, 2008), (Dean and Kurokawa, 2016); iii) (Feferman, 1995), (Dean, 2015); iv) (Feferman, 2005), (Dean and Walsh, 2017, §2.3); v) (Kreisel, 1980, §III) as well as the other sources cited in note 69 below. 2 summarize his philosophical contributions. In fact Kreisel’s influence has mostly been felt at one level of remove via his associates and interpreters who have often described his views incompletely or out of mathematical and historical context (often out of expository necessity). In §5 we will discuss a source which helps to illustrate the relationship of Kreisel’s views with some of his contemporaries – i.e. his exchange with Yehoshua Bar-Hillel recorded in the comments and replies published along with (1967b). Much of this concerns the comparison of Kreisel’s concep- tion of informal rigour relative to the method which Carnap called explication. Kreisel was clearly dissatisfied that this discussion did not engage more deeply with the mathematical details of his examples. But it is still a useful waypoint in appreciating the enduring significance of informal rigour in relation to contemporary discussions of philosophical methodology. 2 Context We will see below that Kreisel took the validity argument to be the most paradigmatic of his case studies in informal rigour. But it is also clear that he understood the significance of this argument in relation to the case for the determinacy of CH which he which to impress on his audiences in the mid-1960s. This is attested by the fact that he juxtaposed the two arguments in at least the following four sources:2 - Mathematical logic. In T.L. Saaty, editor, Lectures on Modern Mathematics, Vol. III. Wiley, 1965. [(1965) / early 1964 / §1.8, pp. 111-112, pp. 114-118] - Mathematical logic: What has it done for the philosophy of mathematics. In R. Schoenman, editor, Bertrand Russell, Philosopher of the Century. Allen and Unwin, 1967. [(1967a) / December 1964 /§3, pp. 253-262] - Informal Rigour and Completeness Proofs. In I. Lakatos, editor, Problems in the philosophy of mathematics: Proceedings of the International Colloquium in the Philosophy of Science, London, 1965. North-Holland, 1967. [(1967b) / July 1966 / §1-2, pp. 147-157] - Elements of Mathematical Logic. Model theory (with Jean-Louis Krivine). Studies in Logic and the Founda- tions of Mathematics. North-Holland. [(1967c) / Krivine, chapters 0-5: 1960-1961; Kreisel chapters 6-7 and appendices: 1966 / Appendix A, §4, pp. 189-194] The task of reconstructing Kreisel’s methodology is made non-trivial by the factors which shaped his presentations in these sources. It will hence be useful to begin by recording some details about the circumstances of their publication. Kreisel was 42 years old in 1965 and had already published more than 30 papers in mathematical logic spanning a number of areas.3 This work forms much of the background to (1965) which corresponds to an entry on mathematical logic which Kreisel was invited to write for Thomas Saaty’s three volume series Lectures in Modern Mathematics.
Recommended publications
  • Set Theory, by Thomas Jech, Academic Press, New York, 1978, Xii + 621 Pp., '$53.00
    BOOK REVIEWS 775 BULLETIN (New Series) OF THE AMERICAN MATHEMATICAL SOCIETY Volume 3, Number 1, July 1980 © 1980 American Mathematical Society 0002-9904/80/0000-0 319/$01.75 Set theory, by Thomas Jech, Academic Press, New York, 1978, xii + 621 pp., '$53.00. "General set theory is pretty trivial stuff really" (Halmos; see [H, p. vi]). At least, with the hindsight afforded by Cantor, Zermelo, and others, it is pretty trivial to do the following. First, write down a list of axioms about sets and membership, enunciating some "obviously true" set-theoretic principles; the most popular Hst today is called ZFC (the Zermelo-Fraenkel axioms with the axiom of Choice). Next, explain how, from ZFC, one may derive all of conventional mathematics, including the general theory of transfinite cardi­ nals and ordinals. This "trivial" part of set theory is well covered in standard texts, such as [E] or [H]. Jech's book is an introduction to the "nontrivial" part. Now, nontrivial set theory may be roughly divided into two general areas. The first area, classical set theory, is a direct outgrowth of Cantor's work. Cantor set down the basic properties of cardinal numbers. In particular, he showed that if K is a cardinal number, then 2", or exp(/c), is a cardinal strictly larger than K (if A is a set of size K, 2* is the cardinality of the family of all subsets of A). Now starting with a cardinal K, we may form larger cardinals exp(ic), exp2(ic) = exp(exp(fc)), exp3(ic) = exp(exp2(ic)), and in fact this may be continued through the transfinite to form expa(»c) for every ordinal number a.
    [Show full text]
  • The Logic of Brouwer and Heyting
    THE LOGIC OF BROUWER AND HEYTING Joan Rand Moschovakis Intuitionistic logic consists of the principles of reasoning which were used in- formally by L. E. J. Brouwer, formalized by A. Heyting (also partially by V. Glivenko), interpreted by A. Kolmogorov, and studied by G. Gentzen and K. G¨odel during the first third of the twentieth century. Formally, intuitionistic first- order predicate logic is a proper subsystem of classical logic, obtained by replacing the law of excluded middle A ∨¬A by ¬A ⊃ (A ⊃ B); it has infinitely many dis- tinct consistent axiomatic extensions, each necessarily contained in classical logic (which is axiomatically complete). However, intuitionistic second-order logic is inconsistent with classical second-order logic. In terms of expressibility, the intu- itionistic logic and language are richer than the classical; as G¨odel and Gentzen showed, classical first-order arithmetic can be faithfully translated into the nega- tive fragment of intuitionistic arithmetic, establishing proof-theoretical equivalence and clarifying the distinction between the classical and constructive consequences of mathematical axioms. The logic of Brouwer and Heyting is effective. The conclusion of an intuitionistic derivation holds with the same degree of constructivity as the premises. Any proof of a disjunction of two statements can be effectively transformed into a proof of one of the disjuncts, while any proof of an existential statement contains an effec- tive prescription for finding a witness. The negation of a statement is interpreted as asserting that the statement is not merely false but absurd, i.e., leads to a contradiction. Brouwer objected to the general law of excluded middle as claim- ing a priori that every mathematical problem has a solution, and to the general law ¬¬A ⊃ A of double negation as asserting that every consistent mathematical statement holds.
    [Show full text]
  • Automated ZFC Theorem Proving with E
    Automated ZFC Theorem Proving with E John Hester Department of Mathematics, University of Florida, Gainesville, Florida, USA https://people.clas.ufl.edu/hesterj/ [email protected] Abstract. I introduce an approach for automated reasoning in first or- der set theories that are not finitely axiomatizable, such as ZFC, and describe its implementation alongside the automated theorem proving software E. I then compare the results of proof search in the class based set theory NBG with those of ZFC. Keywords: ZFC · ATP · E. 1 Introduction Historically, automated reasoning in first order set theories has faced a fun- damental problem in the axiomatizations. Some theories such as ZFC widely considered as candidates for the foundations of mathematics are not finitely axiomatizable. Axiom schemas such as the schema of comprehension and the schema of replacement in ZFC are infinite, and so cannot be entirely incorpo- rated in to the prover at the beginning of a proof search. Indeed, there is no finite axiomatization of ZFC [1]. As a result, when reasoning about sufficiently strong set theories that could no longer be considered naive, some have taken the alternative approach of using extensions of ZFC that admit objects such as proper classes as first order objects, but this is not without its problems for the individual interested in proving set-theoretic propositions. As an alternative, I have programmed an extension to the automated the- orem prover E [2] that generates instances of parameter free replacement and comprehension from well formuled formulas of ZFC that are passed to it, when eligible, and adds them to the proof state while the prover is running.
    [Show full text]
  • On Families of Mutually Exclusive Sets
    ANNALS OF MATHEMATICS Vol. 44, No . 2, April, 1943 ON FAMILIES OF MUTUALLY EXCLUSIVE SETS BY P . ERDÖS AND A. TARSKI (Received August 11, 1942) In this paper we shall be concerned with a certain particular problem from the general theory of sets, namely with the problem of the existence of families of mutually exclusive sets with a maximal power . It will turn out-in a rather unexpected way that the solution of these problems essentially involves the notion of the so-called "inaccessible numbers ." In this connection we shall make some general remarks regarding inaccessible numbers in the last section of our paper . §1. FORMULATION OF THE PROBLEM . TERMINOLOGY' The problem in which we are interested can be stated as follows : Is it true that every field F of sets contains a family of mutually exclusive sets with a maximal power, i .e . a family O whose cardinal number is not smaller than the cardinal number of any other family of mutually exclusive sets contained in F . By a field of sets we understand here as usual a family F of sets which to- gether with every two sets X and Y contains also their union X U Y and their difference X - Y (i.e. the set of those elements of X which do not belong to Y) among its elements . A family O is called a family of mutually exclusive sets if no set X of X of O is empty and if any two different sets of O have an empty inter- section. A similar problem can be formulated for other families e .g .
    [Show full text]
  • Basic Concepts of Set Theory, Functions and Relations 1. Basic
    Ling 310, adapted from UMass Ling 409, Partee lecture notes March 1, 2006 p. 1 Basic Concepts of Set Theory, Functions and Relations 1. Basic Concepts of Set Theory........................................................................................................................1 1.1. Sets and elements ...................................................................................................................................1 1.2. Specification of sets ...............................................................................................................................2 1.3. Identity and cardinality ..........................................................................................................................3 1.4. Subsets ...................................................................................................................................................4 1.5. Power sets .............................................................................................................................................4 1.6. Operations on sets: union, intersection...................................................................................................4 1.7 More operations on sets: difference, complement...................................................................................5 1.8. Set-theoretic equalities ...........................................................................................................................5 Chapter 2. Relations and Functions ..................................................................................................................6
    [Show full text]
  • Completeness
    Completeness The strange case of Dr. Skolem and Mr. G¨odel∗ Gabriele Lolli The completeness theorem has a history; such is the destiny of the impor- tant theorems, those for which for a long time one does not know (whether there is anything to prove and) what to prove. In its history, one can di- stinguish at least two main paths; the first one covers the slow and difficult comprehension of the problem in (what historians consider) the traditional development of mathematical logic canon, up to G¨odel'sproof in 1930; the second path follows the L¨owenheim-Skolem theorem. Although at certain points the two paths crossed each other, they started and continued with their own aims and problems. A classical topos of the history of mathema- tical logic concerns the how and the why L¨owenheim, Skolem and Herbrand did not discover the completeness theorem, though they proved it, or whe- ther they really proved, or perhaps they actually discovered, completeness. In following these two paths, we will not always respect strict chronology, keeping the two stories quite separate, until the crossing becomes decisive. In modern pre-mathematical logic, the notion of completeness does not appear. There are some interesting speculations in Kant which, by some stretching, could be realized as bearing some relation with the problem; Kant's remarks, however, are probably more related with incompleteness, in connection with his thoughts on the derivability of transcendental ideas (or concepts of reason) from categories (the intellect's concepts) through a pas- sage to the limit; thus, for instance, the causa prima, or the idea of causality, is the limit of implication, or God is the limit of disjunction, viz., the catego- ry of \comunance".
    [Show full text]
  • Elements of Set Theory
    Elements of set theory April 1, 2014 ii Contents 1 Zermelo{Fraenkel axiomatization 1 1.1 Historical context . 1 1.2 The language of the theory . 3 1.3 The most basic axioms . 4 1.4 Axiom of Infinity . 4 1.5 Axiom schema of Comprehension . 5 1.6 Functions . 6 1.7 Axiom of Choice . 7 1.8 Axiom schema of Replacement . 9 1.9 Axiom of Regularity . 9 2 Basic notions 11 2.1 Transitive sets . 11 2.2 Von Neumann's natural numbers . 11 2.3 Finite and infinite sets . 15 2.4 Cardinality . 17 2.5 Countable and uncountable sets . 19 3 Ordinals 21 3.1 Basic definitions . 21 3.2 Transfinite induction and recursion . 25 3.3 Applications with choice . 26 3.4 Applications without choice . 29 3.5 Cardinal numbers . 31 4 Descriptive set theory 35 4.1 Rational and real numbers . 35 4.2 Topological spaces . 37 4.3 Polish spaces . 39 4.4 Borel sets . 43 4.5 Analytic sets . 46 4.6 Lebesgue's mistake . 48 iii iv CONTENTS 5 Formal logic 51 5.1 Propositional logic . 51 5.1.1 Propositional logic: syntax . 51 5.1.2 Propositional logic: semantics . 52 5.1.3 Propositional logic: completeness . 53 5.2 First order logic . 56 5.2.1 First order logic: syntax . 56 5.2.2 First order logic: semantics . 59 5.2.3 Completeness theorem . 60 6 Model theory 67 6.1 Basic notions . 67 6.2 Ultraproducts and nonstandard analysis . 68 6.3 Quantifier elimination and the real closed fields .
    [Show full text]
  • The Development of Mathematical Logic from Russell to Tarski: 1900–1935
    The Development of Mathematical Logic from Russell to Tarski: 1900–1935 Paolo Mancosu Richard Zach Calixto Badesa The Development of Mathematical Logic from Russell to Tarski: 1900–1935 Paolo Mancosu (University of California, Berkeley) Richard Zach (University of Calgary) Calixto Badesa (Universitat de Barcelona) Final Draft—May 2004 To appear in: Leila Haaparanta, ed., The Development of Modern Logic. New York and Oxford: Oxford University Press, 2004 Contents Contents i Introduction 1 1 Itinerary I: Metatheoretical Properties of Axiomatic Systems 3 1.1 Introduction . 3 1.2 Peano’s school on the logical structure of theories . 4 1.3 Hilbert on axiomatization . 8 1.4 Completeness and categoricity in the work of Veblen and Huntington . 10 1.5 Truth in a structure . 12 2 Itinerary II: Bertrand Russell’s Mathematical Logic 15 2.1 From the Paris congress to the Principles of Mathematics 1900–1903 . 15 2.2 Russell and Poincar´e on predicativity . 19 2.3 On Denoting . 21 2.4 Russell’s ramified type theory . 22 2.5 The logic of Principia ......................... 25 2.6 Further developments . 26 3 Itinerary III: Zermelo’s Axiomatization of Set Theory and Re- lated Foundational Issues 29 3.1 The debate on the axiom of choice . 29 3.2 Zermelo’s axiomatization of set theory . 32 3.3 The discussion on the notion of “definit” . 35 3.4 Metatheoretical studies of Zermelo’s axiomatization . 38 4 Itinerary IV: The Theory of Relatives and Lowenheim’s¨ Theorem 41 4.1 Theory of relatives and model theory . 41 4.2 The logic of relatives .
    [Show full text]
  • Definitions and Nondefinability in Geometry 475 2
    Definitions and Nondefinability in Geometry1 James T. Smith Abstract. Around 1900 some noted mathematicians published works developing geometry from its very beginning. They wanted to supplant approaches, based on Euclid’s, which han- dled some basic concepts awkwardly and imprecisely. They would introduce precision re- quired for generalization and application to new, delicate problems in higher mathematics. Their work was controversial: they departed from tradition, criticized standards of rigor, and addressed fundamental questions in philosophy. This paper follows the problem, Which geo- metric concepts are most elementary? It describes a false start, some successful solutions, and an argument that one of those is optimal. It’s about axioms, definitions, and definability, and emphasizes contributions of Mario Pieri (1860–1913) and Alfred Tarski (1901–1983). By fol- lowing this thread of ideas and personalities to the present, the author hopes to kindle interest in a fascinating research area and an exciting era in the history of mathematics. 1. INTRODUCTION. Around 1900 several noted mathematicians published major works on a subject familiar to us from school: developing geometry from the very beginning. They wanted to supplant the established approaches, which were based on Euclid’s, but which handled awkwardly and imprecisely some concepts that Euclid did not treat fully. They would present geometry with the precision required for general- ization and applications to new, delicate problems in higher mathematics—precision beyond the norm for most elementary classes. Work in this area was controversial: these mathematicians departed from tradition, criticized previous standards of rigor, and addressed fundamental questions in logic and philosophy of mathematics.2 After establishing background, this paper tells a story about research into the ques- tion, Which geometric concepts are most elementary? It describes a false start, some successful solutions, and a demonstration that one of those is in a sense optimal.
    [Show full text]
  • Equivalents to the Axiom of Choice and Their Uses A
    EQUIVALENTS TO THE AXIOM OF CHOICE AND THEIR USES A Thesis Presented to The Faculty of the Department of Mathematics California State University, Los Angeles In Partial Fulfillment of the Requirements for the Degree Master of Science in Mathematics By James Szufu Yang c 2015 James Szufu Yang ALL RIGHTS RESERVED ii The thesis of James Szufu Yang is approved. Mike Krebs, Ph.D. Kristin Webster, Ph.D. Michael Hoffman, Ph.D., Committee Chair Grant Fraser, Ph.D., Department Chair California State University, Los Angeles June 2015 iii ABSTRACT Equivalents to the Axiom of Choice and Their Uses By James Szufu Yang In set theory, the Axiom of Choice (AC) was formulated in 1904 by Ernst Zermelo. It is an addition to the older Zermelo-Fraenkel (ZF) set theory. We call it Zermelo-Fraenkel set theory with the Axiom of Choice and abbreviate it as ZFC. This paper starts with an introduction to the foundations of ZFC set the- ory, which includes the Zermelo-Fraenkel axioms, partially ordered sets (posets), the Cartesian product, the Axiom of Choice, and their related proofs. It then intro- duces several equivalent forms of the Axiom of Choice and proves that they are all equivalent. In the end, equivalents to the Axiom of Choice are used to prove a few fundamental theorems in set theory, linear analysis, and abstract algebra. This paper is concluded by a brief review of the work in it, followed by a few points of interest for further study in mathematics and/or set theory. iv ACKNOWLEDGMENTS Between the two department requirements to complete a master's degree in mathematics − the comprehensive exams and a thesis, I really wanted to experience doing a research and writing a serious academic paper.
    [Show full text]
  • Taboo Versus Axiom
    TABOO VERSUS AXIOM KATUZI ONO Some important formal systems are really developable from a finite number of axioms in the lower classical predicate logic LK or in the intuitionistic predicate logic LJ. Any system of this kind can be developed in LK (or in LJ) from the single conjunction of all the axioms of the system. I have been intending to develop usual formal systems starting from TABOOS and standing on the primitive logic LO at first, since the logic too could be brought up to the usual logics by means of TABOOS in LOυ. In developing any formal system from TABOOS, we are forced to assume unwillingly that all the TABOOS are mutually equivalent, as far as we adopt more than one TABOOS for the system. If we could develop formal systems from single- TABOO TABOO-systems, we could get rid of this unwilling assumption. It would be well expected that any formal theory developable from a finite number of axioms in LK or in LJ would be developable from a single TABOO.2) In the present paper, I will prove that this is really the case. Before stating the theorem, let us define the δ-TRANSFORM Spy] of any sentence ® with respect to an h-ary relation £y (λ>0). SΓ&3 is introduced by a structural recursive definition as follows: @C8Qs (r)((©->g(r))->#(r)) for any elementary sentence ©, Received January 20, 1966. *> As for this plan, see Ono [1]. LO is called PRIMITIVE SYSTEM OF POSITIVE LOGIC in Ono [1]. The terminology PRIMITIVE LOGIC together with its reference notation LO has been introduced in Ono [2], 2) In my work [1], I had to assume this to bring up logics by means of TABOO systems.
    [Show full text]
  • The Axiom of Determinancy Implies Dependent Choices in L(R) Author(S): Alexander S
    The Axiom of Determinancy Implies Dependent Choices in L(R) Author(s): Alexander S. Kechris Source: The Journal of Symbolic Logic, Vol. 49, No. 1 (Mar., 1984), pp. 161-173 Published by: Association for Symbolic Logic Stable URL: http://www.jstor.org/stable/2274099 . Accessed: 20/05/2013 16:25 Your use of the JSTOR archive indicates your acceptance of the Terms & Conditions of Use, available at . http://www.jstor.org/page/info/about/policies/terms.jsp . JSTOR is a not-for-profit service that helps scholars, researchers, and students discover, use, and build upon a wide range of content in a trusted digital archive. We use information technology and tools to increase productivity and facilitate new forms of scholarship. For more information about JSTOR, please contact [email protected]. Association for Symbolic Logic is collaborating with JSTOR to digitize, preserve and extend access to The Journal of Symbolic Logic. http://www.jstor.org This content downloaded from 131.215.71.79 on Mon, 20 May 2013 16:25:52 PM All use subject to JSTOR Terms and Conditions THE JOURNALOF SYMBOLICLOGIC Volume 49, Number 1, March 1984 THE AXIOM OF DETERMINACY IMPLIES DEPENDENT CHOICES IN L(R) ALEXANDER S. KECHRIS1 Abstract. We prove the following Main Theorem: ZF + AD + V L(R) =>DC. As a corollary we have that Con(ZF + AD) Con(ZF + AD + DC). Combined with the result - of Woodin that Con(ZF + AD) - Con(ZF + AD + AC') it follows that DC (as well as AC') is independent relative to ZF + AD. It is finally shown (jointly with H.
    [Show full text]